Fordham International Law Journal
Volume 40, Issue 2 Article 3
The Legitimacy of Informal Constitutional
Amendment and the “Reinterpretation” of
Japan’s War Powers
Craig Martin
Copyright
c
by the authors. Fordham International Law Journal is produced by The Berkeley
Electronic Press (bepress). http://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/ilj
The Legitimacy of Informal Constitutional
Amendment and the “Reinterpretation” of
Japan’s War Powers
Craig Martin
Abstract
The government of Japan has purported to reinterpret the famous war-renouncing provision of
the Constitution in a controversial process that deliberately circumvented the formal amendment
procedure. This article argues that these developments should be of great interest to constitutional
law scholars in America because they bring into sharp focus issues that remain underdeveloped
and unresolved in the debate over informal amendment. Theories on informal amendment suggest
that there are some constitutional changes that exceed the reasonable range of normal interpretive
development, but which are not implemented through formal amendment procedures. The exis-
tence, scope, and legitimacy of such informal amendments remains hotly contested.
This article focuses on the key issue of legitimacy. It uses the Japanese reinterpretation as the con-
text in which to explore the relationship among three suggested factors affecting the legitimacy of
informal amendment, namely: the public ratification of the change; the intent of the agents of the
change; and the passage of time. It also suggests a new way of conceptualizing the relationship
among authority, legitimacy, and time in thinking about informal amendments, in that the level of
constitutional authority and degree of legitimacy that may be enjoyed by contested changes will
begin to diverge with the passage of time.
The article argues that deliberate attempts to effect significant constitutional change in a manner
calculated to circumvent the formal amendment process—such as the Abe government’s reinter-
pretation effort in Japan—are prima facie unauthorized and illegitimate at the time they occur.
Moreover, only the most explicit and deliberate expressions of popular sovereignty can serve to
legitimate such changes. But while such deliberate informal change will always remain unau-
thorized, it may be legitimated with the passage of time. I argue that this legitimation may, and
should, take longer than for less contested forms of change.
KEYWORDS: Informal Amendment, Japanese Constitutional Reinterpretation
427
ARTICLE
THE LEGITIMACY OF INFORMAL
CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT
AND THE “REINTERPRETATION” OF
JAPAN’S WAR POWERS
Craig Martin
*
ABSTRACT
The government of Japan has purported to reinterpret the
famous war-renouncing provision of the Constitution in a
controversial process that deliberately circumvented the formal
amendment procedure. This article argues that these developments
should be of great interest to constitutional law scholars in America
because they bring into sharp focus issues that remain
underdeveloped and unresolved in the debate over informal
amendment. Theories on informal amendment suggest that there are
some constitutional changes that exceed the reasonable range of
* Professor of Law, Washburn School of Law, B.A. (R.M.C.), J.D. (Univ. of Toronto),
LL.M. (Osaka Univ.), S.J.D. (Univ. of Pennsylvania). This project was presented, at various
stages of its development, at conferences convened by the Law and Society Association in
Seattle, the Asian Law and Society Association in Tokyo, the American Association of Law
Schools in New York City, the Asser Institute in The Hague, Ritsumeikan University in
Kyoto, and the University of New South Wales, Sydney—I am grateful to the organizers of the
conferences and the specific panels for the opportunities to present, and I am thankful for the
many helpful suggestions and comments from many other people that I received both at the
conferences and on various drafts and in discussions about the argument at various stages
along the way. In particular I would like to thank Bruce Ackerman, Koji Aikyo, Richard
Albert, Juliano Benvindo, Carlos Bernal, Lois Chiang, Benson Cowan, Mahesh Daas, Rosalind
Dixon, Eric Feldman, Tom Ginsburg, Yasuo Hasebe, John Haley, John Head, Virginia Harper
Ho, Ali Khan, Akihiko Kimijima, Junko Kotani, Rob Leflar, Mark Levin, Sanford Levinson,
Setsuo Miyazawa, Hitoshi Nasu, Luke Nottage, Susannah Pollvogt, Larry Repeta, Bill Rich,
David Rubenstein, Eiji Sasada, Takeshi Shirōzu, Freddy Sourgens, Bryce Wakefield, and
Hajime Yamamoto. I am also grateful for research assistance from Zacharia Zallo. I of course
remain responsible for any errors. (On a point of transliteration, Romanized Japanese names
throughout the article are rendered surname last, rather than the Japanese custom of surnames
first).
428 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
normal interpretive development, but which are not implemented
through formal amendment procedures. The existence, scope, and
legitimacy of such informal amendments remains hotly contested.
This article focuses on the key issue of legitimacy. It uses the
Japanese reinterpretation as the context in which to explore the
relationship among three suggested factors affecting the legitimacy of
informal amendment, namely: the public ratification of the change;
the intent of the agents of the change; and the passage of time. It also
suggests a new way of conceptualizing the relationship among
authority, legitimacy, and time in thinking about informal
amendments, in that the level of constitutional authority and degree of
legitimacy that may be enjoyed by contested changes will begin to
diverge with the passage of time.
The article argues that deliberate attempts to effect significant
constitutional change in a manner calculated to circumvent the
formal amendment process—such as the Abe government’s
reinterpretation effort in Japan—are prima facie unauthorized and
illegitimate at the time they occur. Moreover, only the most explicit
and deliberate expressions of popular sovereignty can serve to
legitimate such changes. But while such deliberate informal change
will always remain unauthorized, it may be legitimated with the
passage of time. I argue that this legitimation may, and should, take
longer than for less contested forms of change.
ABSTRACT ....................................................................................... 427
INTRODUCTION ............................................................................. 429
I. INFORMAL AMENDMENT ........................................................ 437
A. Preliminaries - Assumptions and Premises ........................ 437
B. Theories of Informal Amendment and the Issue of
Legitimacy ......................................................................... 443
C. Critics and the Contours of Legitimacy .............................. 458
II. THE JAPANESE CONSTITUTIONAL
REINTERPRETATION .......................................................... 462
A. The Constitution of Japan and Article 9 ............................. 462
B. The Government Interpretation and Operation of
Article 9 ............................................................................. 467
C. The Process of Reinterpretation .......................................... 475
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 429
III. THE REINTERPRETATION, INFORMAL AMENDMENT,
AND LEGITIMACY............................................................... 489
A. The Reinterpretation as Normal Interpretive Move ............ 490
B. The Reinterpretation as Informal Amendment ................... 502
C. Clarifying the Contours of Legitimacy ............................... 506
CONCLUSION .................................................................................. 520
INTRODUCTION
There is a vibrant debate in American constitutional law
scholarship regarding the existence, nature, and legitimacy of so-
called informal amendments.
1
The definition of the concept of
“informal amendment” is itself an important subject in the debate, but
we may start with the idea that the term refers to a form of significant
change to the understanding and operation of a constitutional
provision that is neither a formal amendment nor a normal
1. See, e.g., BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE, VOL. 2: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998);
Sanford Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended? (A) >
26; (B) 26; (C) 27; (D) > 27: Accounting for Constitutional Change [hereinafter Levinson,
How Many Times Has the United States Constitutions Been Amended?], in R
ESPONDING TO
IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT 13 (Sanford
Levinson ed., 1995) [hereinafter R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION]; Akhil Reed Amar, Popular
Sovereignty and Constitutional Amendment, in R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION 89; Stephen
Griffin, Constitutionalism in the United States: From Theory to Politics, in R
ESPONDING TO
IMPERFECTION 37; Donald S. Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional Amendment, in
R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION 237 [hereinafter Lutz, Toward a Theory - Responding to
Imperfection]; David R. Dow, The Plain Meaning of Article V, in R
ESPONDING TO
IMPERFECTION 117; Stephen Holmes & Cass R. Sunstein, The Politics of Constitutional
Revision in Eastern Europe, in R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION 275; Jack M. Balkin &
Sanford Levinson, Understanding the Constitutional Revolution, 87 V
A. L. REV. 1045 (2001);
Z
ACHARY ELKINS, TOM GINSBURG & JAMES MELTON, THE ENDURANCE OF NATIONAL
CONSTITUTIONS (2009); Aziz Z. Huq, The Function of Article V, 162 U. PA. L. REV. 1165
(2014); Ernest A. Young, The Constitution Outside the Constitution, 117 Y
ALE L. J. 408
(2007); Brannon P. Denning, Means to Amend: Theories of Constitutional Change, 65 T
ENN.
L. REV. 155 (1997); Brannon P. Denning & John R. Vile, The Relevance of Constitutional
Amendments: A Response to Strauss, 77 Tul. L. Rev. 247 (2002); Rosalind Dixon, Updating
Constitutional Rules, 8 S
UP. CT. REV. 319 (2009); David A. Strauss, The Irrelevance of
Constitutional Amendments, 114 H
ARV. L. REV. 1457 (2001); WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE JR. &
JOHN FEREJOHN, A REPUBLIC OF STATUTES: THE NEW AMERICAN CONSTITUTION (2010);
Randy E. Barnett, We the People: Each and Every One, 123 Y
ALE L. J. 2576 (2014); Richard
Albert, Constitutional Disuse or Desuetude: The Case of Article V, 94 B.U.
L. REV. 1029,
1062 (2014); Heather K. Gerken, The Hydraulics of Constitutional Reform: A Skeptical
Response to Our Democratic Constitution, 55 D
RAKE L. REV. 925 (2007).
430 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
interpretive development. Formal amendments are, of course, those
changes to the constitution initiated and approved in accordance with
the established constitutional amendment procedure. Interpretive
developments are the incremental changes in meaning that are
typically the result of judicial decision-making. Informal amendment
refers to changes in meaning or understanding that are arguably so
dramatic and relatively sudden that they are impossible to reconcile
with the text, purpose, and historical operation of the provision in
question (according to most accepted theories of constitutional
interpretation), and therefore will not be accepted by most jurists as a
“normal” interpretive move.
2
Thus, the argument goes, such a change
is better characterized as being a form of amendment to the
constitutional system rather than an interpretive development, even
though it is not a formal amendment and it creates no change to the
underlying constitutional text.
3
This standard formulation of informal amendment obviously
implicates much broader debates in constitutional law. These include,
particularly, the competing theories of valid constitutional
interpretation and related arguments over the question of whether,
how, or to what extent the constitution can be said to legitimately
change through interpretation by the judiciary or by other branches of
government.
4
There are thus differences among the theories of
informal amendment which mirror differences among theories of
constitutional interpretation. But the theories on informal amendment
largely arise in response to the felt need to explain, and for some
theorists to legitimate, the relatively dramatic changes to the
American constitutional system that were not promulgated by way of
a formal amendment in accordance with the Article V process, and
which cannot be reconciled with most scholars’ notions of legitimate
interpretive change.
5
While the different theories of informal
amendment share this common purpose, supporters of each differ in
their explanations for the modalities and process of change. They
differ both descriptively in terms of what changes qualify as an
2. Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?,
supra note 1, at 14-15.
3. Id.
4. See infra Section I.A.
5. Sanford Levinson, Imperfection and Amendability, in R
ESPONDING TO
IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 7.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 431
informal amendment and how they are said to come about, and
normatively in terms of whether or how such change might be
considered beneficial or legitimate.
6
And of course, there are critics
who reject the very notion of informal amendments on both
descriptive and normative grounds.
7
Even if we take these theories of informal amendment seriously
and on their own terms, however, we are nonetheless left with
profoundly difficult questions, some of which remain somewhat
under-theorized and unresolved. These questions are both descriptive
and normative in form, and while some of them may be impossible to
resolve without first resolving the broader debates about
interpretation,
8
some of them may be less intractable. In particular,
one question that seems insufficiently explored is whether such
informal amendments are legitimate, and more importantly, how we
are to determine if any given change is indeed legitimate.
This article explores the question of the legitimacy of informal
amendments. It does so by examining the recent efforts to
“reinterpret” the famous war-renouncing provision of the Japanese
constitution. This attempt to significantly change the meaning of the
provision was undertaken by the Japanese cabinet in a very deliberate
and calculated manner to circumvent the formal amendment
procedure, and even to minimize legislative involvement and public
participation in the process. The legitimacy of the attempted
reinterpretation is the subject of considerable controversy within
Japan, though the change may be in the process of becoming a fait
accompli. In exploring this reinterpretation effort through the lens of
informal amendment theory, the article identifies and analyzes three
features of informal amendment as important factors for determining
the legitimacy of any given change. In doing so, the article re-
conceptualizes the contours of informal constitutional change,
exploring not only the relationship among these three factors of
6. See infra Section I.B.
7. See infra Section I.B.
8. The exact criteria for identifying informal amendments, for instance, will obviously
depend in large measure upon what theory of constitutional interpretation one embraces, and
so it would be difficult to answer questions about the exact border between interpretive change
and informal amendment with any degree of certainty or precision, until debates over
interpretation are settled. That is not likely to happen any time soon, and yet these remain
important questions if we are to consider theories about informal amendment as useful in
identifying different forms of constitutional change.
432 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
legitimacy, but also the distinction and relationship between the
concepts of legitimacy and authority in the context of constitutional
change.
The first of the three factors that determine legitimacy, is the
extent to which decision-makers within government are deliberately
trying to bring about the specific change, in an intentional
circumvention of the formal amendment procedure. The second is the
extent to which there are explicit expressions of public will in favor of
the change. And the third is the passage of time. With respect to the
first factor, what I will call “deliberate agency,” the question is
whether the claims to legitimacy of any particular informal
amendment are (or ought to be) affected by the extent to which it is
brought about by political actors who understand that the change
constitutes an amendment, but nonetheless deliberately circumvent
the formal amendment process in executing the change. This is in
contrast to changes that might arise more organically through the
complex dynamics of the law and policy making process among
agencies and between the political branches of government, and are
thus the product of the unintentional and unpredictable operations of a
system.
9
Put simply, does informal amendment theory accept as
legitimate the deliberate circumventions of the formal amendment
procedure? I will argue below that it should not.
The second factor is that of popular will. To the extent that
informal amendment theory has addressed the issue of legitimacy, the
debate has tended to focus on the role of popular sovereignty and
expressions of public will. Bruce Ackerman, one of the driving forces
of informal amendment theory,
10
as well as Akhil Amar,
11
make
explicit claims that informal amendments ratified or initiated by the
people are legitimate precisely because they reflect an expression of
popular sovereignty.
12
These claims are contested.
13
But I will explore
them here within the context of the Japanese developments, and
examine the relationship between popular sovereignty and the
9. On system effects in the constitutional context, see Adrian Vermeule, Forward:
System Effects and the Constitution, 123 H
ARV L. REV. 4 (2009).
10. See
ACKERMAN, supra note 1.
11. See Amar, supra note 1.
12. See infra notes 79-86 and 108, and accompanying text.
13. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1. For details see infra notes 99-101 and accompanying
text.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 433
separate factors of deliberate agency and time as a basis for
legitimacy. I will argue that while Ackerman’s theory cannot be
applied to legitimate the Japanese experience, the reinterpretation in
Japan reveals insights about the value of Ackerman’s theory that have
been missed or under-appreciated in some of the critiques of his
model. Specifically, while the critics may be correct that explicit
expression of popular consent may not be a sufficient condition for
the legitimation of deliberate informal amendment, they perhaps miss
the point that such expressions of popular will ought to be a necessary
condition.
14
The third factor is time. By the passage of time, I mean to focus
on the fact that deeply contested constitutional changes, including
informal amendments widely considered to be entirely unauthorized
and illegitimate at the time they are undertaken, will gradually
become legitimate over time, so long as the change can be sustained
and entrenched.
15
Thus, for instance, if some of the moves during the
New Deal were illegitimate at the time (about which there is of course
continued and vigorous debate), most of us will agree that with the
passage of time they became legitimate in practical terms.
16
This is
due to the layers of law, policy, and precedent that are constructed
upon the foundation of these changes. But there remains the question
of whether such ex post recognition or acceptance could ever ground
an argument for legitimizing ex ante the kinds of political or
institutional developments that we are here calling informal
amendment. In other words, can one look to examples such as the
New Deal changes as precedents for purposes of legitimizing
informal constitutional changes before or at the time they are
effected? I will argue that such time-legitimated changes cannot serve
as precedents for the ex-ante legitimation of informal amendments,
particularly when such changes are the result of deliberate
circumvention of the amendment process rather than the unconscious
14. See infra Section III.C.
15. Walter Murphy has turned his attention to the issue of time in the context of
informal amendment, but does not focus on this particular aspect. See Walter F. Murphy,
Merlin’s Memory: The Past and Future Imperfect of the Once and Future Polity, in
R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 163
16. Levinson points out that even Justice Bork implicitly conceded this point even as he
argued against the validity of informal amendments. See Levinson, How Many Times Has the
United States Constitution Been Amended?, supra note 1, at 35 (citing R
OBERT BORK, THE
TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 215 (1990)).
434 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
product of dynamic systems. Be that as it may, however, the
recognition of the effects of time should also serve to galvanize into
action those who believe a change is illegitimate, for time will be of
the essence.
17
What is more, in thinking about the relationship between time
and legitimacy, we begin to understand that the passage of time is one
factor that separates authority and legitimacy. That is to say, the
legitimacy of any change is derived from and is almost synonymous
with the constitutional authority for such change, at the time it is
undertaken. But over time an unauthorized change may gain de facto
legitimacy, while its lack of theoretical authority remains constant.
18
This leads to a possible reformulation of the relationship among
authority, legitimacy, and time, which in turn leads to insights into the
role that deliberate agency and popular will might play in determining
legitimacy. I will suggest that the three factors—deliberate agency,
popular will, and time—need to be understood separately as distinct
criteria for legitimacy, but also collectively, in terms of how they
relate to one another in the determination of legitimacy. And in
particular, I will argue that this insight into the relationship between
time and legitimacy grounds both a descriptive hypothesis and a
normative argument that deliberate informal amendments such as that
undertaken in Japan, in the absence of any ratification by explicit
popular consent, will and ought to take longer to be legitimated than
other forms of change.
19
The developments in Japan may be viewed as a case study of
informal amendment that is unfolding in real-time. In order to
properly use this case study, the article takes some time to explain the
Japanese events in some detail.
20
The salient points, however, are that
the Japanese government under Prime Minister Shinzō Abe has been
engaging in an effort to relax the constitutional constraints on the use
of military force.
21
Article 9 of the Japanese Constitution famously
renounces war as a sovereign right of the nation and prohibits the
17. See infra Section III.C.
18. It has been pointed out that one could reverse this relationship, depending on how
one conceives of legitimacy and authority—that is to say that a change may become
authoritative in practical terms over time, while we might continue to insist that it lacked, and
continues to lack, formal legitimacy. Thanks to my colleague Freddy Sourgens for this point.
19. See infra Section III.C.
20. See infra Part II.
21. See infra Section II.C.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 435
threat or use of force.
22
The government quite deliberately sought to
implement what it acknowledged to be a significant change to the
understanding of Article 9, in a manner that was calculated to
circumvent the formal amendment procedure.
23
The government
implemented the reinterpretation through the issuance of a Cabinet
Decision,
24
based in part on the recommendations of an ad hoc extra-
constitutional body of so-called experts, and with little public input or
legislative debate. It then committed the nation to the reinterpretation
through international agreements with the United States. Only after all
of this did the government submit legislation to the Diet (the
legislature) that would revise national security laws in conformity
with the reinterpretation—but even this did not require a debate on
the substance of the reinterpretation itself.
Meanwhile, the government interfered with the independence of
government agencies that might oppose the reinterpretation, and tried
to suppress media criticism of the moves.
25
The entire effort gave rise
to ferocious debate and protest within Japan, with tens of thousands of
people protesting in the streets of Tokyo and other major cities. The
majority of scholarly and professional opinion held the
reinterpretation, and the subsequently revised national security laws,
to be illegitimate and unconstitutional.
26
Yet, despite all of this, the
governing party was nonetheless hugely successful in elections for the
Upper Chamber of the Diet in July of 2016. The inevitable
constitutional challenges to the national security legislation have not
yet resulted in any judicial decisions—but they will surely reach the
Supreme Court in due course. It is unclear how the Court, which has
been traditionally timid and deferential on constitutional issues, will
deal with the challenges. The government’s effort is thus still very
much a work in process and the jury is still out on whether the
22. NIHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], art. 9, para. 1 (Japan). For the full
text of the provision, see infra note 127 and accompanying text.
23. See infra Section II.C.
24. C
ABINET DECISION ON DEVELOPMENT OF SEAMLESS SECURITY LEGISLATION TO
ENSURE JAPANS SURVIVAL AND PROTECT ITS PEOPLE (provisional English translation) (July
1, 2014), available at http://www.cas.go.jp/jp/gaiyou/jimu/pdf/anpohosei_eng.pdf (last visited
Aug., 2016) [hereinafter C
ABINET DECISION]. The original Japanese language version is
available at: http://www.cas.go.jp/jp/gaiyou/jimu/pdf/anpohosei.pdf.
25. See infra Section II.C.
26. See infra notes 209-14 and accompanying text.
436 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
reinterpretation will end up being entrenched, becoming a
legitimatized change to the Constitution with the passage of time.
These developments provide the constitutional law academy
with a striking and potentially important example of deliberate efforts
to engage in constitutional change in circumvention of the formal
amendment procedure. When examined through the lens of informal
amendment theory, the over-arching question presented by the
Japanese reinterpretation effort is whether it can be classified, either
now or in the future, as nothing more than a legitimate interpretive
development, as an informal amendment, or as something else again.
I argue below that the reinterpretation of Article 9 cannot be accepted
as a normal and legitimate interpretive move—that it was arrived at
through an invalid process, and is in any event substantively outside
of the reasonable range of possible meanings of the provision when
interpreted in accordance with most widely accepted theories of
constitutional interpretation.
Moving from this premise I examine the reinterpretation from
the perspective of informal amendment theory. Specifically, I focus
on the role of deliberate agency, popular will, and passage of time as
determinants of legitimacy. The reinterpretation is one of the clearest
examples of a government trying to implement significant
constitutional change through methods that reflect a deliberate and
self-conscious effort to circumvent the formal amendment procedure,
and so brings the issue of deliberate agency into stark relief. Japan
also provides us with an excellent example of the ambiguity and
complexity involved in trying to attribute constitutional meaning to
election results following putative informal amendments. It provides
support for some of the theoretical criticism of popular sovereignty
arguments for legitimacy, but also reveals some of the overlooked
value in Ackerman’s theories about the relationship between popular
sovereignty and the legitimacy of informal amendment.
27
In sum, I
conclude that the reinterpretation is not legitimate, and that it helps
illustrates how and why deliberate agency and public will should be
considered in assessing the legitimacy of informal amendments, and
why time is of the essence in opposing them.
The article proceeds in three parts. Part I provides an
examination of informal amendment theories, focusing on how they
27. See infra Section III.C.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 437
treat the question of legitimacy, and in particular how or to what
extent the different theories consider deliberate agency, popular will,
and the passage of time as factors contributing to legitimacy. Part II
provides an explanation of Article 9 of the Constitution of Japan and
the efforts of the Japanese government to reinterpret the provision.
Part III examines first whether the reinterpretation can be
characterized as a normal interpretive development, and then analyzes
the reinterpretation as an informal amendment, assessing what it tells
us about the factors of deliberate agency, popular will, and time as
determinants of legitimacy. In addition to evaluating the legitimacy of
the reinterpretation, it examines how we might re-conceptualize the
contours of informal amendment and our understanding of the
determinants of legitimacy. The article has two audiences in mind: the
first being American constitutional law scholars, for whom it seeks to
clarify certain aspects of informal amendment theory, and explain the
significance of the Japanese example; and the second being Japanese
constitutional law scholars, for whom it seeks to provide insights and
warnings regarding what American informal amendment theory may
say about the legitimacy of the reinterpretation of Article 9.
I. INFORMAL AMENDMENT
This Part explores some of the defining features of informal
amendment theory, and in particular those differences among the
various explanations of informal amendment that are most salient to
the issues of deliberate agency, popular will, and time as factors of
legitimacy. But before launching into that examination, it may be
prudent to clarify some of the underlying assumptions and premises
of this study. As mentioned earlier, because the debate over informal
amendment implicates much broader and more fundamental
disagreements in constitutional law, it is important to be quite clear, if
necessarily brief, about some of the principles and theoretical
positions that form part of the foundation for my analysis.
A. Preliminaries - Assumptions and Premises
First, a constitution, as the legal framework that defines the
distribution of power and authority within the State, has the dual
purpose of both facilitating and making the exercise of political power
438 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
possible, and constraining government power in meaningful ways.
28
This idea that constitutions constrain the exercise of government
power of course reflects the basic democratic rule of law principle
that the law applies equally to all, including all branches and agencies
of government, and is also a necessary condition for the concept of
constitutionally protected individual rights.
29
But the idea is also the
foundation of the notion that constitutions, or at least some
constitutional provisions, serve as pre-commitment devices—that is,
mechanisms designed by the drafters to bind future generations of
government to specified values, principles, and conduct, particularly
in circumstances of crisis or passion in which future governments
might be expected to depart from the original vision of the
constitution.
30
This all may seem rather obvious, yet it bears repeating
here, because Prime Minister Shinzō Abe famously remarked in the
context of the reinterpretation debate that the idea that constitutions
are designed to limit state power was an anachronistic view.
31
Finally,
it should be noted that while binding on future generations of
government, liberal democratic constitutions derive some of their
legitimacy from the very fact that they can be changed—that they, in
effect, delegate some of the drafting authority to future generations
through the mechanism of an amending formula.
32
At the same time,
the amendment procedure is typically difficult, and must be more
difficult than the mere passage of laws if the constitution is to fulfill
its entrenchment function in any meaningful way.
33
28. Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Interpretation and Change in the United States: The
Official and the Unofficial, 14 J
US POLITICUM 1, 2 (2015) (constitutions are “frameworks for
making politics possible”).
29. We will return to this relationship between constraints and rights, but on this see,
e.g., Dow, supra note 1, at 136-37.
30. On constitutions as pre-commitment devices generally, see J
ON ELSTER, ULYSSES
AND THE
SIRENS: STUDIES IN RATIONALITY AND IRRATIONALITY (1979); see also CASS
SUNSTEIN, DESIGNING DEMOCRACY: WHAT CONSTITUTIONS DO 96-101 (2001); Stephen
Holmes, Precommitment and the Paradox of Democracy, in C
ONSTITUTIONALISM AND
DEMOCRACY 195 (Jon Elster & Rune Slagstad eds., 1988).
31. Lawyer Group Charges Abe with Constitutional Ignorance, J
APAN TIMES (Feb. 14,
2014), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2014/02/14/national/lawyer-group-charges-abe-with-
constitutional-ignorance/ (“the idea that the Constitution is intended to limit the power of the
state is an old-fashioned view held at the time when a monarch was governing the country with
absolute power.”).
32. Holmes & Sunstein, supra note 1, at 275-76.
33. Dow, supra note 1, at 136-37.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 439
The concept of “constitution” here is more than the mere text or
documents comprising the written constitution. In the United States
(and many other constitutional systems) the actual document looms
large in our thinking about the Constitution, and there are times when
a focus on the text is necessary;
34
however, it is important to
recognize that the Constitution in broader terms is best thought of as a
system. That is to say, that in addition to any document that comprises
the text of a constitution, there is a broader system of principles,
jurisprudence, conventions, understandings, and quasi-constitutional
statutes that together operate to form what may be called the
“constitution-in-practice.”
35
And like most systems, it is assumed here
that most democratic constitutional systems are dynamic and
constantly changing. To say that they are always changing is to
recognize the widely accepted idea that there is legitimate incremental
change in constitutional meaning through judicial interpretation
(recognizing, of course, that this is not accepted by certain strands of
originalist theory).
36
This is so in part because many constitutional
provisions are cast in general language, stipulating standards and
principles rather than clear rules, and thus require judgment in
interpretation, construction, and the development of doctrine and tests
for their future application.
37
While there are differing theories of precisely how constitutional
provisions ought to be interpreted, most accept that there is some
reasonable range of possible meaning for any given provision, and the
range of possible meaning under each of those theories overlap to a
considerable degree.
38
With the passage of time, shifting ideas, and
34. See, e.g., GINSBURG ET AL., supra note 1, at 6 (emphasizing that for their study “we
do indeed mean the text, specifically the written constitutional charter of independent
countries.”).
35. Balkin, supra note 28, at 3; Griffin, supra note 1, at 38, 44; see also D
AVID A.
STRAUSS, THE LIVING CONSTITUTION (2010); Jack M. Balkin, The Roots of the Living
Constitution, 92 B.U.
L. REV. 1129 (2012).
36. For an overview of originalist theories, see, e.g., T
HE CHALLENGE OF
ORIGINALISM: THEORIES OF CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION (GRANT HUSCROFT &
BRADLEY W. MILLER EDS., 2011). Not all strands of originalist theory would disagree. See,
e.g., Balkin, supra note 28, at 3-4, 21-23.
37. Balkin, supra note 28, at 2, 6-7.
38. Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?,
supra note 1, at 17-18; Lutz, Toward a Theory - Responding to Imperfection, supra note 1, at
241. For a short overview of theories of constitutional interpretation, see J
OHN H. GARVEY ET
AL
., MODERN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY: A READER 91-218 (5th ed. 2004); see also
Laurence H. Tribe, Contrasting Constitutional Visions: Of Real and Unreal Differences, 22
440 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
evolving political and social conditions, the interpretation of those
constitutional principles, standards, and constructed doctrines will
evolve incrementally in the jurisprudence of the judiciary. Moreover,
while the ultimate interpretive move is typically undertaken by the
judiciary (at least in those constitutional systems in which there is a
strong convention of constitutional judicial review), this process of
constitutional change is often driven by the other branches of
government, and indeed by political parties and civil society acting
through and on the political branches of government. In most
instances, however, the judiciary is called upon in the final stage to
either ratify or reject the resulting political action, policy, or law.
39
In
many ways the starting point for any discussion of informal
amendment is the idea that this form of interpretive development,
occurring within what most would accept as the range of reasonable
interpretation for any given provision, is valid and legitimate (with
the noted exception of certain strands of originalism).
It is widely accepted that constitutions legitimately change
through this process of interpretive development, but there is far less
agreement on where the outer limits are for the range of reasonable
and legitimate meanings of specific provisions in particular
circumstances. Similarly, there is less agreement over what it means
when any particular interpretation is widely perceived to have
exceeded the limits of legitimate interpretive moves. That some
change does exceed this limit is of course the very basis for the theory
of informal amendment. But it should be made clear that many
scholars and jurists do not accept the idea that putative interpretive
moves, or other forms of constitutional change that exceed the
legitimate bounds of this valid process of interpretive development,
can be properly characterized and normalized as so-called informal
amendments.
40
Many reject the informal amendment claims on descriptive
grounds, simply accepting as legitimate interpretation that which
HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 95 (1987) (arguing that the differences among theories of
constitutional interpretation are not as great as commonly thought).
39. Balkin, supra note 28, at 7-10. There are, of course, challenges to the idea that the
judiciary has the primary role in constitutional interpretation. See, e.g., M
ARK TUSHNET,
TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS (1999); Larry Alexander Frederick
Schauer, On Extrajudicial Constitutional Interpretation, 110 H
ARV. L. REV. 1359 (1997).
40. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1; Barnett, supra note 1.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 441
informal amendment proponents claim to be extraordinary change
requiring special explanation.
41
But more importantly, perhaps, many
also reject the claims on normative grounds, even as some of these
critics concede that as a descriptive matter significant and
unauthorized changes—changes that do exceed the reasonable limits
of interpretation—apparently do occur from time to time. I will
explore their ideas further below. For some in this camp, however, the
idea of informal amendment is bitterly acknowledged as being real,
but at the same time the source of a paradox that cripples the very
idea of rule of law constitutionalism.
42
For others it is a theory to be
denied, denounced, and rejected precisely because its acceptance
would constitute a threat to rule of law constitutionalism.
43
While I am sympathetic to several of the normative arguments of
the critics of informal amendment theory, in this article I assume that
the phenomenon it seeks to explain is real, and that moreover it is an
important issue that requires explanation. Certainly in the American
context (but not only in the American context) there are changes that
are difficult to account for by reference to “normal” interpretive
developments. Moreover, efforts to reconcile such changes with our
accepted theories of constitutional interpretation can end up
weakening the coherence and integrity of those theories, and
undermining the normative power of the Constitution. Thus, the
article takes the theory of informal amendment on its own terms, and
tries to explore the different approaches, explanations, and some
unresolved questions about the process, with a view to advancing our
understanding of the theory. At the same time, it is worth noting that
the informal amendment theories under discussion here, as different
as they are in their detail, all share the idea that a constitution itself, as
a body of law, provides the framework within which one must
consider the idea of constitutional change. This is in contrast to some
scholars who argue that one can validly and legitimately think about
bringing about constitutional change through the radical change to the
socio-political presuppositions from which a constitution initially
developed, in total disregard of what the constitutional system itself
41. See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 1, at 279, n.9.
42. See, e.g., Griffin, supra note 1.
43. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1.
442 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
provides regarding amendment.
44
I am not here engaging these more
radical political theories of constitutional change.
Finally, some preliminary words are perhaps necessary on the
question of whether it is proper or feasible to apply this American
theory of constitutional law to a Japanese situation; and, similarly,
whether it is possible to draw any meaningful lessons for the
American theory from a Japanese case study. It is of course widely
accepted that the comparative analysis of constitutional law is both
valid and fruitful, and there is a growing literature on the topic.
45
With
respect to theories of informal amendment more specifically, most
writing in the American academy has been focused on the American
constitutional experience. Indeed some aspects of American
explanations relate to attributes that are unique to the American
system and its history. But the phenomenon it explores is certainly not
limited to the United States. Questions as to how far the range of
reasonable and legitimate interpretive development extend, and what
branches of government can be involved, are not unique. The
principles involved are common to most liberal constitutional
democracies.
46
What is more, there are have been other comparative
44. Frederick Schauer, Amending the Presuppositions of a Constitution, in
R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 145.
45. See, e.g., C
OMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL DESIGN: COMPARATIVE
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW AND POLICY (Tom Ginsburg ed., 2014); MARK TUSHNET, ADVANCED
INTRODUCTION TO COMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (2006); COMPARATIVE
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (Tom Ginsburg & Rosalind Dixon eds., 2013); Mark Tushnet, The
Possibilities of Comparative Constitutional Law, 108 Y
ALE L.J. 1225 (1999).
46. There are analogous European theories of constitutional mutation that have much
in common with informal amendment theory. In particular see the theories of informal
constitutional change developed by Georg Jellinek, discussed in Carlos Bernal, Forward-
Informal Constitutional Change: A Critical Introduction and Appraisal, 62 A
M. J. COMP. L.
493, 505 n.40 (2014). Similarly, in several of the Commonwealth countries there are forms of
constitutional change that might fall within the range of what is here being called informal
amendment, such as the creation of “constitutional conventions,” some of which are
recognized as legitimate and for which criteria are clearly established. See S
IR W. IVOR
JENNINGS, THE LAW AND THE CONSTITUTION 136 (5th ed., 1959) (articulating the seminal test
for the establishment of a convention). See Ryan Patrick Alford, War With ISIL: Should
Parliament Decide? 20 R
EV. CONST. STUD. 118, 123-28 (2015) (reviewing the modern law on
conventions, and describing the establishment of a new convention on parliamentary approval
of the use of force in the United Kingdom, 2003-14). It might be argued that it is a misnomer
to classify such a convention an informal amendment, since the United Kingdom does not
have a written constitution, and so no formal constitutional amendment procedure, but the fact
that the concept has been adopted in commonwealth countries that do have written
constitutions, with formal amendment procedures, arguably makes the process relevant to
informal amendment theory. But see Richard Albert, Constitutional Amendment by Stealth, 60
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 443
studies that have examined putative examples of informal amendment
in other countries through the lens of American informal amendment
theory.
47
Thus, on both questions of whether the theory is applicable
in other contexts, and whether a Japanese case study can provide
insights, I would argue that the theory is entirely susceptible to
analysis from a comparative law perspective—and for reasons I will
explain in more detail below, American scholars and jurists can
indeed learn from the Japanese experience. Nor is it inappropriate or
inapt to suggest that the theory is relevant to Japan in particular,
notwithstanding that the country is governed by a civil law system
owing much of its legal tradition to Germany. The reality is that
Japanese scholars, lawyers, and jurists increasingly look to American
legal theory, jurisprudence, and scholarship in their own legal
discourse, even on constitutional law, and thus this form of
comparative analysis is not at all unusual in the Japanese context.
48
B. Theories of Informal Amendment and the Issue of Legitimacy
Considerable differences exist among theorists who argue that
there has been constitutional change through some form of informal
amendment in the United States. They differ in terms of their
descriptive explanations of the modalities of the process, the scope of
the phenomenon, and the means of identifying any given informal
amendment. They also differ in terms of their normative claims
regarding the legitimacy, putative benefits, or perceived dangers of
informal amendments. Indeed, some of those who explain alternative
means of constitutional change do not use the term “informal
amendment” at all, and may not situate themselves directly within
MCGILL L.J. 673, 678 (2015) (arguing that efforts to deliberately create such constitutional
conventions are a form of informal amendment, but are illegitimate).
47. See, e.g., Carlos Bernal, Unconstitutional Constitutional Amendments in the Case
Study of Columbia: An Analysis of the Justification and Meaning of Constitutional
Replacement Doctrine, 11 I
NTL J. CONST. L. 339 (2013); Sujit Choudhry, Ackerman’s Higher
Lawmaking in Comparative Constitutional Perspective: Constitutional Moments as
Constitutional Failures, 6 I
NTL J. CONST. L. 193 (2008).
48. See, e.g., Hidenori Tomatsu, Judicial Review in Japan: An Overview of Efforts to
Introduce U.S. Theories, in F
IVE DECADES OF CONSTITUTIONALISM IN JAPANESE SOCIETY
251-77 (Yoichi Higuchi ed., 2001); see also NOBUYOSHI ASHIBE, KENPŌ [CONSTITUTIONAL
LAW] (3d ed. 2002) (this seminal constitutional text imports, for instance, American levels of
scrutiny for judicial review of equality claims); S
HINEGORI MATSUI, NIHON KOKU KENPŌ
[J
APANESE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW] (2d ed. 2002) (Matsui, a former student of John Hart Ely,
is the primary proponent of process theory in Japanese constitutional discourse).
444 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
that debate, though their theories certainly implicate any discussion of
informal amendment.
49
Still, it is fair to say that all of the scholars
involved share the common purpose of trying to explain constitutional
change in more realistic and functional terms. They are trying to
address the fact that the US Constitution, as a system, has changed
markedly over its history, quite separate and apart from the changes
wrought by the few formal amendments, and in ways that are at times
very difficult to reconcile with most notions of legitimate interpretive
development.
50
As will become apparent in this Part, these explanations and the
differences among them give rise to a number of unresolved
questions. I want to suggest, however, that one of the most
fundamental of these questions relates to the issue of legitimacy. At
root, all of these theories and explanations are in some form or
another groping for a means of determining whether any particular
form of constitutional change is or is not legitimate. Indeed, these
explanations are to some degree motivated by the perceived problem
that traditional perspectives, which apparently accept all of these
problematic constitutional changes as “normal” interpretive
developments, are simply ignoring and papering over the questions of
legitimacy raised by potentially unauthorized forms of constitutional
change. But while this may be the subtext, the explanations do not all
address legitimacy explicitly, and those that do, tend to do so in
various ways and to differing degrees.
Before comparing their theoretical explanations, however, it is
worth pausing to further clarify what is meant here by the legitimacy
of constitutional change. There is, of course, considerable literature
on the distinction between legality, authority, legitimacy, and power,
not only in legal discourse but in political science and political
philosophy.
51
I will argue in Part III that the passage of time operates
to open up a distinction between the authority and legitimacy of
informal amendments. But in the first instance, at the time that change
occurs, I conceive of legitimacy as flowing from the formal
49. See, e.g., Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1.
50. See, e.g., Sanford Levinson, Introduction: Imperfection and Amendability, in
R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 3-11.
51. See, e.g., Dan Priel, The Place of Legitimacy in Legal Theory, 57 M
CGILL L.J. 1
(2011) (comparing legitimacy to validity, content, and normativity, with particular reference to
Dworkin).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 445
constitutional authority—like Murphy, who uses legitimacy as
referring “not to popular support but to grounding in the existing
system’s fundamental normative principles.”
52
In this sense,
legitimacy and authority are closely aligned at the time of the
constitutional change, at least to the extent that the source of authority
is itself then accepted and acknowledged as valid and legitimate. In
this understanding, the authority for constitutional change relates to
the formal source of that authority in either constitutional text or other
fundamental normative principle. But the concept of legitimacy of the
change has an additional aspect that is related to the perception and
acceptance of the authoritativeness and validity of the change by
those subject to the constitution. There is thus a psychological
component to legitimacy, derived in the first instance from
perceptions of the principled nature, virtue or validity of the
institutional decision-maker or agent of change. It has been noted that
the Supreme Court of the United States has itself referred to
legitimacy in this sense, as depending in part upon the perceptions of
the people.
53
But over time (as will be discussed below) legitimacy
for a change initially viewed as insufficiently authorized, may
develop from mere acceptance or acquiescence, due to the extent to
which the change has become entrenched and insinuated into the
broader legal system.
54
Returning to the discussion of how legitimacy is treated within
informal amendment theory, Sandy Levinson is one theorist who does
discuss the issue. He suggests that to accept a given constitutional
interpretation as such, is to “accord it a certain dignity” as a legitimate
understanding of the Constitution, while formal amendments are ipso
facto legitimated by the authority of the formal amendment
procedure. Thus, he suggests that to reject that a putative
interpretation is the result of a good faith exercise in legitimate
interpretation, or that it can be plausibly supported by accepted
canons of constitutional interpretation, is to suggest that the effort is
52. Murphy, supra note 15, at 173.
53. Tom R. Tyler & Gregory Mitchell, Legitimacy and the Empowerment of
Discretionary Legal Authority: The United States Supreme Court and Abortion Rights, 43
D
UKE L. J. 703, 709 (1994) (citing Casey v. Planned Parenthood, 505 U.S. 833, 2814-16
(1992)).
54. Owen M. Fiss, Objectivity and Interpretation, 34 S
TAN. L. REV. 739, 756 (1982)
(citing H
ANS KELSEN, GENERAL THEORY OF LAW AND STATE (1945)). For further discussion,
see infra note 287 and accompanying text.
446 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
to surreptitiously amend the Constitution under the pretext of
interpretation.
55
This is to acknowledge that informal amendments
have a legitimacy problem, and even points to the fact that intent and
good faith are factors in determining legitimacy. Yet he does not
return to directly deal with the issue of how the legitimacy of any
given informal amendment is to be determined. The critics, of course,
squarely deny that informal amendments can ever be legitimate at
all.
56
I would suggest that the question of legitimacy has not been
sufficiently addressed in the discourse on informal amendment. Most
of the proponents of informal amendment theory do not identify the
factors that are essential to the legitimacy of constitutional change in
general, and the criteria that might be applied to assess the legitimacy
of specific changes, either at the time such change is unfolding or at
some time after the fact.
57
In the rest of this Section I will explore
several of the prominent theoretical explanations of constitutional
change, paying particular attention to how they address the question
of legitimacy, and more specifically how, under any particular
explanation, these factors may impact the legitimacy of any given
process of constitutional change.
It is helpful to be clear that these more realist and functional
explanations of constitutional change are responding to a perceived
traditional view. To varying degrees and in somewhat different ways,
the proponents of informal amendment claim that there is a
mythological and romantic conception of the US Constitution, in
response to which they are offering what they suggest is a more
realistic understanding.
58
The traditional narrative, they argue, tends
to exaggerate the importance of the constitutional text, the meaning of
which is understood to be authoritatively interpreted and enforced by
the courts. This traditional view downplays or discounts the extent to
55. Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?,
supra note 1, at 7, 17.
56. See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 1; Dow, supra note 1.
57. This is not to say, of course, that there has been no consideration of the question of
legitimacy. As discussed below, Ackerman does make a specific normative argument for the
legitimacy of certain forms of informal amendment; Brannon Denning proposes a theory for
the legitimacy of “constitutional change”, while carefully arguing that such change should not
be characterized as an amendment. See Brannon P. Denning, Means To Amend: Theories of
Constitutional Change, 65 T
ENN. L. REV. 155 (1997).
58. See, e.g., A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 162, 211-12.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 447
which the Constitution is best understood as a system of principles,
norms, conventions, and institutions. A system defined and governed,
it is true, by the framework laid out in the constitutional document,
but nonetheless far more complex in operation than can be discerned
or even inferred from the mere text of the document. Moreover, under
the mythological or romantic view, the Constitution is viewed as the
highest law of the land that trumps all other law, due to the authority
it enjoys as a result of the super-majoritarian process by which it was
ratified and subsequently amended, consistent with the fundamental
ideals of popular sovereignty.
59
Finally, according to the critics,
myths have developed to explain dramatic constitutional changes,
such as those that accompanied the New Deal, such that they can be
implausibly reconciled with this traditional narrative and its principles
of interpretative development.
60
The proponents of informal
amendment are seeking to pull aside this formalistic account and
provide not only a more realistic description, but also a more
sophisticated functional explanation. And some of them are trying to
provide a normative defense of these extra-textual non-formal
amendments.
While these realist theories share a purpose of trying to better
explain constitutional change, the explanations tend to differ in their
understanding of the mechanisms and modalities of the process of
change. I should also emphasize that some of these explanations of
constitutional change relate to legitimate interpretive development as
well as to what we are here calling informal amendment—they
advance a more realistic account for all constitutional change along a
spectrum, and do not always focus on defining the dividing line
between interpretive change and informal amendment. Levinson
breaks down the forms of constitutional change along this conceptual
spectrum in the following way: (i) regular interpretation, typically by
the judiciary; (ii) interpretive change in government powers effected
by permissible legislation, executive order, or other policy; (iii)
amendment, which represents a genuine change that is “not immanent
within the pre-existing materials or allowable simply by the use of
powers granted (or tolerated) by the [C]onstitution”; (iv) revision,
which is a more significant kind of amendment, that alters more
59. ESKRIDGE & FEREJOHN, supra note 1, at 34.
60. A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 199, 210-211.
448 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
fundamental aspects of the Constitution, but is nonetheless congruent
with the values of the Constitution, and effected through the formal
amendment procedure for such revision; and (v) revolutionary
change, being constitutional change of such a dimension that it is not
consistent with the immanent constitutional order, and which is
“legitimated, if at all, by some extra-constitutional set of events.”
61
The “amendment” in (iii) is, to the extent it is not done in accordance
with the amending formula, what we are calling informal amendment.
We need not concern ourselves here with the distinction between
“amendment” and “revision,” but are interested in the difference
between “amendment” and the two forms of “interpretive change” on
the one hand, or “revolution” on the other.
While differing in their emphasis, the most common
explanations tend to focus on changes arising from some combination
of the judgments of courts, the implementation of law and policy by
the political branches and the bureaucracy, and activities of various
actors within civil society. As Jack Balkin describes it, constitutional
change generally comes through a recursive process in which courts
develop and apply constitutional constructions, which are more than
mere interpretations of the text but rather are doctrines and tests
developed for use in the analysis and application of principles and
standards articulated in the Constitution.
62
But construction is also
developed by political branches of government and applied in the
form of new laws, policies, institutions, and practices, and then
pressed upon the judiciary to accept and endorse in the course of
constitutional litigation. What is more, the political branches
frequently develop such constructions under pressure or influence
from other actors in civil society. There is, therefore, a recursive
dialectical process among all these actors that leads to new
constitutional constructions.
63
Most of the results of this process of constitutional change would
be characterized by many or even most jurists as being within the
61. Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?,
supra note 1, at 21. It should be noted that different scholars use the term or concept of
“revision” somewhat differently, but here Levinson is drawing from certain State constitutions,
such as that of California, that explicitly contemplate a revision as being a more fundamental
and significant form of amendment. We can put this distinction to one side for the moment.
62. Balkin, supra note 28, at 6-7.
63. Id. at 8-10.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 449
scope of legitimate interpretive development, and thus not within the
realm of informal amendment. But the implication here is that there
will be times when the dialectic process results in “state building
constructions,” by which Balkin means new constructions that both
constitute significant interpretive moves and result in the construction
of new state capacities.
64
Some of these state building constructions
will exceed the range of reasonable meaning supported by most
theories of constitutional interpretation, at which point we have what
some would call informal amendment.
Some (but by no means all) proponents of informal amendment
have drawn examples from the New Deal as reflecting this kind of
combined construction, with judicial ratification of government action
in the form of judgments that exceeded the limits of normal
interpretive development.
65
This would include several of the
innovative government programs, such as the National Labor
Relations Act
66
and the Social Security Act,
67
advanced by the
Roosevelt administration during the later stages of the New Deal.
These were then validated in a string of decisions by the Supreme
Court, which had begun to exhibit a clearly shifting understanding of
the relevant provisions of the Constitution.
68
The constitutional
changes wrought during the later stages of the New Deal quite
obviously reflect one of the primary practical examples of the
difficulty in determining the border between legitimate interpretive
development and informal amendment. Ackerman, Strauss, and
Levinson are just some of the more prominent scholars to suggest that
these changes exceeded the range of normal interpretive development,
while Stephen Holmes and Cass Sunstein, David Dow, and many
others involved in the debate clearly disagree.
69
64. Id. at 9. See also Heather Gerken, The Hydraulics of Constitutional Reform, supra
note 1, (arguing that informal amendment is the result of a dialogical process involving inter-
institutional debate and input from civil society).
65. A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 1-420; ESKRIDGE & FEREJOHN, supra note 1, at 46;
Strauss, supra note 1, at 1475-76; Balkin, supra note 28, at 11-12; Stephen Griffin, The
Problem of Constitutional Change, 70 T
UL. L. REV. 2121 (1996).
66. National Labor Relations Act of 1935, Pub. L. No. 74-198, 49 Stat. 449 (codified as
amended at 29 U.S.C. §§ 151-169 (2012)).
67. Social Security Act, Pub. L. No. 74-271, 49 Stat. 620 (codified as amended at 42
U.S.C. ch. 7 (2012)).
68. A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 141-50.
69. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1, at 126-27; Sunstein, supra note 1, at 279, n.9.
450 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
What is less clear in the debate, however, is how the proponents
of informal amendment understand the legitimacy of these changes.
Ackerman, as we will see below, makes very explicit claims
regarding their legitimacy, but many of the others do not. If the
decisions of the Supreme Court that ratified or acquiesced in these
changes exceeded the range of reasonable interpretation, were they
thus illegitimate at the time? Did the fact that Roosevelt and his
Cabinet thought the programs were constitutional, and that the
Supreme Court of the early 1930s had been wrong in its
understanding of the relevant provisions of the Constitution, make a
difference to how legitimate the changes were at the time? To put it
another way, if there was evidence that Roosevelt thought that his
programs were inconsistent with the Constitution but he set out to
implement them anyway in order to force an informal change to
constitutional understanding, rather than pursue a formal Article V
amendment, would that (or should that) influence our assessment of
their legitimacy?
The proponents of informal amendment do not directly explore
these questions in any sort of comprehensive way. Ackerman, one of
the few who tackles legitimacy head on, focuses on the role of
expressions of popular will as legitimating these changes, rather than
on the intent of the agents of change.
70
What is clear, however, is that
none of the proponents of informal amendment argue that the changes
are now illegitimate. In other words, with the passage of time the
changes were entrenched and at some point accepted as legitimate
within the constitutional system.
Some observers, such as David Strauss (who goes so far as to
argue that informal amendments are far more significant mechanisms
of constitutional change than formal amendments),
71
go further back
in time to identify such cases as McCulloch v. Maryland
72
as being
illustrative of this process of combined government-judiciary
constructions. In McCulloch the Supreme Court adopted a very broad
interpretation of the Necessary and Proper Clause
73
to validate the
70. ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 141-50.
71. Strauss, supra note 1, at 1459.
72. McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819).
73. U.S.
CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 18 (which provides that: “The Congress shall have
Power. . . To make all Laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying into Execution
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 451
Federal Government’s constitutional authority to establish the Second
Bank of the United States.
74
When Hamilton had earlier relied on
similar arguments to justify the establishment of the First Bank,
James Madison had responded that the Constitution would not likely
have been ratified had the clause been so understood at the time. Yet
some twenty five years later, as President Madison, he accepted that
this understanding was by then entrenched and so must be accepted.
75
While Strauss does not make explicit what his views are on the
legitimacy of the decision in McCulloch at the time it was made, the
implication is certainly that the Court’s judgment was outside of the
reasonable range of meanings supported by accepted theories of
constitutional interpretation. That would suggest that Strauss
considers it to have been illegitimate at the time. Yet he describes
how it became accepted—and thereby arguably legitimate—with the
passage of time; and in Madison’s eyes, the passage of a mere twenty
five years was sufficient.
While Strauss and others tend to emphasize the judicial role in
this process, others such as Eskridge and Ferejohn tend to focus on
the role of legislation, and of unelected officials within both the
legislature and the executive, in driving change.
76
Again, this
approach is more of a shift in emphasis than an entirely different
theory of change. It too is responding to the formalistic and traditional
view of constitutional law, an account which critics such as Eskridge
argue must be revised to acknowledge the role of “super-statutes” and
“administrative constitutionalism” in expanding and developing the
constitutional system.
77
Without getting into the details of their
explanations, they rely to a considerable extent on the deliberative
process by which these super-statutes are enacted. It is for this reason
that Eskridge and Ferejohn term the process “administrative
the foregoing Powers, and all other Powers vested by this Constitution in the Government of
the United States, or in any Department or Officer thereof.”).
74. See Strauss, supra note 1; see also A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 126 (in which
Ackerman also identifies McCulloch v. Maryland, and the consequent expansion of the
Necessary and Proper clause, as an informal amendment).
75. Strauss, supra note 1, at 1473; see P
ETER SUBER, THE PARADOX OF SELF-
A
MENDMENT 197-206 (1990); JAMES BOYD WHITE, WHEN WORDS LOSE THEIR MEANING
263 (1984); see also Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been
Amended?, supra note 1, at 22.
76. E
SKRIDGE & FEREJOHN, supra note 1.
77. Id. at 26.
452 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
constitutionalism,” in contrast to a “judicial constitutionalism” that
emphasizes the role of the judiciary in driving interpretive change.
78
This emphasis on the deliberative process and the extent to which the
statutes reflect the popular will might be seen as grounding some
claim to legitimacy. But suppose that the judicial decisions ratifying
these super statutes provide interpretations of the implicated
constitutional provisions that are outside the reasonable range of
legitimate interpretation—Eskridge and Ferejohn do not actually
focus directly on the issue of whether such changes may raise
questions of legitimacy.
The proponents of informal amendment who are clearest on the
issue of legitimacy are perhaps Ackerman and Amar, both of whom
ground their arguments in favor of informal amendment in notions of
popular sovereignty (though in strikingly different ways). Ackerman,
who is perhaps the most closely associated with theories of informal
amendment, also delves more deeply into the process by which such
amendments might unfold and the form they might take. In so doing
he provides some criteria for how to assess constitutional changes that
are candidates for classification as informal amendment.
79
He begins
with the notion that while most law is made by the government, there
is also (in the American context at least) a “higher law” that is created
by the people. From this he argues that informal amendment can be
characterized as an example of this form of higher law, which may be
made in violation of the formal amendment procedure, and yet still
fall within the framework of the Constitution and be consistent with
its underlying vision.
80
This creation of higher law by the people
occurs in “constitutional moments,” characterized by a response to
some form of constitutional crisis. Three examples of such
constitutional moments that lead to informal amendments, in
Ackerman’s view, are the original drafting and ratification process (as
a change to the Articles of Confederation), the Reconstruction
Amendments, and the New Deal programs discussed above. From
these examples he abstracts a five-stage model of the process by
which this form of constitutional change occurs.
81
78. Id. at 33.
79. A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 403-20.
80. Id. at 248, 296.
81. Id. at 402.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 453
The first stage is characterized by a constitutional impasse, in
which there is increasing disagreement over not only specific
substantive policy being pursued by one of the political branches, but
also over the extent to which such policy is constitutionally
permissible. In the New Deal this impasse was over the President’s
efforts, through both executive orders and federal legislation, to
establish a foundation for more progressive social welfare, labor, and
financial regulatory regimes.
82
The second stage is electoral success
by the party pressing for change, which is seen as a public ratification
of the contentious programs, and is the initial step in the people’s role
in the process. The third stage involves the political branch that is
pressing for change, taking steps to challenge and confront those
institutions that are “dissenting” or standing in the way of progress
and thereby causing the impasse. During the New Deal, the executive
was the branch pressing for change, with support from Congress,
while the dissenting institution was the Supreme Court, which viewed
the innovations as inconsistent with an interpretation of the
Constitution that was strongly infused with ideas of laissez-faire
economic theory and States’ rights. The challenge to the Court came
most explicitly with Roosevelt’s threat to “pack the Court,” but
political pressure had been mounting even prior to that.
83
The fourth stage of Ackerman’s framework is what he calls the
“switch in time,” which is characterized by the challenged institution
essentially buckling under the pressure or threat and changing course
in line with the wishes of the moving branch before any lasting harm
can be caused to the challenged institution or the system as a whole.
The switch in time during the New Deal era, of course, was in the
form of the Supreme Court beginning to change direction with its
repudiation of the Lochner line of cases and acceptance of
Roosevelt’s new labor and social security legislation.
84
The entire
process of informal amendment, however, is not complete until, in the
fifth stage, the people ratify the changes through a consolidating
popular election, in which the branch that had been pressing for the
changes is vindicated with electoral success.
85
Assessing whether this
stage of the model has been met, of course, requires significant
82. Id. at 464.
83. See id.
84. A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 400.
85. Id. at 402.
454 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
interpretation and attribution of meaning to electoral results, which is
open to significant question and has been the subject of considerable
criticism.
86
A great deal has been written about Ackerman’s model, and
while it has been very influential, aspects of it have also been heavily
criticized. For the moment, however, I want to focus on how it relates
to the three elements I am examining here. First, Ackerman is clearly
making a normative claim that such informal amendments are
legitimate precisely because they are expressions of popular
sovereignty. But because of the elaborate nature of the process, with
the determination that a given constitutional change is a legitimate
informal amendment being contingent upon it satisfying the key
elements of the five-stage model, it too would seem to be entirely
retrospective. It does not depend upon the passage of time to confer
legitimacy, since that is derived from the expression of popular
sovereignty, but the passage of some time appears to be nonetheless
required before one can identify developments as a legitimate
informal amendment according to this model. Balkin and Levinson
have made this point, arguing that Ackerman’s theory “works best in
hindsight” and that it “offers little help for someone in the midst of
potential constitutional revolution who needs guidance.”
87
Moreover,
they note that Ackerman’s theory requires actors to intuitively
recognize, understand, and embrace the criteria for constitutional
change that his model stipulates in order for them to understand
whether some of the pre-conditions for action have been satisfied—
“they must understand that a key moment of transition has occurred
or that a form of unconventional adaptation has been confirmed
through subsequent election.”
88
These last comments also get at the issue of intent in
Ackerman’s theory. I think that Ackerman, in contrast to many of the
other proponents discussed thus far, would not view it as a problem
that some of the actors involved in the process of informal
amendment were acting with a deliberate view to effecting change
outside of the formal amendment process. They would be viewed as
merely engaging in what he calls constitutional politics. I do not read
86. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1, at 117.
87. Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1079-80.
88. Id.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 455
Ackerman as suggesting that it would have deprived the informal
amendment of legitimacy had Roosevelt been acting in a self-
conscious and deliberate fashion to circumvent the Article V
amendment procedure in order to effect constitutional change. But
this is precisely because for Ackerman the legitimacy is derived from
the popular ratification after a period of contested deliberative
democratic process, in not one but two stages of the process. And, as
Balkin and Levinson suggest, whether the change has been so ratified
can only be assessed after the fact, and thus the model is of little
assistance to those acting in the moment, in the middle of the process.
Balkin and Levinson have proposed an alternative theory of
what they call “constitutional revolution.” While presented as an
alternative to Ackerman’s theory of constitutional change, it builds on
Balkin’s idea of the state-building construction through a dialectic
process among the judiciary, the other branches of government, and
civil society. What is different is that it suggests that the process can
be skewed by a process of “partisan entrenchment” to create more
radical or “revolutionary” change.
89
Partisan entrenchment refers to a
sustained ideological shift in the Federal judiciary during periods in
which one political party is dominant for sufficient time to
significantly alter the composition of the judiciary, and particularly
the Supreme Court, by appointing judges who subscribe to a
particular ideological position on constitutional issues. Because
Supreme Court justices serve for almost two decades on average, their
influence persists well after the period of domination by the political
party that appointed them. Balkin and Levinson argue that when a
party has been able to dominate long enough to appoint sufficient
numbers of judges and justices to create an imbalance within the
Federal judiciary, an imbalance that tends to then be entrenched for a
period lasting well beyond the party’s ascendency, the judiciary will
tend to represent and express their nominating party’s understanding
of the Constitution and public policy. The cumulative and aggregate
effect of their constitutional decisions begin to change the
interpretation and construction of the Constitution along the lines
consistent with their party’s understanding of the Constitution.
90
And
this can give rise to constitutional revolutions, which are significant,
89. Id.
90. Id. at 1067-68.
456 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
sustained departures from established understandings of the
Constitution and its fundamental constitutive principles, and at times
outside the range of the reasonable possible meanings of specific
provisions.
91
Balkin and Levinson do not explicitly suggest that they view
such “revolutions” as being per se illegitimate, or indicate whether
some may be legitimate while others are not. But the implication is
that they view some revolutions as having been legitimate, at least
with the passage of time. For instance, they explain the judicial
appointments by Roosevelt and the subsequent ratification of
Roosevelt’s New Deal programs by the reformed Supreme Court as
being an example of constitutional revolution resulting from partisan
retrenchment.
92
Yet they do not seem to suggest that this was in any
way an illegitimate constitutional change. Indeed, Balkin has
elsewhere viewed the New Deal as being within the ambit of natural
and legitimate constitutional change.
93
On the other hand, they also
argue that the changes wrought with respect to States’ rights, racial
equality, and civil rights by the Rehnquist Court in the fifteen years
leading up to Bush v. Gore constitute a constitutional revolution
resulting from partisan entrenchment.
94
While they do not explicitly
state that this revolution constitutes illegitimate change, they are
clearly far more critical of the substance of these changes under the
Rehnquist Court than they are of the New Deal changes, or changes
wrought by the Warren Court.
Intent or deliberate agency would not seem to be a factor in
determining legitimacy under this theory, but this is largely due to the
nature of the process itself. There is of course a deliberate and self-
conscious aspect to the decisions of politicians to appoint judges that
share a particular understanding of the Constitution. Increasingly, in
the last couple of decades, this can be seen as part of a deliberate
strategy to effect precisely the kind of partisan entrenchment that
91. It is not entirely clear whether Levinson would characterize these revolutions as
being the same as the “revolutions” in his five-stage spectrum of constitutional change. See
Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?, in
R
ESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 21, and text associated with note 73, supra.
(It does not seem to me that what he and Balkin describe in their theory is change of quite that
magnitude).
92. Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1073.
93. Balkin, supra note 28, at 11-12.
94. Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1052-53.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 457
Balkin and Levinson identify. But as they argue, the process of
change that results from this appointment of like-minded judges is
incremental and unpredictable—the result of a complex mix of
factors—and contingent on such variables as the mix of cases that
come before the courts.
95
The government actors cannot be said to
have acted with deliberation and calculation in trying to bring about
any specific change, but rather only to move the ideological center of
constitutional understanding in a particular direction. Thus, it would
seem to follow that intent or deliberate agency in trying to circumvent
the formal amendment procedure are not going to be elements in
determining the legitimacy of any particular change under this theory
of constitutional change.
It may be that the key to understanding their position on the
legitimacy of this more radical form of constitutional change is to be
found in their arguments on how best to respond to constitutional
revolution. They argue that it is somewhat meaningless, at least ex
post, to criticize constitutional revolutions on the grounds that the
changes wrought failed to comply with the constitutional principles
that govern and define legitimate constitutional change. That is, to
argue that the changes failed to comply with amendment procedure,
or that they are outside of the range of reasonable interpretation.
Meaningless not because such arguments are wrong, but because they
will have little or no purchase—they are not, for instance, going to
convince Supreme Court justices to alter their views or their
subsequent judgment. Rather, Balkin and Levinson argue,
constitutional revolutions must be criticized on the basis of the
substantive public policy principles that the revolution seeks to
advance, its conception of “we the people,” and “the constitutional
principles that [the revolution] espouses and the vision of the country
that it summons.”
96
In short, they argue that one must criticize such
changes not in terms of constitutional law, but in terms of what they
call “high-politics,” with a view to winning the political battle over
control of the appointments process.
97
95. Id. at 1081-82.
96. Id. at 1088.
97. They conceive of high-politics as the discourse and struggle over constitutional and
political ideologies regarding such issues as State rights, civil rights, distributive justice, and so
forth, as distinguished from the kind of partisan politics that can be called low-politics, which
they claim was reflected in Bush v. Gore. See id. at 1061-62.
458 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
This would seem to suggest that at least when assessing the
legitimacy of the kind of change that takes the form of constitutional
revolution through partisan entrenchment, the determination is likely
to be deeply divided and contested along partisan or ideological lines,
based on each observer’s ideological and normative understanding of
the Constitution’s vision. Legitimacy will be based on one’s
agreement or disagreement with the substance of the change, and not
by reference to legal arguments over the range of reasonable
meanings that can be supported by the text, purpose, history and
operation of a constitutional provision, in accordance with accepted
theories of interpretation. In short, the passage of time will likely
confer legitimacy on any revolutionary change so long as it can be
sustained over time, regardless how contested it is at the time of its
development, and this means it will be more difficult to overturn such
changes absent a countervailing revolution.
As I will take up in more detail below, this conclusion means
that time is of the essence in disputing such changes at the time that
they get underway. Balkin and Levinson, writing in the aftermath of
Bush v. Gore and bewailing the conservative constitutional revolution
flowing from the Republican Party’s partisan entrenchment of
appointees in the judiciary leading up to that most political of cases,
suggest that if President Bush were to win the upcoming 2004
election, it would tend to further entrench and perhaps even legitimate
the changes wrought in the revolution.
98
Thus, while certainly not the
kind of normative arguments for legitimating constitutional change
through popular sovereignty advanced by Ackerman and Amar, in
practical and descriptive terms we are back to the idea that
legitimation may come through some form of ratification by the
expression of popular will, if only because success in the election will
lead to an extension of the entrenchment period and thus legitimation
through the passage of time.
C. Critics and the Contours of Legitimacy
These claims of informal amendment have been the subject of
considerable criticism. These criticisms relate to both the descriptive
and normative aspects of the claims. As a descriptive matter, critics
question what the criteria are for determining whether any given
98. Id. at 1103-04.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 459
constitutional change constitutes an informal amendment. And from a
normative perspective, if such change can ever be legitimate in
principle, what exactly are the criteria for determining whether any
such specific change is legitimate?
Going beyond such questions, many of the critics advance
affirmative normative arguments against the theories of informal
amendment. David Dow is one of the harshest critics along these
lines. He, like Griffin, seems to concede that informal amendments
may occur as a descriptive matter, but he argues that proponents such
as Ackerman and Amar fatally confuse an ability and power to effect
informal amendment with the authority and legitimacy to do so. That
such change may happen does not make it right or suggest that there
was any legal authority for it, or that any legitimacy can or should be
conferred upon it after the fact. Thus, in his view, the claims of
Ackerman and Amar that such informal amendment could ever be
legitimate is flawed.
99
The theoretical foundation for Dow’s argument is not mere
formalism and a dogmatic adherence to the text of the Constitution.
Rather, he argues that to accept the idea that the Constitution can be
amended by majority whim, apart from the formal amendment
process, would be to hopelessly undermine the notion of strong
individual rights.
100
Moreover, he points out that the projects of both
Ackerman and Amar are in part trying to wrestle with the counter-
majoritarian problem posed by the difficulty of amendment. But they
make the crucial error of conflating popular sovereignty with
majoritarianism in the process. It is due to this conflation that they
mistakenly argue that change wrought by a popular majority
somehow constitutes an expression of popular sovereignty. Yet, the
formulation and ratification of a difficult amendment process, one that
requires a supermajority, was itself an exercise of popular
sovereignty.
101
Cass Sunstein and Stephen Holmes similarly note that while the
difficulty of formal amendment does pose a counter-majoritarian
problem, it is not inconsistent with democratic principles. While a
liberal democratic constitution derives much of its legitimacy from
99. See, e.g., Dow, supra note 1; see also Barnett, supra note 1.
100. Dow, supra note 1, at 127-28.
101. Id.
460 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
the idea that it can be amended in the future, with the amendment
procedure comprising a delegation of drafting authority to future
generations, the process must be sufficiently difficult in order to
safeguard the individual rights that are also a fundamental component
of liberal conceptions of democracy.
102
Those in this camp more
generally argue that a theory that accepts as legitimate the idea that a
constitution can undergo change in some way that exceeds the normal
interpretive development, but in the absence of formal amendment, is
to normalize and validate an idea that negates the very purpose of
mandating a difficult amendment procedure. This in turn undermines
the constraining nature of constitutions as the highest law of the land,
erodes the strength of constitutional provisions as pre-commitment
devices, and guts the commitment to strong constitutional rights for
individuals, and particularly for minorities.
103
Stepping back from this survey of both proponents and critics of
informal amendment, it remains difficult to distill the exact contours
of the normative claims, particularly on the issue of legitimacy. At
one end of the spectrum is Griffin, who acknowledges the existence
of informal amendments while at the same time condemning them
from a normative perspective, arguing that they constitute an
illegitimate phenomenon that arises from a paradox inherent in liberal
constitutionalism.
104
Somewhere in the middle are proponents such as
Levinson, who not only acknowledge the existence of informal
amendments as a descriptive matter, but also seem to concede that
such changes must be accepted as being legitimate after the fact, even
if they may not have been so at the time they were made. Balkin
views some such change resulting from a dialectic among branches of
government as clearly legitimate, though it is a little less clear what
his position is on the legitimacy of constitutional revolutions arising
from partisan entrenchment. He is clear that such changes should be
attacked (or defended) on the ideological level by engaging in what
he calls high politics, but that is not to say that the process of change
is itself illegitimate. At the other end of the spectrum are Ackerman
and Amar, who clearly suggest that informal amendment as they each
102. Sunstein, supra note 1, at 276-77; see also Walter Dellinger, The Legitimacy of
Constitutional Change: Rethinking the Amendment Process, 97 H
ARV. L. REV. 386, 387
(1983).
103. See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 1; Dow, supra note 1; Sunstein, supra note 1.
104. Griffin, supra note 1, at 42-43.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 461
define it is legitimate, but even here there is some uncertainty
regarding the contours. It is clear that Ackerman accepts the
legitimacy of such informal amendments ex post, once ratified by “we
the people” in an election—but it is less clear whether he accepts that
it would be legitimate for actors in either of the political branches to
self-consciously set out to deliberately circumvent the Article V
amendment process by seeking to follow the five-step process he
outlines.
Indeed, Balkin and Levinson, in their work on partisan
entrenchment, reject Ackerman’s theory in part for reasons that flow
from this normative uncertainty. They suggest that it offers very little
assistance or guidance to political actors in the midst of a potential
constitutional change, and rather “works best in hindsight.”
105
Nor,
they argue, does Ackerman’s theory help in the moment for
determining whether a “judicial adventure” such as Bush v. Gore
should be condemned as illegitimate, or acknowledged as an early
stage of a “constitutional moment.”
106
By the same token, however,
Balkin and Levinson’s theory of constitutional revolution through
partisan entrenchment contemplates a cumulative and unpredictable
process, which may involve self-conscious efforts in terms of the
appointment of ideologically committed judges, but the legitimacy of
any resulting constitutional revolution would seem to depend on
whether the revolution can be sustained through victory in the intense
high-politics debate that follows.
107
Amar would appear to come
closest to arguing that there may be some ex ante justification for
claims of informal amendment, but he places the legitimacy for such
claims squarely with “we the people” and the direct exercise of
popular sovereignty. He explicitly states that the Article V
amendment procedure is the only legitimate avenue for government
itself to amend the Constitution.
108
Amar’s approach would thus seem
to rule out any self-conscious effort by political actors within
government to initiate such an informal amendment.
The forgoing discussion has not yet answered with any
specificity where the borders between authorized change and informal
amendment may lie, what the criteria may be, or how and when
105. Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1080-81.
106. Id. at 1081.
107. Id. at 1082.
108. Amar, supra note 1, at 89-90.
462 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
legitimacy may be enjoyed by such informal amendments. Rather, it
attempts to clarify the landscape of constitutional change and helps
bring into focus the scope and importance of these questions. I will
return to again engage the questions later in the article with a view to
getting closer to the answers, particularly on the issue of legitimacy.
Thinking about whether Japan’s reinterpretation effort constitutes an
informal amendment, and on what basis we would know that, and
whether it is now or under which conditions it could be considered
legitimate, should help illuminate and sharpen our understanding of
the contours of the model and perhaps even suggest ways in which we
need to alter our thinking about informal amendment.
II. THE JAPANESE CONSTITUTIONAL REINTERPRETATION
In this Part of the article I will explain the process and substance
of the reinterpretation of Article 9 of the Constitution of Japan. In
order to understand that within the broader context of Japanese
constitutional law, however, a brief preliminary explanation of Article
9 and the Constitution itself is necessary.
A. The Constitution of Japan and Article 9
The story of the origins of the Constitution of Japan is
extraordinary, full of drama, intrigue, and sources of inspiration.
109
The current Constitution was drafted in 1946, though it was
technically promulgated as a revision of the original Meiji
Constitution of 1889, which had been modeled on the Prussian
Constitution.
110
The failure of the Meiji Constitution was viewed by
109. There is a large literature on the history of the Constitution of Japan. For my own
short account, see Craig Martin, Binding the Dogs of War: Japan and the Constitutionalizing
of Jus ad Bellum, 30 U.
PENN. J. INTL L. 267 (2008), [hereinafter Martin, Binding the Dogs of
War] which in turn is based upon R
AY A. MOORE & DONALD L. ROBINSON, PARTNERS FOR
DEMOCRACY: CRAFTING THE NEW JAPANESE STATE UNDER MACARTHUR (2002); KOSEKI
SHŌICHI, THE BIRTH OF JAPANS POSTWAR CONSTITUTION (1997); OSAMU NISHI, THE
CONSTITUTION AND THE NATIONAL DEFENSE LAW SYSTEM IN JAPAN (1987); OSAMU NISHI,
TEN DAYS INSIDE GENERAL HEADQUARTERS (GHQ): HOW THE ORIGINAL DRAFT OF THE
JAPANESE CONSTITUTION WAS WRITTEN IN 1946 (1989); THEODORE MCNELLY, THE
ORIGINS OF JAPANS DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION (2000); Charles L. Kades, The American
Role in Revising Japan’s Constitution, 104 P
OL. SCI. Q. 215 (1989).
110. The story of the drafting, operation, and failure of the Meiji Constitution is part of
the remarkable story of the constitution as a whole. See, e.g., H
IDESHIGE HARA, NIHONKOKU
KENPŌ SEITEI NO KEIFU [THE ORIGINS OF THE JAPANESE CONSTITUTION] (2004); GEORGE M.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 463
the allied powers as one of the causes of World War II, and the
United States demanded that the post-surrender Japanese government
substantially revise or replace the Meiji Constitution.
111
When the
Japanese government made little headway on the project by early
1946, MacArthur’s staff in General Head Quarters (“GHQ”) took
over the task, shortly before the United States was to lose jurisdiction
over the issue to the Far Eastern Commission.
112
MacArthur directed
that a team of young American staff members develop an entirely
new draft constitution based on four major points, two of which were
that sovereignty was to reside in the people (as opposed to the
Emperor, as it was in the Meiji Constitution), and that war and the
maintenance of armed forces were to be renounced.
113
The small
group of young military and civilian members of General Whitney’s
staff in Tokyo worked around the clock for six days (unbeknownst to
the Japanese government, the US government, or even much of the
senior staff in GHQ) to produce the first draft of what is now the
Constitution of Japan.
114
It was then presented to the Cabinet of Prime
Minister Shidehara as a fait accompli, with considerable pressure to
accept the draft as the working basis of a new constitution to replace
the Meiji Constitution.
115
After initial resistance the Japanese
government did accept the American draft, though it managed to
negotiate some changes to it in the following weeks. The draft was
then translated and made public, and then went through a year of
BECKMANN, THE MAKING OF THE MEIJI CONSTITUTION: THE OLIGARCHS AND THE
CONSTITUTIONAL DEVELOPMENT OF JAPAN 1868-1891 (1957).
111. Potsdam Declaration Defining Terms for Japanese Surrender, U.S.-P.R.C.-U.K.,
July 26, 1945, reprinted in A Decade of American Foreign Policy, Basic Documents: 1941-49,
at 49-50 (S. Comm. on Foreign Relations, Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office
1950), available at http://www.ndl.go.jp/constitution/e/etc/c06.html (last accessed Dec. 2016);
and see M
OORE & ROBINSON, supra note 109, at 28-29.
112. M
OORE & ROBINSON, supra note 109, at 74-75, 89-90.
113. The other two were that the feudal system and the nobility were to be abolished
and a British style budge system was to be adopted. See T
HREE BASIC POINTS STATED BY
SUPREME COMMANDER TO BE “MUSTS IN CONSTITUTIONAL REVISION, NATIONAL DIET
LIBRARY, available at http://www.ndl.go.jp/constitution/e/shiryo/03/072/072_002l.html (last
visited Dec. 2016) (containing the photographic image of the original memo). The original
handwritten note, thought to have been written by Gen. Whitney as dictated to by Gen.
MacArthur, has been lost. See M
CNELLY, supra note 109, at 115–116.
114. S
HŌICHI, supra note 109, at 74-76.
115. Robinson and Moore argue that MacArthur essentially threatened to put the draft
to the people for consideration, and also suggested that only if the government accepted this
draft could MacArthur’s staff stave off a possible prosecution of the Emperor for war crimes.
See M
OORE & ROBINSON, supra note 109, at 109-10.
464 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
further debate and revision within the Privy Council and each of the
two Chambers of the Diet, during which its provenance remained a
secret to the public and most members of the Diet.
116
There are recurring arguments by conservatives and nationalists
within Japan that the Constitution lacks legitimacy precisely because
it was initially written by Americans and imposed upon Japan. It is
also sometimes argued, more technically, that it is illegitimate
because it could not possibly constitute a valid “amendment” to the
Meiji Constitution, not having conformed to the amendment
procedure.
117
This is not the place to make the fully developed
counter-arguments to those claims, as the arguments are not central to
the issues here, but it is worth addressing them both briefly. On the
first point, it may be noted in passing that constitutions frequently and
indeed quite typically arise in circumstances in which the authority of
the drafters is very much in question—whether it is the aftermath of
revolution or coup, or simply an amendment conference in which the
delegates vastly exceed their mandate. As others have argued, it is not
so much the process of inception or creation that determines the
legitimacy of a constitution, as it is the process of ratification and
subsequent acceptance and valid operation of the constitutional
system.
118
On this measure, the Constitution of Japan was markedly
successful. It was not only ratified by overwhelming numbers in both
Chambers of the Diet, but it was vocally embraced by the rank and
file within the political world. The finalized document was
promulgated in 1947, and it very quickly captured the imagination
and overwhelming support of the people of Japan.
119
What is more,
Article 9 became a constitutive norm that played an enormous role in
shaping a national identity of post-war Japan that was imbued with
pacifist values.
120
As to the second point, it is probably true enough to
say that the 1947 Constitution simply replaced the Meiji Constitution,
notwithstanding the effort at the time to characterize the process as an
amendment.
116. Id.
117. Id.
118. Christohper F. Zurn, The Logic of Legitimacy: Bootstrapping Paradoxes of
Constitutional Democracy, 16 L
EGAL THEORY 191 (2010).
119. M
OORE & ROBINSON, supra note 109.
120. P
ETER J. KATZENSTEIN, CULTURAL NORMS AND NATIONAL SECURITY: POLICE
AND
MILITARY IN POSTWAR JAPAN 44 (1996); Martin, Binding the Dogs of War, supra note
109, at 284-85.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 465
Aside from Article 9, to which I will return shortly, the
Constitution of Japan conforms to many of the ideas thought typical
of the liberal democratic constitution. Notwithstanding its American
origins, it was modeled on a Westminster parliamentary system of
government, but in keeping with the ideals of its New Deal drafters it
enshrined a strong set of individual rights, and provided for a robust
power of judicial review. It provides (in Articles 97 through 99) that
the Constitution is the supreme law of the land,
121
and (in Articles 76
and 81) that the judiciary, with the Supreme Court of Japan as the
highest court, is to be both independent and charged with the
authority to interpret and enforce this supreme law.
122
The
Constitution also provides for its own entrenchment, with the sole
means of amendment laid out in Article 96, which requires that
amendment proposals be initiated in the Diet and voted for by a two-
thirds majority in each chamber, following which it must be approved
by a majority of votes cast in a referendum or election.
123
According
to well-regarded studies on the comparative difficulty of the
amendment procedures of many of the liberal democratic
constitutions of the world, the procedure in Article 96 is of average
difficulty.
124
Nonetheless, and notwithstanding considerable pressure
from some quarters at various points over the last sixty-five years, the
Constitution of Japan has never been amended. This is due to a
complex set of political dynamics both among the factions of the
Liberal Democratic Party (“LDP”), which has governed Japan for
almost sixty of the last sixty-five years, and among the LDP and the
various opposition parties. Another significant factor has been the
121. See NIHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], ch. X, arts. 97-99 (Japan).
122. See N
IHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], ch. VI, arts. 76, 81 (Japan).
123. See N
IHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], ch. IX, art. 96 (Japan).
124. See Lutz, Toward a Theory - Responding to Imperfection,
supra note 1, at 260-61.
See also Donald S. Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional Amendment, 88 A
M. POL. SCI.
REV. 355, 362-64 (1994) [hereinafter Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional Amendment];
but see Tom Ginsburg & James Melton, Does the Constitutional Amendment Rule Matter at
All?: Amendment Cultures and the Challenges of Measuring Amendment Difficulty, 14 I
NTL J.
CONST. L. 686 (2014) (arguing that there are problems with the social science literature on
amendment difficulty, and suggesting that amendment culture is more important than
amendment rules).
466 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
consistently strong public opinion opposed to any constitutional
amendment, particularly of Article 9.
125
Article 9 gives expression to the second of the four principles
initially laid down by MacArthur, and it is relatively unique in the
world as a pre-commitment device prohibiting future governments
from any involvement in war.
126
The language of Article 9 was
subject to considerable negotiation and revision, both between the
Americans and Japanese during the initial translation process, and
later during the debate and revision in the Diet. The final language in
English is as follows:
Chapter II. Renunciation of War
Article 9. Aspiring sincerely to an international peace based on
justice and order, the Japanese people forever renounce war as a
sovereign right of the nation and the threat or use of force as
means of settling international disputes.
In order to accomplish the aim of the preceding paragraph, land,
sea, and air forces, as well as other war potential, will never be
maintained. The right of belligerency of the state will not be
recognized.
127
There are three distinct elements to the provision: (i) the
renunciation of war and the threat or use of force; (ii) the prohibition
on the maintenance of armed forces or other war potential; and (iii)
the non-recognition of the rights of belligerency. The first was drawn
directly from the principles of the jus ad bellum regime in
international law, incorporating the language of the Kellogg-Briand
Pact 1928
128
and the then recently established UN Charter;
129
the
125. For one of the best explanations of these dynamics, see generally J. PATRICK
BOYD & RICHARD J. SAMUELS, NINE LIVES?: THE POLITICS OF CONSTITUTIONAL REFORM IN
JAPAN (2005).
126. There continues to be some dispute over whether the initial idea for Article 9 came
from MacArthur or Prime Minister Shidehara. Not much turns on the issue, but for reasons I
have explained elsewhere, I think the evidence strongly supports it being MacArthur. See
M
CNELLY, supra note 109, at 106-13; SHŌICHI, supra note 109, at 83-86; Martin, Binding the
Dogs of War, supra note
109, at 295 n.76.
127.
NIHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], ch. II, art. 9 (Japan).
128. See General Treaty for Renunciation of War as an Instrument of National Policy
art. 1, Aug. 27, 1928, 46 Stat. 2343, 94 L.N.T.S. 57 [hereinafter Kellogg-Briand Pact 1928],
available at http://avalon.law.yale.edu/20th_century/kbpact.asp.
129. See generally U.N. Charter, available at http://www.un.org/en/charter-united-
nations/.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 467
second was a sui generis provision that has almost no equivalent in
any other constitution;
130
and the third is a unique incorporation of
principles from the jus in bello regime aimed at buttressing the
prohibition on the use of force in the first paragraph.
131
It is the first
paragraph and the first of these elements that has operated most
effectively to constrain government policy—with the impressive
result that Japan has not been a belligerent in any armed conflict since
1945—and it is this paragraph that is the subject of the
reinterpretation effort. The second element, the prohibition on the
maintenance of armed forces, has typically attracted the most
controversy, in ways that often cloud and confuse the discourse
around Article 9, and this is no less true for the debate around the
reinterpretation. The third element is quite often ignored, and as I
have argued elsewhere, is often misunderstood.
132
My primary focus
here is what I will refer to as Article 9(1), and I will only mention the
other two elements in Article 9(2) where it is necessary to clarify the
relevant debate about the entire provision.
B. The Government Interpretation and Operation of Article 9
In order to understand the extent to which the recent
reinterpretation has diverged from the long-established understanding
of the provision, it is necessary to consider in some detail the
government interpretation of Article 9.
133
Similarly, I need to explain
a little of its history in order to respond to arguments, made recently
by some members of the LDP, that the interpretation of the provision
has changed in the past and thus the recent reinterpretation effort
should not be viewed as either unprecedented or extraordinary.
134
130. The Constitution of Costa Rica is frequently cited as being one of the only
analogues, but it differs in material respects. See C
ONSTITUCIÓN DE COSTA RICA. art. 12
(Costa Rica), unofficial English translation available at http://costaricalaw.com/costa-rica-
legal-topics/constitutional-law/costa-rica-constitution-in-english/.
131. For more on the proper analysis of this third element, see Martin, Binding the
Dogs of War, supra note 109, at 316-19.
132. Id.
133. This Section II.B is based largely on a section of my earlier work, see generally
Martin, Binding the Dogs of War, supra note 109, at 318 passim.
134. This argument was asserted by the Advisory Panel itself. See generally
A
NZENHOSHŌ NO HŌTEKIKIBAN NO KŌCHIKU NI KANSURU KONDANKAI (Japan), translated in
R
EPORT OF THE ADVISORY PANEL ON RECONSTRUCTION OF THE LEGAL BASIS FOR
SECURITY, (May 15, 2014) [hereinafter ADVISORY PANEL REPORT 2014], available at
http://www.kantei.go.jp/jp/singi/anzenhosyou2/dai7/houkoku_en.pdf. (last visited Dec. 2016).
468 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
These latter arguments are misguided, for as I will explain below, the
government interpretation of Article 9(1) has remained remarkably
consistent in its essentials since it was formally established in 1954,
very shortly after full sovereignty was restored to the country. While
there has been some shifting in the national security posture and
military capability permissible under the interpretation of Article 9(2),
it has been in ways that were made possible by the elasticity built into
the initial interpretation of the “no armed forces” element of Article
9(2), rather than being developed through any extraordinary process
resembling that which gave rise to the current reinterpretation.
The arguments that the interpretation of Article 9(1) has
previously changed are based in large part on the fact that Prime
Minister Shigeru Yoshida had, during the initial ratification process in
1946, taken the position that Japan was not necessarily denied the
right of self-defense but that the point was moot because Japan would
be denied the right to maintain even the most limited military forces
necessary for self-defense.
135
His government maintained that
position against mounting pressure both inside the party and from the
United States to begin re-arming Japan, but in 1954 he finally relented
and the force that had been established in 1950 as a National Police
Reserve was transformed into the Self-Defense Force (“SDF”).
136
For
constitutional legitimation of the move, Yoshida looked to the
Cabinet Legislation Bureau (“CLB”) for a formal interpretation of
Article 9. The CLB’s 1954 interpretation of Article 9 was the first
formal interpretation of the provision based on careful legal analysis
that had thus far been issued by any branch of government, and it was
undertaken within less than two years of the country having had full
sovereignty returned to it, and a mere seven years after the
Constitution had been promulgated. The interpretation can thus be
viewed as the establishment of the formal understanding during the
period when constitutional meaning is most dynamic and is in the
135. See MOORE & ROBINSON, supra note 109, at 212; see also NISHI, CONSTITUTION
AND THE
NATIONAL DEFENSE LAW SYSTEM IN JAPAN, supra note 109, at 5, 100–02 (quoting
Yoshida on the non-right to self-defense); cf. K
IICHIRŌ YASUZAWA, KENPŌ DAIKYŪJŌ NO
KAISHAKU
[INTERPRETATION OF ARTICLE 9 OF THE CONSTITUTION] 156, 186 (1981) (Japan)
(criticizing Yoshida’s comments and dismissing them as irrelevant).
136. For this history of the development of Japan’s SDF, see generally C
HRISTOPHER
W. HUGHES, JAPANS RE-EMERGENCE AS A ‘NORMAL MILITARY POWER (2006).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 469
process of “settling.”
137
The fact that there were differences between
this initial CLB interpretation and comments made by the Prime
Minister in the Diet during the ratification process, before the
Constitution had even been promulgated, does not amount to a
“reinterpretation” of the Constitution, and is certainly no precedent
for the current effort.
The CLB is an administrative agency attached to the Cabinet
Secretariat and has been described as having greater prestige and
greater independence than any other agency in the Japanese
government.
138
The predecessor to the CLB, established in the late
Eighteenth Century, was modeled after the French Conseil d’Êtat, and
it can also be loosely analogized to the Office of Legal Counsel in the
US Department of Justice. It performs the fundamental role of vetting
draft legislation for consistency with other laws and with the
Constitution, and from time to time pronouncing on the proper
interpretation of constitutional provisions.
139
While it has no formal
institutional authority specified in the Constitution, it has developed
enormous respect and authority over the years as an independent
agency within the government that serves as the guardian of the
Constitution.
140
Given that the Supreme Court took an increasingly
passive and hands off approach to Article 9 after 1959 (as will be
discussed further below), the CLB increasingly took on the role as the
137. See, e.g., Strauss, supra note 1, at 1460 (“[A] constitutional system is first getting
underway and making its shakedown voyage, so to speak, amendments are more properly seen
as part of the initial establishment of the regime, rather than as a means of changing it.”).
138. See Richard J. Samuels, Politics, Security Policy, and Japan’s Cabinet Legislation
Bureau: Who Elected These Guys Anyway? 2 (Japanese Pol’y Res. Inst., Working Paper No.
99, 2004),
http://www.jpri.org/publications/workingpapers/wp99.html (last visited Dec. 2016).
139. The Legislation Bureau had been disbanded by SCAP in 1947 but was restored
as the CLB by Yoshida in 1952. See S
HINICHI NISHIKAWA, SHIRAREZARU KANCHŌ: NAIKAKU
HŌSEIKYOKU
[THE UNKNOWN AGENCY: THE CABINET LEGISLATION BUREAU] ch. 2 (2000)
(Japan) [hereinafter N
ISHIKAWA, THE UNKNOWN AGENCY]; see also AKIRA NAKAMURA,
S
ENGOSEIJI NI YURETA KENPŌ KYŪJŌ NAIKAKU HŌSIEKYOKU NO JISHIN TSUYŌSA [ARTICLE 9 OF
THE
CONSTITUTION ROCKED BY POST WAR POLITICS: THE STRENGTH AND SELF-
C
ONFIDENCE OF THE CABINET LEGISLATION BUREAU] ch. 1 (1996) (Japan); Samuels, supra
note 138, at 3.
140. More recently, see generally S
HINICHI NISHIKAWA, KOREDE WAKATTA! NAIKAKU
HŌSEIKYOKU [HERE UNDERSTOOD! THE CABINET LEGISLATION BUREAU] (2013) (Japan)
[hereinafter N
ISHIKAWA, HERE UNDERSTOOD]; MASAHIRO SAKATA, HŌ NO BANJIN: NAIKAKU
HŌSEIKYOKU NO KYŌJI: KAISHYAKU KAIKEN GA YURUSANAI RIYŪ [THE LAWS GATEKEEPER
THE DIGNITY OF THE CABINET LEGISLATION BUREAU: REASONS WHY THE
REINTERPRETATION IS UNACCEPTABLE] (2014) (Japan).
470 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
primary authority for the interpretation of Article 9, arbiter of what
was consistent with that interpretation, and at times enforcer of the
provision.
141
Turning to the content of the 1954 CLB interpretation, it
provided that while Article 9(1) renounced war and the threat or use
of force as a means of settling international disputes, it was not
understood to renounce Japan’s inherent and sovereign right under
international law to use force in the individual self-defense of Japan.
Moreover, it was only natural for a country with such a right of self-
defense to have the capability necessary to defend its national
territory in the event that it came under foreign attack. Thus it
followed that Article 9(2) was not to be understood to prohibit the
maintenance of the defensive capability “necessary” for such
individual self-defense. Therefore, such “necessary” defense
capability, which would comprise the new SDF, would not be
understood to constitute the “land, sea, and air forces or other war
potential” that was prohibited by Article 9(2).
142
Put another way, the
armed forces or other war potential prohibited by Article 9(2) was
interpreted as being armed forces or weapons in excess of that which
was necessary for individual self-defense. In 1957, the CLB refined
and narrowed the interpretation further, opining that a defense
capability that constituted “the minimum necessary force” for the
exercise of self-defense was not the kind of war potential prohibited
141. See, e.g., NAKAMURA, supra note 139, at 3-6 (discussing the power and authority
of the CLB), at 11-18 (discussing the independence of the CLB), and at 32-34 (arguing that the
courts’ avoidance of Article 9 enforcement has made the CLB role that much more important);
N
ISHIKAWA, THE UNKNOWN AGENCY, supra note 139, at ch. 2 (detailing the CLB’s role in
interpreting Article 9, and arguing that its interpretations have constrained policy on the issue
of collective self-defense and troop deployment); John O. Haley, Waging War: Japan’s
Constitutional Constraints, 14 C
ONST. F. 18, 19, 21, 23, 28-29 (2005) (arguing that the stance
of the judiciary on Article 9 opened the way for the CLB to become the principal authority on
the question, and that the CLB has imposed a “lasting and politically effective constitutional
constraint” on Japanese defense policy). See also B
OYD & SAMUELS, supra note 125, at 51
(discussing the power of the CLB in vetting legislation, and its power vis-à-vis other
ministries); Samuels, supra note 138, at 4 (similarly arguing that the CLB filled the void left
by the Courts). On enforcement, see Samuels, supra
note 138, at 8-9 (noting the role of the
CLB in the government decision not to participate in the Gulf War in 1991).
142. This interpretation was provided by Director Hayashi in the House of
Representatives Budget Committee deliberations, on December 21, 1954. See N
ISHIKAWA,
T
HE UNKNOWN AGENCY, supra note 139, at 40; see also BOYD & SAMUELS, supra note 125,
at 5, 24-29 (tracing the development of the “minimum necessary force” doctrine).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 471
by Article 9(2).
143
Japan was entitled to both maintain and to use the
“minimum necessary force” for individual self-defense.
The CLB interpretation of 1954 was extremely significant in
terms of the constraints that it entrenched under Article 9(1). Though
it defined what was permissible in the form of individual self-defense,
the interpretation also made clear what was not permissible, namely
collective self-defense and collective security operations.
144
This is a
crucial point that rests on distinctions between the different bases for
the legitimate use of force in the modern jus ad bellum regime of
international law. The language of Article 9 was drawn from the
prohibition against the threat or use of force provided for in Article
2(4) of the UN Charter. There are three exceptions to this broad
prohibition. The first two, provided for in Article 51 of the Charter,
are the right to use force for individual or collective self-defense,
while the third is the use of force authorized by a resolution of the UN
Security Council to restore or maintain international peace and
security, as authorized under Articles 39 and 42 of the Charter.
145
While the two forms of self-defense are provided for in the same
Article of the UN Charter, there are important differences between
them, particularly for purposes of the interpretation of Article 9. The
right of individual self-defense permits the use of force by a State to
defend itself in the face of an armed attack against it by some
aggressor. The right of collective self-defense permits a State to use
force, alone or with others, to assist some other State that has been the
victim of armed attack by some other aggressor, and has requested
143. Prime Minister Kishi provided this interpretation in the House of Councilors
Cabinet Committee on May 7, 1957. See N
ISHIKAWA, THE UNKNOWN AGENCY, supra note
139, at 41, and N
ISHIKAWA, HERE UNDERSTOOD, supra note 140, at 48-51.
144. N
ISHIKAWA, THE UNKNOWN AGENCY, supra note 139, at 46, NISHIKAWA, HERE
UNDERSTOOD, supra note 140, at 63-66, SAKATA, THE LAWS GATEKEEPERS, supra note 140,
at 145-46 and 155-56, and Samuels, supra note 138, at 5; also see Haley, Waging War:
Japan’s Constitutional Constraints, supra note 141, at 29-33 (noting that the “prevailing view”
[is that] Article 9 prohibits any deployment of combat forces for collective security measures
in the absence of a direct threat to Japanese security.”
145. In international law these are typically characterized as being two exceptions—the
right of individual and collective self-defense being one, and collective security operations
being the second—but there are differences between individual and collective self-defense,
and given the importance of those differences for purposes of Article 9, I am here
characterizing them as three distinct exceptions. See generally
YORAM DINSTEIN, WAR,
AGGRESSION AND SELF-DEFENCE (2005); CHRISTINE GRAY, INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE
USE OF FORCE (2004); and for my own analysis of Article 9 from an international law
perspective, see Martin, Binding the Dogs of War, supra note
109, at 309 passim.
472 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
assistance.
146
The use of force in either collective self-defense or for
purposes of collective security operations authorized by the UN
Security Council is part of the collective security system developed as
part of the UN system. The CLB interpretation made clear that Article
9(1) renounced, as sovereign rights of the nation, and thus prohibited,
the use of force for either of these collective security purposes.
Indeed, for many years this interpretation operated to effectively
constrain SDF participation in even those UN peacekeeping
operations that were not conducted under Chapter VII authority,
which are not typically understood to constitute a use of force under
international law.
147
It will be noted that while the interpretation of Article 9(1)
articulated a fairly clear rule (namely, no use of force except for
individual self-defense), the interpretation of Article 9(2) created a
rather vague and relative standard for what was a permissible size and
capability of the armed forces, constituting a sliding scale that
required reference to external threat levels. The CLB justification for
the establishment and maintenance of the SDF has long been assailed
by scholars inside and outside Japan as being contrary to the purpose
and text of the Article 9(2) prohibition on the maintenance of armed
forces.
148
Moreover, the relative nature of the standard is what made
possible the several changes in defense posture over the years, which
defenders of the current reinterpretation now claim constituted
previous “reinterpretations” of Article 9.
149
146. See generally DINSTEIN, supra note 145; GRAY, supra note 145; and for my own
analysis of Article 9 from an international law perspective, see Martin, Binding the Dogs of
War, supra note
109, at 309 passim.
147. For more on the relationship between Japan’s participation in UN peacekeeping
and Article 9, see, e.g., Caroline Rose, Japanese Role in PKO and Humanitarian Assistance,
in J
APANESE FOREIGN POLICY TODAY: A READER 122, 124 (Takashi Inoguchi & Purnendra
Jain eds., 2000). See also Y
OSHIO HIROSE, KOKUREN NO HEIWAIJI KATSUDOKOKUSAIHŌ TO
KENPŌ NO SHIZA KARA
[U.N. Peacekeeping Activity: From the Perspective of International Law
and the Constitution] (1992) (Japan).
148. For the discussion in English, see Kenneth L. Port, Article 9 of the Japanese
Constitution and the Rule of Law, 13 C
ARDOZO J. INTL & COMP. L. 127, 128 (2005). See also
James E. Auer, Article Nine: Renunciation of War, in J
APANESE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 69,
74-80 (Percy R. Luney, Jr. & Kazuyuki Takahashi eds., 1993) (outlining the political process
by which Article 9(2) was reinterpreted). There is a massive body of literature in Japanese
criticizing the interpretation and government policy on Article 9(2).
149. For an examination of and response to these arguments, see N
ISHIKAWA, HERE
UNDERSTOOD, supra note 140, at 132-47.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 473
While debate has raged for decades over what, precisely, a
“minimum necessary force” might mean in practical terms, and
whether the SDF has exceeded it, the fact remains that the CLB has
been remarkably consistent in its adherence to the fundamental
interpretation of the “use of force” aspect of its understanding of
Article 9. While there has been some whittling away of the policy
limitations once imposed on the overseas dispatch of troops for UN
peacekeeping operations, and the conditions under which Japan might
be able to provide rear-area support to the United States in crisis
circumstances in “areas surrounding Japan,”
150
the fundamental
prohibition on participation in collective self-defense or UN
authorized collective security operations has been assiduously
maintained.
151
Even when the limitations were relaxed with respect to
the dispatch of troops for UN peacekeeping missions, and to provide
logistical support for such operations as the post-9/11 coalition
activities in Afghanistan and Iraq, stringent conditions on SDF
operations were designed and implemented to keep their conduct
within the scope of the broader constitutional interpretation.
152
What is more, this interpretation has operated to constrain
policy. The fact that Japan has not engaged in the use of force since
World War II—a feat that is almost unique among the major
industrial nations—was not the result of mere policy choice or
preference. Article 9(1) has operated in precisely the manner for
which pre-commitment devices are designed, effectively constraining
government policy and preventing the use of force, even in perceived
crisis conditions when the government was under great pressure to
participate in international collective security operations. The most
famous and clear illustration of this was when the Kaifu
administration was under enormous pressure from the Administration
of George H.W. Bush and the US Congress to contribute troops to the
international effort to drive Iraqi forces from Kuwait in the Gulf War
150. The “rear-area support” and “situations in areas surrounding Japan” are concepts
articulated in the 1997 Guidelines, which are discussed in the text associated with notes 194,
infra.
151. The CLB reinforced its interpretation in 1981, explicitly stating that participation
in collective self-defense was prohibited by Article 9(1). See B
OYD & SAMUELS, supra note
125, at 30-33 (providing a more complete account of the CLB interpretation). See also
S
AKATA, supra note 140, at ch. 3.
152. For details on these operations and the limits thereon, see Martin, Binding the
Dogs of War, supra note 109, at 321 passim.
474 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
of 1991.
153
The government was inclined to accede to US requests,
until the Director of the CLB informed Prime Minister Kaifu that any
such participation would be a violation of the Article 9(1) prohibition
against the use of force for anything other than individual self-
defense. There was a growing sense of crisis within the Japanese
government, with the view that failure to participate would do
irreparable harm to the alliance with the United States, but the
government nonetheless respected the CLB view and complied with
the understood constitutional limits.
154
Regardless of whether one
views this constraint on policy to have been in the national interest,
the evidence is fairly clear that it was effective.
Factions within the ruling LDP have sought for decades to
amend Article 9. This has proved impossible for complex political
reasons involving both dynamics among factions within the party and
among the LDP and the opposition parties, as well as enduring public
resistance to the idea.
155
The myth has thus arisen that the formal
amendment procedure in the Constitution is simply too difficult, and
that other means of revision are thus justified.
156
But as mentioned
previously, the comparative analysis of the relative difficulty of
constitutional amendment procedures indicates that, at least as a
structural matter, the Constitution of Japan is merely average.
157
The
constitutions of several countries, such as the United States and
Germany, are significantly more difficult to amend,
158
and have
nonetheless been formally amended many times. That said, the
153. There are differences of opinion among international law scholars whether this
operation constituted an exercise of collective self-defense under Article 51 or a collective
security operation authorized by Article 42, or both—but it was certainly at least one of these.
See, e.g., D
INSTEIN, supra note 145, at 273-77 (arguing that it was an act of collective self-
defense) and T
HOMAS M. FRANCK, RECOURSE TO FORCE: STATE ACTION AGAINST THREATS
AND
ARMED ATTACKS 24-30 (2002) (arguing that it was an instance of collective security
authorized under Article 42).
154. See generally K
ENNETH B. PYLE, JAPAN RISING: THE RESURGENCE OF JAPANESE
POWER AND PURPOSE (2007); Martin, Binding the Dogs of War, supra note 109, at 343
passim, relying on K
AZUHIKO TOGO, JAPANS FOREIGN POLICY 1945-2003 (2d ed. 2005);
Samuels, supra note 138.
155. See generally B
OYD & SAMUELS, supra note 125.
156. See generally G
LENN D. HOOK & GAVAN MCCORMACK, JAPANS CONTESTED
CONSTITUTION: DOCUMENTS AND ANALYSIS (2001).
157. See Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional Amendment, supra note 124.
158. See id.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 475
Constitution of Japan has never been amended in its almost seventy
years of existence, and as such is a significant outlier.
159
C. The Process of Reinterpretation
Prime Minister Shinzō Abe, beginning during his first term as
prime minister in 2007, decided to make revision of Article 9 one of
his primary objectives.
160
He paid lip service to the ongoing efforts to
formally amend the provision in accordance with the procedure laid
out in Article 96 of the Constitution, but he also set out to circumvent
and subvert that legitimate procedure if necessary. He lay the
foundation for a “reinterpretation” process by establishing an ad hoc
Advisory Panel on the Reconstruction of the Legal Basis for Security
(the “Advisory Panel”, also known as the “Yanai Committee”, named
after its chairman Shunji Yanai).
161
This was a group of experts in
fields from international relations and diplomacy to international law,
but nonetheless contained few lawyers, and only one constitutional
scholar.
162
It was argued in the media that members of the panel were
primarily selected for their hawkish views on national security.
163
It
was given a mandate to provide recommendations on how, not
whether, Article 9 should be reinterpreted.
164
Before it could finish its
work, however, Abe had to resign on grounds of ill health, and his
successor quietly shelved the first report of the Advisory Panel.
Efforts at constitutional revision of any kind were put on hold.
159. See generally GINSBURG ET AL., supra note 1.
160. Consistent with the vision of the country he laid out in his 2006 book: S
HINZŌ
ABE, UTSUKUSHII KUNI HE [Towards a Beautiful Country: My Vision for Japan] (2006).
161. Abe Shapes Agenda for Defense Panel, A
SAHI SHIMBUN, May 19, 2007.
162. A list of the members can be found at the back of the 2008 report of the
committee. See T
HE ADVISORY PANEL ON RECONSTRUCTION OF THE LEGAL BASIS FOR
SECURITY, REPORT OF THE ADVISORY PANEL ON RECONSTRUCTION OF THE LEGAL BASIS
FOR
SECURITY (June 24, 2008) [hereinafter ADVISORY PANEL REPORT, 2008],
http://www.kantei.go.jp/jp/singi/anzenhosyou/report.pdf (last visited Dec. 2016).
163. Abe’s Panel on Defense Dominated by Hawks, JAPAN TIMES, May 6, 2007,
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2007/05/06/national/abes-panel-on-defense-dominated-by-
hawks/ (last visited Dec. 2016).
164. Yanai Committee Mandate, Order of the Prime Minister, April 17, 2007.
http://www.kantei.go.jp/jp/singi/anzenhosyou/konkyo.pdf. In 2007 I published an essay critical
of the effort to then “revise” the interpretation of Article 9. See Craig Martin, The Case
Against Revising Interpretations of the Japanese Constitution, 5:5 A
SIA-PACIFIC J.: JAPAN
FOCUS, May 2007, http://apjjf.org/-Craig-Martin/2434/article.pdf (last visited Dec. 2016).
476 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
Upon returning to power in 2012, Abe immediately revived his
efforts to change Article 9. The LDP published a proposal for the
amendment of the Constitution, which included extensive revisions to
not only Article 9, but individual rights and various other aspects of
the Constitution.
165
He also revived the Advisory Panel and gave it a
renewed and broadened mandate to update its prior report.
166
When it
soon became apparent that amendment of Article 9 would again prove
too difficult, Abe proposed to first amend only the amending formula
in Article 96 itself, so as to make amendment of the Constitution
possible with a bare majority vote in each chamber of the Diet, and
approval by a majority of votes cast in a referendum.
167
This move
was quite transparently made for the purpose of laying the foundation
for then more easily amending Article 9. The proposal was heavily
criticized by Japanese scholars, as it would have had the effect of
undermining the Constitution’s status as the supreme law, and its
ability to provide effective constraints on government power.
168
While
it still lingers in the background of government constitutional
commentary, the effort was shelved in 2013 as a result of the
opposition, and Abe reverted to the plan-B of orchestrating a
165. JIMINTŌ, KENPŌ KAISEI SŌAN [LIBERAL DEMOCRATIC PARTY, CONSTITUTIONAL
AMENDMENT PROPOSAL], 2012, http://constitution.jimin.jp/draft/. For a more extensive Q&A
document explaining the proposal, see J
IMINTŌ, NIHONKOKU KENPŌ KAISEI SOAN Q&A,
[LIBERAL DEMOCRATIC PARTY, JAPANS CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT PROPOSAL Q&A],
https://www.jimin.jp/policy/pamphlet/pdf/kenpou_qa.pdf. For my essay analyzing the
proposal, see Craig Martin, LDP’s Dangerous Proposals for Amending Antiwar Article, J
APAN
TIMES (June 6, 2012), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/opinion/2012/06/06/opinion/ldps-
dangerous-proposals-for-amending-antiwar-article/, and a more recent article, Craig Martin,
Change it to Save it: Why and How to Amend Article 9, 17 R
ITSUMEIKAN J. PEACE STUD.
(forthcoming 2017), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2883588; see also
Lawrence Repeta, Japan’s Democracy at Risk – The LDP’s Ten Most Dangerous Proposals
for Constitutional Change, 11:28 A
SIA-PACIFIC J.: JAPAN FOCUS, July 2013,
http://apjjf.org/2013/11/28/Lawrence-Repeta/3969/article.html.
166. Mizuho Aoki, Clearing the Way for Wider Military Role, T
HE JAPAN TIMES, Aug.
19, 2013, http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2013/08/19/reference/clearing-way-for-wider-
military-role/ (last visited Dec. 2016); all the documents of the re-constituted ad-hoc Advisory
Panel can be found on the webpage of the Kantei: http://www.kantei.go.jp/jp
/singi/anzenhosyou2/index.html.
167. Jiji, Article 96 Invites Sent Out to Ishin, Your Party, J
APAN TIMES (May 5, 2013),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2013/05/05/national/politics-diplomacy/article-96-invites-
sent-out-to-ishin-your-party/#.VeZjGdNVhBc.
168. Back to the Future: Shinzo Abe’s Plan to Re-Write Japan’s Constitution is
Running Into Trouble, E
CONOMIST, June 1, 2013, http://www.economist.com/news/asia/
21578712-shinzo-abes-plan-rewrite-japans-constitution-running-trouble-back-future.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 477
reinterpretation of Article 9. The work of the Advisory Panel thus
took center stage.
While the Advisory Panel got back to work, Prime Minister Abe
made one more move to lay the foundation for his reinterpretation
efforts. In 2013, he asked for the resignation of the Director of the
CLB and replaced him with the political appointment of an outsider, a
diplomat from the Foreign Ministry named Ichiro Komatsu.
169
This
was an unprecedented departure from a long-standing convention of
appointing legal experts from within the ranks of CLB, and
sometimes from among former Supreme Court Judges or from within
the Ministry of Justice.
170
The appointment of Komatsu, who was
known to be a supporter of the reinterpretation efforts, was criticized
by many at the time as being a cynical and transparent effort to pre-
empt any possible challenge the CLB might have otherwise made to
the constitutionality of the planned reinterpretation.
171
As it turned
out, Komatsu himself had to resign in 2014 due to ill health, but it is
thought that he had by then done the important work of laying the
groundwork for acceptance of the reinterpretation. Many prominent
Japanese scholars have argued that the political interference not only
broke the CLB’s potential resistance on this particular issue, but has
grievously weakened and undermined the integrity of the institution
within the constitutional system as a whole.
172
The Advisory Panel, now under the effective leadership of
Shinichi Kitaoka, submitted a revised and updated final report in
May, 2014.
173
As will be discussed in more detail below, this ad-hoc
committee was an extra-constitutional body with no authority
whatsoever to engage in constitutional interpretation, but was formed
to provide a veneer of authority and legitimacy for subsequent
executive moves to effect a reinterpretation of Article 9. On the basis
169. Abe to Pick Backer of Collective Self-Defense as Head of Legislation Bureau,
A
SAHI SHIMBUN (Aug. 2, 2013).
170. Abe to Pick Backer of Collective Self-Defense, supra note 169. For detailed
discussion of the convention and criticism of the appointment by Abe, see N
ISHIKAWA, HERE
UNDERSTOOD!, supra note 140, ch. 2.
171. Abe’s Personnel Move Could Hamper Constitutional Debate, A
SAHI SHIMBUN
(Aug. 3, 2013); See also N
ISHIKAWA, HERE UNDERSTOOD!, supra note 140, ch 2.
172. Yasuo Hasebe, The End of Constitutional Pacifism? (Aug. 12, 2016) (unpublished
manuscript, presented at the University of New South Wales Faculty of Law) (on file with
author); See also N
ISHIKAWA, HERE UNDERSTOOD, supra note 140, ch. 2.
173. T
HE ADVISORY PANEL REPORT 2014, supra note 134.
478 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
of the “recommendations” of the Advisory Panel (though, to be fair,
not implementing all of its recommendations), the Cabinet in July
2014 passed a resolution as the mechanism for purporting to
unilaterally change the meaning of Article 9.
174
This “Cabinet
Decision” provided both the rationale for a reinterpretation of the
provision, and an outline for how key legislation would be revised to
facilitate and enable an expanded national security posture. The
rationale for the reinterpretation was essentially that which had been
provided by the Advisory Panel, namely that the strategic
environment around Japan had become more threatening, and that the
government’s obligation to guarantee the security of the Japanese
people required a more robust national security posture, and
particularly the development of a more proactive role within the US-
Japan security arrangements.
175
In short, it was a transparently result-
oriented argument that the situation had changed so as to require
greater latitude in the use of military force, and therefore the meaning
of Article 9 must be deemed to have changed in a manner that would
allow such a use of force. The Cabinet Decision laid out three basic
categories of policy for which legislation would be developed to
achieve the new policy objectives, and for which a new interpretation
of Article 9 would be required. In order to later assess the
constitutionality of the reinterpretation, these must be examined here
in some detail.
The first category related to the use of the SDF in response to
“an infringement that does not amount to an armed attack.” Such use
of the military is to be permitted in “situations that are neither pure
peacetime nor contingencies.” The word “contingencies” is taken
from the formal Cabinet translation of the Cabinet Decision, but it
represents the word yūji in Japanese, which might be better translated
as “emergency”, though in this context the word would appear to have
a meaning that is closer to “hostilities” or “armed conflict”. As an
aside, this is merely one example of the incredibly euphemistic
terminology, in both languages, that is employed in both the Cabinet
Decision and the U.S-Japan Guidelines (which will be examined
further below), such that one might suspect it is quite deliberately
174. CABINET DECISION, supra note 24.
175. Id. at 2.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 479
designed to obfuscate.
176
But returning to the substance of this change
articulated in the Cabinet Decision, it provides that the use of force in
circumstances that do not involve an armed attack would include
responses to “infringements” that occur in the areas “surrounding
remote islands”, and in circumstances in which the police are not able
to effectively respond.
177
It is likely that this policy change is
precisely to provide authority to use force in response to any Chinese
encroachments in the area of such islands as the Senkaku chain, over
which China and Japan have ongoing territorial disputes.
178
This
section of the Cabinet Decision also provides that Japan could use
force to provide assistance to US forces that had come under attack
while engaged in activities which contribute to the defense of Japan,
but not necessarily in the territory of Japan.
179
The second category of policy for which new legislation would
be required, according to the Cabinet Decision, is to further Japan’s
contributions to “the peace and stability of the international
community.”
180
This policy development is to permit an expansion of
the scope and nature of logistical and rear-area support to foreign
armed forces engaged in hostilities.
181
Japan has in the past imposed
stringent limits on such support, with the view that extensive
logistical support and transport assistance for the armed forces of
belligerents may be deemed “integral” to the use of force by such
foreign armed forces, and thus prohibited by Article 9. Indeed, in a
notorious decision in 2008 the Nagoya High Court opined (in what
was extensive obiter dicta, in a judgment that ultimately dismissed
the claim of the applicants for lack of standing) that Japanese support
for coalition forces during the belligerent occupation of Iraq
176. This is not a new phenomenon. The 1997 Guidelines themselves were also
excessively and deliberately ambiguous, leading to controversy when the Japanese
Government insisted that the phrase “situations surrounding Japan” was not actually
geographic in nature, and thus did not impose any geographic limit on SDF support operations.
The 1997 Guidelines are described in more detail below. See infra note 194 and accompanying
text.
177. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, at 3.
178. See, e.g., Ryan Scoville, A Defense of Japanese Sovereignty Over the
Senkaku/Diayu Islands, 46 G
EO. WASH. INTL L. R. 571 (2014).
179. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, at 2. Depending on the exact circumstances
this would be more likely an exercise of collective self-defense (which is addressed later in the
Cabinet Decision), rather than a response to infringements not amounting to an armed attack.
180. Id. at 3.
181. See id.
480 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
beginning in 2005, constituted action that was integral to the use of
force by coalition forces and was thus a violation of Article 9.
182
The
Cabinet Decision purported to revise the interpretation of these limits,
and particularly this concept of integration with the use of force by
other belligerents to an armed conflict (known in Japanese as the
ittaika” doctrine). Under the new revised understanding, Japanese
support for the armed forces of other countries would only constitute
an integral component of their use of force if the support was
provided directly to foreign armed forces actually operating in active
theatres of combat. Providing such support for armed forces behind
the lines, or on their way to the theatre of conflict, would not
constitute a use of force under the new interpretation.
183
The third category in the Cabinet Decision, the “Measures for
Self-Defense Permitted under Article 9”, was the most controversial.
Noting that “sufficient responses would not necessarily be possible if
the constitutional interpretation to date were maintained,” the Cabinet
Decision purported to expand the scope of Article 9 to permit the use
of force in the exercise of the right of collective self-defense.
184
This,
of course, makes permissible a form of use of force that was precisely
understood to be prohibited under the long-standing interpretation of
Article 9. The Cabinet Decision made some effort to justify this move
in constitutional terms, by reference to the preamble and Article 13 of
the Constitution. The preamble refers to the “right to live in peace”,
and Article 13 provides that the people’s “right to life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness shall, to the extent that it does not interfere with
the public welfare, be the supreme consideration in legislation and
other governmental affairs.”
185
Thus, the Cabinet Decision argued,
“Article 9 cannot possibly be interpreted to prohibit Japan from taking
measures of self-defense necessary to maintain its peace and security
and to ensure its survival.”
186
It suggested that the only change now
was that collective self-defense was deemed necessary, in some
182. See Nagoya High Court, 2056 Hanrei-jiho 74 (2008), available at
http://www.haheisashidome.jp/hanketsu_kouso [hereinafter Nagoya Decision], a translation of
which is available in Hudson Hamilton, Mōri v. Japan: The Nagoya High Court Recognizes
the Right to Live in Peace, 19:3 P
ACIFIC RIM L. & POL. J. 549 (2010), http://papers.ssrn.com/
sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1767658.
183. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, at 4.
184. Id. at 6.
185. N
IHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], ch. III, art. 13 (Japan).
186. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, at 7.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 481
circumstances, to maintain peace and security, ensure the survival of
Japan, and preserve the people’s right to life, liberty and pursuit of
happiness.
187
In accordance with this logic, however, the government
developed a concept of collective self-defense that is quite different in
scope and contour from the understanding of the concept in
international law. The Cabinet Decision qualified the concept by
adding certain conditions precedent and apparent limitations, thus
creating a sui generis concept of collective self-defense for the
purpose of the reinterpreted substance of Article 9. Indeed, the
Cabinet Decision explicitly stated that “a legal basis in international
law and constitutional interpretation need to be understood
separately.”
188
Thus, the use of force in the exercise of this sui generis
right of collective self-defense is only permissible in circumstances in
which there has been an armed attack against “a foreign country that
is in a close relationship with Japan,” and when such an attack is one
that “threatens Japan’s survival and poses a clear danger to
fundamentally overturn [the] people’s right to life, liberty and pursuit
of happiness, and when there is no other appropriate means available
to repel the attack.”
189
The Cabinet Decision also noted that the use of
force in response must be the minimum necessary for the defense of
Japan. Finally, it specified that the enabling legislation would include
the condition that “in principle” the Diet should be required to
approve any such use of force.
190
These limits were subsequently
articulated by the government as constituting three clear and distinct
conditions precedent to the use of force for collective self-defense,
namely: (i) an armed attack on a country with close relations to Japan,
and such attack poses a threat to Japan’s survival and the rights of the
people to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness; (ii) there is no
other means available to protect against the threat to Japan and its
people; and (iii) the use of force is the minimum necessary for such
defense and proportionate to the threat.
191
187. Id.
188. Id. at 8.
189. Id. at 6-8.
190. Id. at 8.
191. See, e.g., Sachiko Miwa, Diet Debate on Security Bills Starts with Confusion Over
Limits on Collective Self-Defense, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (May 26, 2015).
482 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
This limitation of the use of force to situations in which Japan or
its people are threatened by the attack on a foreign state was, it has
been suggested by government representatives, designed to make for
a narrower or more limited concept than the right of collective self-
defense under international law. The latter, of course, permits the use
of force against an aggressor that has attacked a third country,
regardless of any threat posed to the state using force under this
justification, or the nature of the relationship between the victim and
the country exercising the right.
192
But how the government’s new
conception of collective self-defense would operate in practice is
unclear at best, and indeed the actual intent of the language itself is
far from clear. Would armed attack against an ally have to pose a
threat to both the survival of Japan and the people’s right to life,
liberty and the pursuit of happiness, or would a threat to the people’s
rights be sufficient to trigger the right to use force? If so, how would
the standard be defined and applied in practical terms? The Prime
Minister has made comments that suggest just such a “disconnection”
of the conditions, and I will return to these questions below when the
examination turns to the enabling legislation, and to the analysis of
how the constitutionality of the reinterpretation should be assessed.
193
Such was the Cabinet Decision itself. Next, in April 2015, prior
to tabling any draft legislation or providing any other opportunity for
debate on the reinterpretation issues in the Diet, the Abe government
moved to commit the country to these policy changes in an
international agreement. The government entered into talks with the
US for the purpose of revising the formal guidelines that flesh out the
mutual obligations, expectations, and responsibilities under the US-
Japan Security Treaty. The existing Guidelines for Japan-US Defense
Cooperation, as the agreement is titled, was agreed to in 1997 (the
“1997 Guidelines”), and reflected a shared understanding regarding
the limitations on Japan’s ability to use force, provide logistical
support or deploy the SDF in accordance with treaty obligations.
194
192. Blurry Limits on SDF Missions, JAPAN TIMES, (Apr. 24, 2015),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/opinion/2015/04/24/editorials/blurry-limits-sdf-missions/#.VO-
nTKZOqA; Sachiko Miwa, Conditions for Exercising Right to Collective Self-Defense Open to
Interpretation, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (May 12, 2015).
193. See infra Section III.A.
194. A
MERICAN SOCIETY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW, JAPAN-UNITED STATES: JOINT
STATEMENT ON REVIEW OF DEFENSE COOPERATION GUIDELINES AND DEFENSE
COOPERATION GUIDELINES 1621-38 (1997) [hereinafter 1997 GUIDELINES]. These were a
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 483
The April 2015 talks led to an agreement, the 2015 Guidelines, which
was finalized without any Diet deliberation, and which reflected a
marked expansion of the limitations in the 1997 Guidelines.
195
The 2015 Guidelines pay lip-service to the idea that the
fundamental rights and obligations under the treaty remained
unchanged, that no legislation is required to implement the
agreement, and that all actions and activities undertaken by Japan
would be consistent with the Japanese Constitution.
196
Yet it was later
revealed that during the talks senior Japanese military officials
advised their US counterparts that the government could guarantee
that the Cabinet Decision and the 2015 Guidelines would be
implemented in the form of legislation that would be enacted in the
coming summer.
197
Moreover, in the details of the agreement, the
revised Guidelines actually reflect the expanded scope and role of the
SDF articulated in the Cabinet Decision, stipulating that Japan may
use force in response to infringements that do not involve an armed
attack on Japan,
198
and that Japan and the US could cooperate in
anticipatory self-defense, in response to either an imminent attack on
Japan,
199
or indeed any “situation that will have an important
successor agreement to a set of guidelines agreed to in 1978. For more on the 1997 Guidelines
generally, see T
OGO, supra note 154, at 80-85; HUGHES, supra note 136, at 100-01; THOMAS
A. DROHAN, AMERICAN-JAPANESE SECURITY AGREEMENTS, PAST AND PRESENT 143-51
(2007). For more detailed analysis of the legal significance of the 1997 Guidelines see, e.g.,
Robert A. Fisher, The Erosion of Japanese Pacifism: The Constitutionality of the 1997 U.S.-
Japan Defense Guidelines, 32 C
ORNELL INTL L.J. 393, 395-96 (1999); NICHIBEI
SHINGAIDORAIN TO SHUHEN JITAIHŌ
[JAPAN-U.S. NEW GUIDELINES AND THE SURROUNDING
SITUATIONS LAW] (Yamauchi Toshihiro ed., 1999); MOTOAKI HATAKE, KENPŌ 9 JŌ: KENKYŪ
TO GIRON NO SAIZENSEN
[ARTICLE 9 OF THE CONSTITUTION: THE VANGUARD ON RESEARCH
AND ARGUMENTS
], 129 (2006). SHIGENOBU TAMURA, et al., NIHON NO BŌEIHŌSEI [THE
NATIONAL DEFENSE LEGAL SYSTEM OF JAPAN] (2008), ch. 10.
195. J
APAN MINISTRY OF DEFENSE, THE GUIDELINES FOR JAPAN-U.S. DEFENSE
COOPERATION (2015), http://www.mod.go.jp/e/d_act/anpo/shishin_20150427e.html
[hereinafter 2015
GUIDELINES].
196. Id. at 2.
197. SDF Chief Told U.S. Late Last Year That Security Bills Would Pass This Summer,
A
SAHI SHIMBUN (Sept. 3, 2015).
198. 2015
GUIDELINES, supra note 195, at 4 (stating that “In this increasingly complex
security environment, the two governments will take measures to ensure Japan’s peace and
security in all phases, seamlessly, from peacetime to contingencies, including situations when
an armed attack against Japan is not involved.” In light of the Cabinet Decision, “taking
measures” would include the use of force).
199. Id. at 9-10.
484 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
influence on Japan’s peace and security.”
200
The 2015 Guidelines also
commit Japan to conducting bilateral operations to “secure the safety
of sea lines of communication,”
201
and quite explicitly eliminate any
geographic limits (which had been controversially ambiguous in the
1997 Guidelines). The 2015 Guidelines also clearly reflect and
operationalize the Cabinet Decision in an entirely new section (as
compared to the 1997 Guidelines), under the title “Actions in
Response to an Armed Attack against a Country other than Japan.”
202
This section recognizes and implements the new policy position that
would permit Japan to engage in the use of force for purposes of
collective self-defense, using precisely the same language as was
promulgated in the Cabinet Decision.
203
It provides a number of
examples of how the armed forces of the two countries would
cooperate in the exercise of collective self-defense, including the
protection of US armed forces’ assets, ballistic missile defense, and
the securing of sea-lanes, including minesweeping operations.
204
Finally, in May 2015 the government submitted to the Diet the
proposed national security legislation that would formally implement
the changes to national security policy and posture reflected in the
Cabinet Decision and the 2015 Guidelines. The draft legislation was
in the form of two bills,
205
the first of which was an omnibus bill that
would implement significant revisions to ten existing national security
laws.
206
The revisions to these laws effectively implemented the
200. Id. at 7. (The next sentence clarifies that “Such situations cannot be defined
geographically. The measures described in this section include those that may be taken, in
accordance with the two countries’ respective laws and regulations, in circumstances that have
not yet amounted to such a situation.”).
201. Id. at 12.
202. Id. at 15.
203. Id. at 15-16.
204. Id. at 16-17.
205. The bills, the short titles of which are Heiwa Anzenhosei Seibiho [Law for the
maintenance of the peace and security legal system], and Kokusai Heiwa Shijiho [International
peace support Law] are available online at: http://www.cas.go.jp/jp/gaiyou/jimu/
housei_seibi.html. For a preliminary analysis of the legislation, see Y
ASUO HASEBE, KENSHO
ANPOHŌAN: DOKO GA KENPŌIHANKA [EXAMINED NATIONAL SECURITY LAWS: WHERE ARE
THEY
UNCONSTITUTIONAL?] (2015) [hereinafter HASEBE, NATIONAL SECURITY LAWS].
206. These included, most significantly, the Self-Defense Forces Law (Jieitaihō, Law
No. 164, 1954), the Maintaining Peace and Security in Situations Surrounding Japan Law
(shūhenjitai ni saishite wagakuni no heiwa oyobi anzen wo kakuhosuru tame no sochi ni
kansuru hōritsu, Law No. 64, 1999), the Maintaining Peace and Security in the Event of
Armed Attack Law (Buryoku kōgeki jitai ni okeru wagakuni no heiwa to dokuritsu narabini
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 485
policies outlined in the Cabinet Decision outlined earlier. The second
bill was for the creation of an entirely new law, the International
Peace Support Law,
207
which would among other things create
permanent authority for the government to deploy the SDF for
participation in “international cooperation activities” upon a simple
up or down vote of approval by the Diet. This would displace the
current convention that requires the Diet to pass special laws
authorizing the deployment of the SDF for each and every mission,
with detailed limits on the scope of operations and the activity of the
SDF units being deployed.
208
As the debate over these bills developed during the summer of
2015, it provoked increasing public and professional opposition. By
the time that they were finally passed in the Upper House, at 2:05
a.m. on September 19, there had been tens of thousands of people
protesting in the streets of Tokyo and other major cities, and there had
been a brawl among members of the Diet in the Upper House over
efforts to delay the vote.
209
Polls during the summer consistently
showed that well over fifty percent of the population was opposed to
the legislation.
210
The public opposition was spurred by surprising
kuni oyobi kokumin no anzen no kakuho ni kansuru hōritsu, Law No. 79, 2003),
Implementation of Measures by Japan in Relation to the Activities of the U.S. Armed Forces in
a Situation of Armed Attack Law (buryoku kōgeki jitai ni okeru amerika gōshūkoku no guntai
no kōdō ni tomonai wagakuni ga jisshi suru sochi ni kansuru hōritus, Law No. 113, 2004), and
the National Security Council Establishment Law (Kokka anzen hoshō kaigi secchihō, Law No.
71, 1961).
207. The full title of the law is Kokusai Heiwa Kyōdōtaisho jittai ni saishite Waga Kuni
ga jisshisuru Shogaikoku no Guntai nadoni taisuru Kyōryoku Shijikatsudō nado ni kansuru
Hōritsu [Law Related to the Implementation of Japan’s Cooperative Support for the Armed
Forces of Foreign Countries in Circumstances of International Peace and Security Cooperation
Activity].
208. For my discussion of this convention, see Craig Martin, Permanent SDF Overseas
Deployment Law Endangers Democracy, J
APAN TIMES (May 21, 2008),
http://search.japantimes.co.jp/opinion/2008/05/21/commentary/world-commentary/permanent-
sdf-overseas-deployment-law-endangers-democracy/.
209. Reiji Yoshida & Mizuho Aoki, Amid Angry Scenes, Ruling Parties Force Security
Bills Through Lower House Committee, J
APAN TIMES (July 15, 2015),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/07/15/national/politics-diplomacy/amid-angry-scenes-
ruling-parties-force-security-bills-lower-house-committee/#.V_PR_jKZOqA; Tomohiro Osaki,
Thousands Protest Abe, Security Bills at Diet Rally, J
APAN TIMES (Aug. 30, 2015),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/08/30/national/thousands-protest-abe-security-bills-
diet-rally/#.V_PSIDKZOqA.
210. Takashi Nakamichi, Support for Abe Falls to Lowest Level on Security Bills,
W
ALL ST. J. (Jul. 19, 2015), http://blogs.wsj.com/japanrealtime/2015/07/19/support-for-abe-
falls-to-lowest-level-on-security-bills/; Satoru Mori, The New Security Legislation and
486 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
levels of professional criticism and objection. Three former directors
of the CLB publicly voiced their view that provisions of the bills were
unconstitutional.
211
A former Chief Justice of the Supreme Court
similarly pronounced that the draft legislation was unconstitutional.
212
The incident that galvanized the media and drew the most attention to
the questioned constitutionality of the bills, and thereby catalyzed
much of this opposition, was the testimony in June by three very
prominent constitutional scholars in the Diet Constitutional
Commission hearings. All three scholars, including Professor Yasuo
Hasebe of Waseda University, who was ostensibly there as the
nominee of the governing LDP, testified quite emphatically that the
draft legislation would be unconstitutional if enacted.
213
In the wake
of this testimony, which was front page news for several days, over
two hundred constitutional scholars came forth to support their
position, and the government was hard-pressed to find a couple of law
professors from lesser universities who would voice tepid support for
the legitimacy of the legislation.
214
Notwithstanding the protests and resistance in the summer of
2015, less than a year later, in July, 2016, the governing LDP was
Japanese Public Reaction, TOKYO FOUNDATION, Dec. 2, 2015,
http://www.tokyofoundation.org/en/articles/2015/security-legislation-and-public-reaction.
211. Kotaro Ono, Former Legislation Bureau Chiefs Criticize Security Bills as Placing
Citizens in Danger, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (June 22, 2015); SAKATA, supra note 140, (Sakata is
himself a former Director General of the CLB).
212. Former Justice Brands Security Bills as Unconstitutional, Slams Abe for
Sophistry, J
APAN TIMES (Sept. 16, 2015), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/09/16/
national/politics-diplomacy/ex-justice-brands-security-bills-unconstitutional-upper-house-hits-
abe-duping-public/#.V_PVNTKZO8U; Ex-Chief Justice Blasts Abe’s Lack of Respect for
Constitutionalism, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (Sept. 3, 2015) .
213. See id. (The other two scholars were Eiji Sasada, also of Waseda University, and
Setsu Kobayashi of Keio University); see also Constitutional Law Scholars Lash Out at
Government Criticism, Insults, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (June 16, 2015).
214. Two Legal Experts Defend Constitutionality of Contentious Security Bills, J
APAN
TIMES (June 20, 2015), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/06/20/national/politics-
diplomacy/two-experts-defend-constitutionality-contentious-security-bills/#.V_PYCjKZO8U.
The two scholars were Osamu Nishi, professor emeritus of Komazawa University, who is a
long-standing champion of constitutional revision; and Akira Momochi, of Nihon University.
Meanwhile it was reported that as of the week following the testimony of the three scholars,
fully 225 constitutional law scholars had signed a joint statement condemning the
reinterpretation as unconstitutional. See Reiji Yoshida, Japan Security Bills Reveal
Irreconcilable Divide Between Scholars, Politicians, J
APAN TIMES (June 12, 2015),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/06/12/national/politics-diplomacy/japan-security-
bills-reveal-irreconcilable-divide-scholars-politicians/#.V_PY9TKZO8U.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 487
massively successful in the Upper House elections. The LDP had not
enjoyed a majority in the Upper House since before 2000, but in the
2016 elections it not only obtained a majority, but together with the
Komeitō, its coalition partner, it finally obtained the long-elusive two-
thirds majority. Thus, for the first time the LDP was within striking
distance of having the two-thirds majority within both chambers of
the Diet necessary to initiate and approve a proposal to amend the
Constitution. It might be tempting to see the election as thus having
been an expression of public approval of the reinterpretation, or at the
very least an acquiescence to it. I will return to this point in more
detail below,
215
but as a factual matter it is important to note that the
LDP quite prominently avoided discussion of constitutional issues in
the election campaign. The focus was on economic issues, and there
was virtually no mention of either the reinterpretation, the national
security legislation, or of possibly amending the Constitution going
forward.
216
Indeed, just days prior to the election, a representative of
the government stated emphatically that there was “zero prospect” of
amending the Constitution.
217
While few experts took this at face
value, it does tend to undermine any argument that the election result
was a either a mandate for change, or a reflection of public approval
of the reinterpretation. It was more a reflection of the Japanese
people’s strong sense that there were few viable alternatives.
218
A final consideration, of course, is how the courts will respond
when the revised laws are challenged, as they inevitably will be if the
government takes military action in accordance with those aspects of
the revised laws that are considered unconstitutional under the
established interpretation of Art. 9.
219
Past experience would suggest
215. See discussion infra Section III.A.
216. Tomohiro Osaki, LDP-led Ruling Bloc, Allies Clear Two-Thirds Majority Hurdle
in Upper House Poll, J
APAN TIMES (July 11, 2016), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/
news/2016/07/11/national/politics-diplomacy/ruling-bloc-wins-big-in-upper-
house/#.V_PaqTKZO8U; Constitution as a Campaign Issue, J
APAN TIMES (June 23, 2016),
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/opinion/2016/06/23/editorials/constitution-campaign-
issue/#.V_PaxTKZO8U.
217. Osaki, LDP-led Ruling Bloc, Allies Clear Two-Thirds Majority Hurdle in Upper
House Poll, supra note 216.
218. Gerald Curtis, Japan’s Election Offers Little Choice, W
ALL ST. J. (June 26, 2016),
http://www.wsj.com/articles/japans-election-offers-little-choice-1466960042.
219. As this article was in the editing process, there were reports of one lawsuit having
been commenced, and another being prepared: Lawsuit Challenging Controversial Laws Filed
by Group at Hiroshima Prefecture Court, J
APAN TIMES (Sept. 17, 2016),
488 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
that the courts, and particularly the Supreme Court, are unlikely to
strike down provisions of the new legislation. This is primarily
because the Supreme Court has, in the infamous Naganuma case, set
the bar so high for standing in any Article 9 based challenge that it is
difficult to imagine a scenario in which any likely applicant could
clear the hurdle.
220
In the unlikely event that a challenge did get
passed the standing obstacles, the prospects for success on the merits
would be still very uncertain.
As mentioned earlier, the Nagoya High Court in 2008 famously
opined (albeit in obiter dicta that was severely criticized by the
government) that the SDF provision of logistical support for the
armed forces of the US and coalition partners in the belligerent
occupation of Iraq was integral to the use of force by those foreign
forces, and thus was in violation of Art. 9(1).
221
This was an
affirmation of the ittaika” (or “integral use of force”) doctrine that
the Cabinet Decision explicitly rejected.
The Supreme Court, however, has been far more cautious and
deferential than the lower courts even when it has reached the
substantive issues related to Article 9. The only Supreme Court
decision that has squarely considered the interpretation and operation
of Art. 9, the notorious Sunagawa case of 1959, involved the question
of whether the US-Japan Security Treaty, and the presence of the US
armed forces in Japan, violated the Art. 9(2) prohibition against
maintaining armed forces or other war potential. In deciding the case
the Court adopted in obiter dicta the CLB interpretation that Japan
retained a right of individual self-defense. The narrow ratio decidendi
of the judgment was that the US forces were not being maintained by
Japan, and so could not constitute a maintenance of armed forces or
http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2016/09/17/national/crime-legal/lawsuit-challenging-
controversial-security-laws-filed-group-hiroshima-prefecture-court/ (last visited Dec. 2016),
and Collective Lawsuit Being Readied to Challenge Security Laws, J
APAN TIMES (Sept. 19,
2016), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2015/09/19/national/crime-legal/collective-lawsuit-
being-readied-to-challenge-security-laws/ (last visited Dec. 2016) (reporting on lawsuit being
prepared in Mie Prefecture).
220. Naganuma case, 36 M
INSHŪ 1679 (Sup. Ct., Sept. 9, 1982) [Uno et al. v. Minister
of Agriculture, Forestry, and Fisheries], in L
AWRENCE W. BEER & HIROSHI ITOH, THE
CONSTITUTIONAL CASE LAW OF JAPAN, 1970 THROUGH 1990, at 124-26 (1996).
221. Nagoya Decision, supra note 182. See Craig Martin, Rule of Law Comes Under
Fire: Government Response to High Court Ruling on SDF Operations in Iraq, J
APAN TIMES
(May 3, 2008), http://www.japantimes.co.jp/opinion/2008/05/03/commentary/world-
commentary/rule-of-law-comes-under-fire/#.V_J6-5MrIb1.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 489
other war potential in violation of Art. 9(2). But the majority of the
Court went further than necessary, and purported to employ a thin
facsimile of the US political question doctrine to also hold that the
judiciary should play no role in determining the constitutionality of
government action in the national security realm unless such action
was “obviously unconstitutional.”
222
The dissent was scathing in its
criticism of this aspect of the judgment, and the Court has never again
invoked the political question doctrine, but the precedent remains—
and it is unclear whether a timid and conservative Court would find
the reinterpretation to be “obviously unconstitutional.”
In my view, the primary reason for Abe’s appointment of the
Advisory Panel, and his attempt to manipulate CLB support for the
reinterpretation, both of which would lead to recommendations and
opinions in support of the constitutionality of the reinterpretation, was
to make it more difficult for the Supreme Court to subsequently find
that the reinterpretation, while inconsistent with the text and long-
established understanding of Article 9, is “obviously
unconstitutional.” But given the extraordinary criticism of the
reinterpretation by prominent constitutional scholars, former
Directors of the CLB, and even a retired Supreme Court Justice, there
will be strong cross-cutting pressure on the Supreme Court if it
receives a case that it cannot dismiss on standing or other doctrinal
grounds. While precedent would suggest that a ruling of
unconstitutionality is unlikely, it is not entirely implausible.
III. THE REINTERPRETATION, INFORMAL AMENDMENT, AND
LEGITIMACY
This examination of the reinterpretation efforts in Japan should
leave us with some obvious questions. To begin with, how should this
reinterpretation effort be characterized? Is it the kind of interpretive
move that falls within the range of incremental evolutionary change in
interpretation that is considered normal and entirely legitimate in
most liberal democratic constitutional systems? If not, why not, and
222. Saikō Saibansho [Sup. Ct.] Dec. 16, 1959, 13 KEISHŪ 3225, SAIBANSHO
SANBANREI JŌHŌ [SAIBANSHO WEB] http://www.courts.go.jp/app/hanrei_en/detail?id=13
(Japan). For my more detailed analysis and further authority, see Martin, Binding Dogs of War,
supra note 109, at 337-43. See also, Haley, Waging War: Japan’s Constitutional Constraints,
supra note 141, at 25 (more charitably arguing that the Court thus importantly reserved the
power to strike down laws that were obviously unconstitutional).
490 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
what then is it? Is it an informal amendment in line with the theories
we examined in Part I? If so, is it thereby legitimate, and how do we
know either way? And as raised at the outset, how do the factors of
deliberate agency and popular will interact to affect the legitimacy of
such a intentional constitutional change? How will it be seen over
time? Thinking these questions through should contribute to our
understanding of how these determinations get made and the lines
drawn in informal amendment theory, and more importantly, how we
should assess the legitimacy of informal amendments in general
terms. It will also leave us with some thoughts on how to assess the
legitimacy of the Japanese reinterpretation specifically.
A. The Reinterpretation as Normal Interpretive Move
In this section I will begin with the first of these questions,
namely whether the reinterpretation constitutes a valid and legitimate
interpretive move within Japan’s constitutional system. The
reinterpretation only becomes relevant to theories of informal
amendment, after all, if it is not a normal interpretive development of
the constitution, so we must first resolve that question. As I have
suggested earlier, one of ironies of the debate over informal
amendment is that those who oppose the very existence of the concept
are somewhat more forgiving in their characterization of interpretive
moves. That is, they are willing to accept rather radical constitutional
changes as falling within the scope of “normal” and legitimate
incremental interpretive moves, in order to accommodate and explain
that which others are inclined to call informal amendments. However,
for reasons of both process and substance, it is extremely difficult to
persuasively argue that the reinterpretation of Article 9 by the Abe
administration can be characterized as a legitimate interpretive
development, regardless of how widely one casts the net.
The first argument to be made is that the overwhelming majority
of constitutional law scholars in Japan, applying the principles of
constitutional interpretation most accepted within the Japanese legal
system, have concluded and publicly avowed that the reinterpretation,
and the national security legislation that reflects it, are invalid and
unconstitutional.
223
What is more, both the fact that there is such a
223. See supra notes 211-13 and accompanying text. In addition, for recent publication
on the issue, see, e.g., H
ASEBE, NATIONAL SECURITY LAWS, supra note 205.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 491
near consensus among legal scholars against a government policy,
and the very public nature in which they have expressed their opinion,
is more remarkable in Japan than it might be in the US.
224
Thus, this
position taken by the legal academy on the validity of the
reinterpretation should by itself stand as fairly persuasive evidence
that it cannot be characterized as a normal interpretive move within
the Japanese constitutional system.
The process and form of the change also militate against any
attempt to characterize the change as a normal interpretive
development. First, the agents of change are irregular. The executive,
with the support of some extra-constitutional ad-hoc panel of experts,
is not what we would typically consider to be the normal institution
for advancing constitutional interpretation. This abnormality is
exacerbated by the manner in which the executive has attempted to
make an interpretive change here, with the Cabinet simply advancing
a “new interpretation” that converts a fairly clear constitutional rule
into a vague standard with ambiguous conditions precedent for the
exercise of government power. Aside from the substantive problems
with this, which I will return to below, there is simply no tradition or
convention for limiting the frequency or range of such Cabinet
“changes” to the interpretation of the Constitution, along the lines of
the well-established conventions that constrain the interpretive
developments of courts.
225
This is all the more problematic when the
executive reinterpretation is in the direction of relaxing constraints on
government power. Once accepted as a valid form of change,
presumably the Cabinet could revise its own interpretation at will
whenever it was convenient to do so.
Some would argue that in the US context the political branches
of government enjoy greater competency than the judiciary to engage
in the interpretation of some aspects of the constitution, such as war
224. The legal academy tends to be more conservative and deferential to government
policy than its American counterpart, and scholars in public universities are public officials,
arguably having less academic freedom than tenured scholars in North America, and certainly
with nothing like the tradition of public protest and criticism of public policy.
225. While stare decisis is not formally a principle in civil law systems, there does tend
to be respect for precedent, and in Japan in particular it has been long established that an
informal principle similar to stare decisis operates to constrain judicial decision-making. See,
e.g., J
OHN OWEN HALEY, THE SPIRIT OF JAPANESE LAW 2 (1998).
492 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
powers and foreign policy.
226
But even under this view, interpretive
change is still seen as being far more the province of the judiciary,
even if it is primarily in the role of endorsing and explaining the
legitimacy of moves made by the other branches. As we saw in our
discussion of informal amendment above, it is precisely when the
political branches have pursued dramatic legislative or policy changes
that are difficult to reconcile with the established understanding of the
constitution, even if acquiesced in by the judiciary, that such changes
tend to be viewed as something other than a normal interpretive
development. It is too early to tell whether the Japanese judiciary will
acquiesce or endorse this move, and it remains for me to presently
explain how this change is difficult to reconcile with established
understanding—but the fact that this change was deliberately
orchestrated by the Cabinet is in any event irregular.
Added to this is the unusual nature of the form of argument that
was advanced in support of the reinterpretation. The very essence of
the concept of legitimate interpretive development is that the
proposed interpretation can be explained and justified as falling
within a reasonable range of possible meanings for the provision in
question, employing accepted principles of constitutional
interpretation. The arguments advanced by the Cabinet, in its brief
eight page Decision, made little attempt to conform to this idea and
were not framed as constitutional analysis or interpretive argument.
The basic form of the argument was largely result-oriented. It began
with the claim that the increased threat levels in the region
surrounding Japan required the country to have greater latitude to use
force in collaboration with its allies to ensure its national security,
from which it followed that Article 9 must be re-interpreted in a
manner that permitted such use of force. In introducing the section on
the controversial change regarding collective self-defense, the Cabinet
Decision stated that:
In order to adapt to the changes in the security environment
surrounding Japan and secure the lives and peaceful livelihood of
its people under any situations, the Government has examined
what constitutional interpretation would be appropriate, as
226. My thanks to Bill Rich for this point. On this, see, e.g., MARK TUSHNET, TAKING
THE
CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS (1999) (generally arguing against judicial
supremacy, and for a more populist constitutional law, with the political branches assuming a
greater role in interpreting the constitution).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 493
sufficient responses would not necessarily be possible if the
constitutional interpretation to date were maintained.
227
This bald-faced process of working backward from a desired
policy result to the formulation of a constitutional construction that
would permit its realization, is simply not a legitimate approach to
constitutional interpretation. The only constitutional argument
attempted, after laying out the need for change to meet the demands
of a new security situation, is a paragraph that tries to develop
connections between the language of Article 9, that of the preamble of
the Constitution, and Article 13. The preamble contains a clause
which provides that the Japanese people recognize that “all peoples of
the world have a right to live in peace”; and Article 13 provides that
the right of all of the people “to life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness shall, to the extent that it does not interfere with the public
welfare, be the supreme consideration in legislation and in other
governmental affairs.”
228
First of all, the Cabinet Decision actually
misquotes the Preamble in a manner that suggests that the clause is
articulating a right of the Japanese people to live in peace, when in
fact it is referring to a right enjoyed by all the people of the world. In
any event, it goes on to suggest that when considered within the
context of these other provisions, the use of force to the “minimum
extent necessary” permitted by Article 9, must be understood as
allowing whatever is necessary for the “peace and security and to
ensure [Japan’s] survival.”
229
Moreover, this is coupled with the fact that there was a frank
acknowledgment, in both the Cabinet Decision and in the many
presentations by Prime Minister Abe, that the reinterpretation
comprised a significant change to the long established meaning of
Article 9(1).
230
While the Cabinet Decision did attempt to argue that
there was some continuity with the underlying “basic logic” of the
established interpretation,
231
there was no suggestion that the
reinterpretation was a mere incremental development in the evolution
of the meaning of Article 9(1), but rather the Cabinet Decision
227. CABINET DECISION, supra note 24, § 3(1), at 6.
228. N
IHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], pmbl. (Japan); id. art. 13.
229. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, § 3(2), at 7.
230. A
DVISORY PANEL REPORT 2014, supra note 134; CABINET DECISION, supra note
24.
231. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, § 3(2)-(3), at 7.
494 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
conceded that the reinterpretation was a marked change to permit
policy that would have been otherwise unconstitutional. This, again,
is not the typical form of incremental interpretive development.
More important, of course, is the substantive analysis of the
reinterpretation, and whether it can be viewed as being within a
reasonable range of possible meanings of Article 9. The initial
difficulty in analyzing the content of the reinterpretation for this
purpose, however, is the degree of ambiguity and uncertainty that
surrounds the precise contours of the reinterpretation itself. Thus far I
have been focused on the Cabinet Decision, but what is less clear is
the role the two Advisory Panel reports might play in any subsequent
judicial interpretation of the reinterpretation. Depending on whether
the Advisory Panel reports are to be considered as part of the
reinterpretation, we have two distinct problems with its validity. On
the one hand, if we look at the Advisory Panel reports as being part of
the reinterpretation or informing how it is to be understood, then the
reinterpretation could be said to render the renunciation in Article
9(1) meaningless, which offends basic canons of constitutional
interpretation.
232
On the other hand, if we look at just the Cabinet
Decision, then there is sufficient ambiguity and vagueness as to make
the new interpretation of the provision non-justiciable.
Beginning with the 2014 Advisory Panel report, it initially
described how the established interpretation of Article 9 has
consistently denied and prohibited any use of force beyond that for
the exercise of individual self-defense. From there it went on to not
only very explicitly recommend a reinterpretation that would allow
for the exercise of collective self-defense, but also collective security
operations authorized by the UN Security Council. Indeed, it
recommended a construction that would permit any use of force that
would be permitted by public international law. It did so on the
fallacious argument that the clause “as means of settling international
disputes” in Article 9(1) qualifies and limits the scope of the
prohibition on the use of force, in that the exercise of neither
individual nor collective self-defense constitutes “a use of force for
232. The Advisory Panel report probably should play no role whatsoever in interpreting
the reinterpretation, given that it is an extra-constitutional body with no constitutional
authority whatsoever. But Abe clearly sought the report to bolster and lend legitimacy to the
move, and it could be anticipated that it would form part of the argument in subsequent
judicial review.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 495
settling international disputes”. It goes even further, for good
measure, by suggesting that the words “to which Japan is a party”
should be simply read into the clause. As such any use of force for
self-defense or UN collective security operations would be
permissible, as it would then not be for the “settlement of
international disputes to which Japan is a party.”
233
The background to this argument about the meaning of the
phrase “settling international disputes” is not new, and indeed the
Advisory Panel quotes testimony of a former Director General of the
SDF to the Diet on the issue.
234
The claim is often made by
conservative proponents of expanding the meaning of Article 9 that
this interpretation mirrors language and accepted meaning of the
Kellogg-Briand Pact, but that is entirely inaccurate—not only is the
language in the treaty actually quite different, but the relevant clause
has never been accepted as having the meaning that Japanese
conservatives attribute to it in any event.
235
What is more, there is
simply no foundation whatsoever for the idea that the jus ad bellum
regime in international law makes a conceptual distinction between
uses of force based on whether they are for “settlement of
international disputes” as opposed to for any other purpose. It does
not recognize self-defense as being somehow distinct from an
international dispute, nor for that matter accept that a state is not “a
party to a dispute” if it is acting in self-defense.
236
What this argument
in effect attempts to do, while studiously avoiding the language itself,
is to reinterpret the clause “settling of international disputes” as
meaning “engaging in acts of aggression”. This harkens back to older
reactionary arguments that have been made within conservative
circles in Japan, to the effect that Article 9 should be understood as
233. ADVISORY PANEL REPORT 2014, supra note 134, at 23-24.
234. Id. (citing Director-General of the Defense Agency Seiichi Omura, answering
questions to the Diet, December 22, 1954).
235. The language of the Kellogg-Briand Pact is to “condemn recourse to war for the
solution of international controversies, and renounce it, as an instrument of national policy in
their relations with one another.” Kellogg-Briand Pact 1928, supra note 128, art. I. There were
strained interpretations at the time that suggested that wars not waged for the purpose of
“national policy,” such as wars for religious or ideological ends, might thus be legal. This was
not, however, the accepted view or interpretation of the provision in international law. See,
e.g., D
INSTEIN, supra note 145, at 84. In any event, the language is not the same as that of
Article 9(1).
236. See supra note 145 for sources analyzing the international law principles of jus ad
bellum.
496 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
only prohibiting aggressive war—arguments that were rejected with
the official interpretation of 1954, and consistently rejected ever
since, for reasons that I turn to next.
237
Leaving aside all of these detailed objections to the basis for the
Advisory Report argument, however, a more fundamental
constitutional interpretation problem is posed by the implication of its
argument. If, as the Advisory Panel report argued, Article 9 is to be
now understood as permitting all uses of force that are permitted by
the jus ad bellum regime in international law, or Article 9 only
prohibits “aggressive war”, then we are left with Article 9(1)
renouncing exactly nothing. It will be recalled that the provision
states that “the Japanese people forever renounce war as a sovereign
right of the nation and the threat or use of force as means of settling
international disputes.” It is prohibiting certain uses of force that
constitute sovereign rights under international law. While it is true
that the English language version could be construed as identifying
only “war” and not “the threat or use of force” as the sovereign rights
that have been renounced, the Japanese language version makes it
much more clear that it is both war and the threat or use of force that
are being renounced as sovereign rights.
238
But if Article 9 is
construed as prohibiting only that which is already prohibited by
international law, then it has renounced nothing, and the interpretation
renders at least part of the text of the provision meaningless—which
offends basic principles of constitutional interpretation. The meaning
goes from a clear rule that renounces and prohibits the exercise of
certain sovereign rights (that is, the right to collective self-defense or
participation in UN authorized collective security operations), to a
provision that renounces nothing, and merely confirms in ambiguous
terms the country’s adherence to the jus ad bellum regime—which is
entirely and categorically inconsistent with the original purpose of the
provision, precedent, and the consistent understanding and operation
of the provision for over sixty-five years.
Such is the problem with the Advisory Panel’s report. If, on the
other hand, we consider only the Cabinet Decision as articulating the
substance of the reinterpretation, we are presented with a different
237. For my more extensive analysis and rejection of these arguments, see Martin,
Binding the Dogs of War, supra note 109, at 312-13, 310 n.114.
238. Id.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 497
problem. As discussed earlier in Part II, the Cabinet Decision does not
go so far as to suggest that all uses of force permitted by international
law are to be henceforth constitutional under the new understanding
of Article 9(1), and indeed it even creates a sui generis conception of
collective self-defense.
239
But therein lies part of the problem—this
conception of collective self-defense is vague, ambiguous, and non-
justiciable, if ever it came to be the basis for a constitutional
challenge. Collective self-defense under Article 51 of the Charter
permits states to use force against an aggressor state in response to an
armed attack on any other member of the United Nations, upon a
request for assistance from the victim and notification of the UN
Security Council that it is exercising the right.
240
As explained earlier,
the Cabinet resolution purports to limit the use of force in collective
self-defense to responses to an armed attack on a state with which
Japan has close relations, and where the armed attack is viewed as a
threat to Japan’s survival or its people’s rights to life, liberty and the
pursuit of happiness, and the use of force is necessary and
proportionate.
241
These additional conditions were provided as a sop
to mollify the Komeitō, the ruling party’s coalition partner, as they
create an impression that the bar for using force is higher, or the right
of collective self-defense is narrower, than it is in international law.
242
But in reality the conditions and criteria are ill-defined and difficult to
either interpret or enforce, and the government pronouncements have
further exacerbated the problem.
In discussing the operation and scope of the new right of
collective self-defense, Prime Minister Abe and Defense Minister
Nakatani have both made comments about the possibility of Japan
conducting mine-sweeping operations in the Straits of Hormuz if it
were mined by Iran.
243
If, as they have suggested, the authority relied
upon for such action would be this right of collective self-defense as
defined (rather than on other international law principles that might
239. See supra Section II.C.
240. U.N. Charter, art. 51. See D
INSTEIN, supra note 145; GRAY, supra note 145.
241. See supra Section II.C.
242. LDP Set to Limit Use of Collective Self-Defense, Y
OMIURI SHIMBUN, Mar. 30,
2014.
243. Operations in Strait of Hormuz to Come Under New Defense Guidelines, A
SAHI
SHIMBUN (Apr. 9, 2015); Mina Pollmann, Could Japan Go Minesweeping in the Strait of
Hormuz?, D
IPLOMAT (Feb. 18, 2015), http://thediplomat.com/2015/02/could-japan-go-
minesweeping-in-the-strait-of-hormuz/.
498 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
authorize the clearing of mines from international straits),
244
the
comments reveal even greater uncertainty about the meaning of the
new standard. They suggest that the armed attack on a country in
close relations with Japan (however that relationship might be
determined) may be uncoupled from the threat to Japan’s survival and
the people’s rights to the pursuit of happiness, such that each is a
separate trigger for exercising the right of collective self-defense.
Abe’s comments on the issue have made no reference to how Iran’s
mining the straits of Hormuz might even constitute an armed attack,
but have instead focused on the threat posed to the livelihood of the
Japanese people by such a blockade – a threat to the “people’s right to
life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness” in the language of the
clause. This not only uncouples the exercise of collective self-defense
from an armed attack on another country, but even from a threat to the
survival of Japan, and potentially conditions it solely upon a threat to
the livelihood of the people of Japan – however, that might be
measured or defined.
245
Finally, if the ambiguity of these conditions
were not enough, representatives of the government have actually
stated publicly that not all the conditions for the use of force have
been or will be disclosed, thereby quite explicitly suggesting that
there are additional secret criteria for the use of force.
246
This
ambiguity and uncertainty in the standard makes it arguably non-
justiciable. In the event that the national security legislation that
implements this part of the reinterpretation, or some specific
deployment authorized by it, is challenged in court as being a
violation of Article 9, how is a court to interpret the provision in light
of this ambiguous new understanding? The reinterpretation has the
potential of rendering the provision, which was a relatively clear rule
capable of enforcement, non-justiciable and thereby unenforceable.
244. For a review of such principles, see, e.g., CHATHAM HOUSE, INTERNATIONAL
L
AW APPLICABLE TO NAVAL MINES (2014), https://www.chathamhouse.org/sites/files/
chathamhouse/field/field_document/20140226NavalMines.pdf; S
EAN HENSELER, PROJECT
2049 INSTITUTE, CLARIFYING U.S. – JAPAN MINE WARFARE ROLES, MISSIONS, AND
C
APABILITIES IN THE PERSIAN GULF: AN EXAMINATION OF INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ISSUES
(2013), https://project2049.net/documents/countermining_henseler.pdf.
245. This discussion is drawn from an earlier essay on this issue. See Craig Martin, Jus
ad Bellum Implications of Japan’s New National Security Laws, 14:10 A
SIA-PACIFIC J.:
JAPAN FOCUS, May 15, 2016, http://apjjf.org/-Craig-Martin/4893/article.pdf.
246. Sachiko Miwa, Diet Debate on Security Bills Starts with Confusion Over Limits on
Collective Self-Defense, A
SAHI SHIMBUN (May 26, 2015).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 499
The other problem posed by the reinterpretation as articulated by
the Cabinet Decision, is that it is potentially inconsistent with the
principles of jus ad bellum in international law. It has been argued
that because the principles in Article 9(1) were drawn from
international law, the interpretation of the provision should be
informed by, and be consistent with the principles of jus ad bellum.
247
The Cabinet Decision’s articulation of collective self-defense is
obviously a marked departure from any requirement to interpret the
concepts in Article 9(1) in a manner consistent with the jus ad bellum,
but the problem is far greater than that. The Cabinet Decision, and the
resulting national security legislation, could authorize state action that
would result in Japan being in actual violation of the principles of jus
ad bellum. This is true with respect to the contemplated use of force
in collective self-defense as indicated above—a use of force in
response to conduct that does not constitute an armed attack on a third
country, but is responding to a perceived threat to future survival of
Japan, or even worse, merely to the Japanese people’s right to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness, would obviously not fall within
the accepted exception for self-defense. This is more radical than the
infamous Bush Doctrine of preventative self-defense, which has been
roundly rejected in international law.
248
The reinterpretation does not, however, pose this problem only
with respect to the use of force in collective self-defense. A careful
review of the other two major elements of the Cabinet Decision
reveals that it contemplates other possible uses of force that are also
not at all consistent with international law. The most serious of these,
is the stipulation that Japan could use force in response to “an
infringement that does not amount to an armed attack,” in “situations
247. See, e.g., TOSHIO FUJII, KENPŌ TO KOKUSAI SHAKAI [THE CONSTITUTION AND
INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY] ch. 12-14 (2d ed. 2005); Masanari Sakamoto, Buryokukōshi ihōka
gensoku no naka no kyūjōron [The Article 9 Debate Within the Criminalization of the Use of
Armed Force] 1334 J
URISTO 50, 56 (2007); Hitoshi Nasu, Japan’s 2015 Security Legislation:
Challenges to its Implementation Under International Law, 92 I
NTL L. STUD. 249 (2016);
Hitoshi Nasu, Article 9 of the Japanese Constitution Revisited in the Light of International
Law, 18 J.
JAPAN L. 50 (2004).
248. T
HE WHITE HOUSE, NATIONAL SECURITY STRATEGY OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA 15-16 (2002), http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/63562.pdf (expounding
the actual doctrine); see Eyal Benvenisti, The US and the Use of Force: Double-Edged
Hegemony and the Management of Global Emergencies, 15 E
UR. J. INTL L. 677 (2004)
(describing the “Bush Doctrine” as an effort to respond to various security challenges but
criticizing it as upsetting the existing UN regime and creating other risks to global stability).
500 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
that are neither pure peacetime nor contingencies”.
249
The use of force
in individual self-defense in international law is permitted under
Article 51 of the UN Charter, and customary international law, when
either an armed attack has been carried out against the state exercising
the right; or, under a more liberal interpretation that is widely
accepted, when the launch of such an armed attack against the state is
imminent.
250
Depending on how the Cabinet Decision and
implementing legislation is interpreted and acted upon, it could
conceivably authorize Japanese military operations that would
constitute a use of force in the absence of any armed attack, actual or
imminent—circumstances that would not come close to satisfying the
international law conditions for the lawful use of force under either
Art. 51 or 42. The Advisory Panel actually sounded a note of sage
caution in this regard in its 2014 Report, but was apparently
ignored.
251
The second major part of the Cabinet Decision deals with the
authorization for increased logistical and transportation support for
the armed forces of allied forces engaged in armed conflict. The
Cabinet Decision suggests that Japan’s increased support for the
armed forces of belligerents is to be simply deemed as not integral to
the use of force by such belligerent forces unless it is within actual
theaters of combat,
252
however that might be determined, and so will
not constitute a use of force by Japan in violation of Art. 9.
253
In a
sense, this is not so much a reinterpretation of Art. 9 as it is an
attempted reinterpretation of what constitutes support for and
involvement in the actions of belligerents so as to attract state
responsibility under international law. This is of course beyond the
power and jurisdiction of the government of Japan—it cannot by
249. CABINET DECISION, supra note 24, § 1, at 2.
250. See U.N. Charter, art. 51; D
INSTEIN, supra note 145, GRAY, supra note 145; see
also Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.), 1986 I.C.J.
Rep. 14, (June 27).
251. A
DVISORY PANEL REPORT 2014, supra note 134, at 45 (“Sometimes, the right to
take measures against infringements that do not amount to an armed attack is referred to as
‘minor self-defense rights’; however, the use of this term is not advisable as it has not been
established in international law, and could invite criticism from at home and overseas that
Japan is expanding beyond the concept of the right of self-defense under Article 51 of the
Charter.”).
252. C
ABINET DECISION, supra note 24, at 4 (the precise language is: “the scene where
combat activities are actually being conducted.”).
253. See id. at 3-4.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 501
Cabinet resolution or domestic legislation simply “deem” its actions
to be not complicit in the use of force by other nations as a matter of
international law. And under international law, certain levels of
support for or involvement in the operations of a belligerent state in a
given armed conflict, will be sufficient to make the supporting state a
belligerent to the conflict as well. It makes no distinction as to
whether the support is directly to forces within theatres of combat or
not, as the Cabinet Decision attempts to do. What is more, where the
actions of the first belligerent constitute an act of aggression,
responsibility for such aggression can be attributed to the supporting
state.
254
Neither the Cabinet Decision nor the implementing
legislation includes any conditions that the belligerents that are
benefiting from Japanese support are themselves complying with
international law. Thus, such close logistical and transportation
support could lead to Japanese operations being integrated with the
unlawful use of force by other countries.
255
There is nothing, of course, that requires a constitutional
provision in general to be consistent with international law. But as
explained in Part II, Article 9(1) was drafted and ratified with the
purpose of not only incorporating international law constraints into
the Constitution, but also to add further limitations, renouncing rights
that Japan would otherwise have under international law. That
purpose and understanding was formalized by the CLB, obliquely
confirmed by the Supreme Court in 1959, and complied with and
acknowledged by every government for close to sixty years, until
2014. The provision operated to effectively constrain policy in
accordance with this understanding. The reinterpretation is a radical
departure from that understanding, making permissible precisely that
which had long been forbidden. Moreover, an interpretation that
either renders the provision irrelevant or hopelessly ambiguous and
vague, and which not only divorces its constituent concepts from their
international law origins but would actually authorize state action that
254. See generally GRAY, supra note 145; G.A. Res. 3314 (XXIX) (Dec. 14, 1974);
Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.), Judgment, 1986
I.C.J. Rep. 14 (June 27).
255. As mentioned earlier, the Nagoya High Court in 2008 found that Japanese
support for coalition forces in Iraq in 2005 constituted a use of force in violation of Art. 9(1),
highlighting the risk of Japan becoming complicit in the belligerent actions of countries to
which it is providing support, see supra notes 182 and 221 and accompanying text.
502 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
would violate the jus ad bellum principles from which the language of
Article 9(1) was drawn, simply cannot be accepted as a normal
interpretive development.
B. The Reinterpretation as Informal Amendment
If the reinterpretation cannot be categorized as a normal and
legitimate interpretive development, then the question is whether it
can be classified as the kind of informal constitutional amendment
discussed in Part I. Perhaps more importantly, if it is to be considered
such an informal amendment, is it legitimate, and how would we
know? And most central to our inquiry, what does that tell us about
the nature of legitimacy, and the factors that determine legitimacy,
within the context of informal amendment theory?
On Levinson’s five-point scale, if the reinterpretation is not a
formal amendment nor a normal interpretive development (leaving
aside the category of “revision”), we are left with either informal
amendment or revolutionary change. Informal amendment is the most
likely option. And indeed there are aspects of the reinterpretation that
map onto or share features of a number of the different theories of
informal amendment. It could even be argued that it fits the five-stage
model of Ackerman’s constitutional moment, which it will be recalled
is comprised of: (i) contestation; (ii) challenge to dissenting
institutions; (iii) public ratification; (iv) a switch in time; and (v)
another public ratification.
256
Following Abe’s return to the office of
the Prime Minister in 2012, there was public discussion and some
debate regarding the possible amendment, and then reinterpretation,
of Article 9 of the Constitution; there was a government challenge to
one of the dissenting institutions, with the political appointment of an
outsider as Director of the CLB; in December 2014, some six months
after the Cabinet Decision was announced, the governing LDP and
Komeitō coalition was broadly successful in the Lower House
elections; the CLB might be said to have exhibited a “switch in time”
by acquiescing to the validity of the reinterpretation, which was also
implemented in a fashion through the new national security
legislation passed in September, 2015; and then, finally, in July of
2016 the governing LDP enjoyed considerable electoral success in the
256. See supra notes 100-04 and accompanying text.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 503
Upper House elections, gaining a two-thirds majority for the first time
in decades.
Rosalind Dixon and Guy Baldwin have examined the extent to
which the Japanese reinterpretation conforms to Ackerman’s theory
of constitutional moments in a forthcoming article.
257
They argue that
despite the superficial conformity, the reinterpretation cannot be said
to satisfy the criteria of Ackerman’s model, in part because there was
not the kind of political competition and contestation required. They
point out that a key component of Ackerman’s theory is that the
public consider the proposed or contested change “with a seriousness
that they do not normally accord to politics.”
258
But while there was
extraordinary public protest against the reinterpretation, and in
particular the passing of the revised national security laws, all of
which would appear to reflect some level of public engagement, there
was not the kind of informed debate that would produce open and
searching deliberation, and thus no genuine public ratification and
political consensus.
To start, the government itself attempted to stifle the public
debate, leading to widespread criticism of the increasing erosion of
press freedoms in Japan.
259
This undermined the prospect for open
and searching deliberation. Notwithstanding this, the public
opposition to the reinterpretation has persisted, and public opinion
polls have continued to show a majority of the Japanese people
opposed to both the reinterpretation and the revised national security
legislation, right on down to the present day,
260
and the majority of
the opposition parties also remained opposed to the entire
reinterpretation effort throughout.
261
But that too does not evidence
true contestation, and it certainly cuts against the idea of ratification.
This is because the LDP could, and did, entirely ignore the opposition
and protest without fear of punishment at the polls. The reason that
such public and political opposition did not translate into electoral
losses for the LDP was simply because of the fragmented and
257. See generally Rosalind Dixon & Guy Baldwin, Globalizing Constitutional
Moments? A Reflection on the Japanese Article 9 Debate (unpublished manuscript) (on file
with author).
258. Id. at 10 (citing A
CKERMAN, supra note 1, at 6).
259. See id. at 11. See generally Martin Fackler, The Silencing of Japan’s Free Press,
F
OREIGN POLY, May 27, 2016.
260. See generally Mori, supra note 210.
261. See Dixon & Baldwin, supra note 257, at 11.
504 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
impotent nature of political opposition in Japan generally. The LDP
has dominated the political process in Japan since 1955, with only
three short breaks. After the perceived failures of the Japanese
Democratic Party (“DPJ”) during its short reign between 2009-12,
there developed a prevailing view that there was no real alternative to
the LDP, even though there was little support for Abe’s policies.
262
One result of this, Dixon and Baldwin argue, is that the process
surrounding the reinterpretation has not been characterized by the
kind of political and public contestation that is required by
Ackerman’s theory of democratic constitutional change.
263
Another consequence of this analysis, however, is that it would
be very difficult to really classify either the 2014 Lower House
election results or the even more successful 2016 Upper House
elections, as being a public ratification of the reinterpretation policy.
As was noted in Part I, critics such as John Dow have argued that
even in the US context, it is extremely difficult to attribute meaning to
election results, and that therefore Ackerman’s distinction between
normal politics and constitutional politics, and his interpretation of
election results as expressions of popular sovereignty in the process of
higher law-making, is entirely misguided.
264
This criticism is all the
more powerful when applied to the Japanese political system, where
one party has dominated for six decades, and the election success of
individual candidates and parties as a whole are said to be little
influenced by policy platforms or positions.
265
The clear and
consistent opposition to the reinterpretation effort though and after the
elections, coupled with the conspicuous policy of the LDP not to refer
to constitutional issues during the 2016 campaign, deprives the
elections of any value as an expression of popular will in support of
the constitutional change. I will return to this point below when we
return to the question of legitimacy, but here it is relevant to the
262. See generally Gerald Curtis, Japan’s Election Offers Little Choice, WALL ST. J.
(June 26, 2016), http://www.wsj.com/articles/japans-election-offers-little-choice-1466960042.
263. See Dixon & Baldwin, supra note 257, at 14 (noting that political competition
does not fit explicitly into any of the five stages of Ackerman’s model, but is implicitly
essential to “the actual operation of Ackerman’s theory as account of democratic constitutional
change”).
264. See Dow, supra note 1, at 131-33.
265. See generally G
ERALD CURTIS, THE LOGIC OF JAPANESE POLITICS (1999); ETHAN
SCHEINER, DEMOCRACY WITHOUT COMPETITION IN JAPAN: OPPOSITION FAILURE IN A ONE-
P
ARTY DOMINANT STATE (2006).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 505
question of whether the Japanese reinterpretation fits Ackerman’s
model—and it arguably does not.
It might be objected at this point that not only Ackerman’s
model, but the informal amendment theory I have explored more
generally is simply too dependent upon the particular proclivities of
the US constitutional system to be susceptible to application to a
system such as Japan’s. Where one party has been in power for more
than sixty of the last seventy years, and Supreme Court justices rarely
serve for more than two or three years,
266
the theory of constitutional
revolution through partisan entrenchment, for instance, can have little
relevance. Indeed, where a Supreme Court is so weak that legislation
or government action has only ever been determined unconstitutional
ten times in sixty-nine years, there is actually little tradition of normal
interpretive development as a process of constitutional change, far
less informal amendment.
267
These are all valid objections up to a
point, but they do not, in my view, disqualify the effort of applying
informal amendment theory to the Japanese situation, or make the
Japanese case study irrelevant to our understanding of informal
amendment. Indeed, Carlos Bernal has focused on the particular role
that weak courts may play in the form of informal amendment that he
terms “infra-constitutional mutation”.
268
The mechanisms and
modalities of informal amendment may differ from system to system,
but the underlying concept, and the problems that it raises, remain
relevant. As indicated earlier, there are European analogues to
theories of informal amendment, and there is similarly a theoretical
debate over a form of informal amendment in Japanese constitutional
law as well.
269
One of the primary problems that is common to all of these
debates (even if not the explicit focus of them), is the question of
266. See generally David Law, The Anatomy of a Conservative Court: Judicial Review
in Japan, 87 T
EX. L. REV. 1545 (2009).
267. For discussion of the Supreme Court, see generally id.; Frank K. Upham, Political
Lackeys or Faithful Public Servants? Two Views of the Japanese Judiciary, 30 L
AW & SOC.
INQUIRY 421 (2005); J. MARK RAMSEYER & ERIC B. RASMUSEN, MEASURING JUDICIAL
INDEPENDENCE: THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF JUDGING IN JAPAN (2003); John O. Haley, The
Japanese Judiciary: Maintaining Integrity, Autonomy, and the Public Trust, in L
AW IN JAPAN:
A TURNING POINT 99 (Daniel H. Foote ed., 2007).
268. See generally Bernal, Unconstitutional Constitutional Amendments in the Case
Study of Columbia, supra note 47.
269. See generally M
ASAHIRO AKASAKA, RIKKEN KOKKA TO KENPŌ HENSEN [THE
CONSTITUTIONAL STATE AND CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGE] (2008).
506 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
legitimacy. At the end of the day Ackerman’s model is not a theory
for identifying all informal amendments, it is a theory for explaining
why informal amendments that share certain characteristics deserve to
be accepted as being legitimate. That is precisely why there is such an
emphasis on political contestation and expressions of popular
sovereignty in his theory—not as essential elements for determining
whether a constitutional change that exceeds normal interpretive
development is an informal amendment, but as necessary conditions
for such changes to be blessed with the status of legitimacy. The fact
that Ackerman’s model does not fit the Japanese developments does
not negate the reinterpretation’s status as an informal amendment, but
it does mean that Ackerman’s model cannot be a source of support for
claims that the Japanese reinterpretation is a legitimate constitutional
change.
C. Clarifying the Contours of Legitimacy
This brings us directly to the question of how we are to assess
the legitimacy of the reinterpretation, and from there, how we should
think about the legitimacy of informal amendments more generally.
As indicated at the outset, this may depend in part on contingencies
that have yet to unfold, such as how the Supreme Court deals with
challenges to the reinterpretation. But let us assume that the courts
either dismiss any claims on doctrines such as standing, or even,
under a worst/best case scenario, meekly endorses the
constitutionality of the national security legislation. That would not be
dispositive of the legitimacy of the change. There are other factors or
criteria to be considered in assessing its legitimacy.
To begin with, I would suggest that the absence of any
expression of popular will in favor of the change, is a factor that
counts against its legitimacy. It is here that the Japanese case forces
us to look at Ackerman’s model from a slightly different perspective,
and in so doing reveals some potentially under-appreciated value in
his theory. As mentioned earlier, the point from Ackerman’s theory to
be emphasized here, is not that public ratification is a criteria for
defining informal amendment, or that it is a sufficient condition for
the legitimacy of such an informal amendment—but rather, that such
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 507
ratification should be a necessary condition for the legitimacy of any
putative informal amendment.
270
This insight tends to be missed in the criticisms of the theory.
Dow and others have criticized Ackerman’s theory on the grounds
that, contrary to his assertions, it is impossible to meaningfully infer
any expression of popular sovereignty from the elections surrounding
the Reconstruction Amendments or the New Deal policy
developments.
271
But this is first an empirical or factual critique, from
which they then develop a more general normative argument, namely
that one can never attribute sufficiently precise meaning to elections
so as to enable us to learn whether the popular will relates at all to any
given constitutional change. As Dow puts it, “the basic problem with
postulating a theory whereby the political climate yields constitutional
text is that reading electoral politics is only slightly less fatuous than
reading tea leaves.”
272
But none of this means that Ackerman is
wrong in his basic intuition—that absent an expression of popular will
in favor of the putative informal amendment, such a constitutional
change cannot be legitimate. Amar’s theory shares the same intuition,
and goes somewhat further by arguing that informal amendment can
only be legitimate if it is initiated by “we the people”.
273
We may be
inclined to agree with the critics that it is impossible to know whether
any given election actually represents some kind of ratification, and
thus it is not sufficient to endow a constitutional change with
legitimacy—but we could still agree with Ackerman that absent some
expression of public consent the constitutional change surely cannot
be legitimate. In short, what remains sound from Ackerman, even
after the critics are done, is the idea that a clear expression of popular
will in favor of the constitutional change may not be sufficient, but it
is surely necessary. And if this is so, the Japanese reinterpretation
must surely be judged to be illegitimate, at least for now. In this
sense, then, the Japanese experiment may reveal that Ackerman’s
theory retains some considerable value.
270. Tom Ginsburg made a related point in a short essay during the reinterpretation
debate. See Tom Ginsburg, Rearmament and the Rule of Law in Japan: When is it OK to
Change the Constitution with a Statute?, H
UFFINGTON POST (July 22, 2016),
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/tom-ginsburg/rearmament-and-the-rule-o_b_7845402.html.
271. See Dow, supra note 1, at 129-31.
272. Id. at 129.
273. Amar, supra note 1, at 89. Unlike Ackerman, however, Amar denies that the
government can engage in constitutional amendment outside of the Art. V process.
508 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
The second factor of legitimacy that the Japanese developments
bring into stark focus, is that of the deliberate intent on the part of
those trying to effect a constitutional amendment—what I have called
the “deliberate agency” factor. The reinterpretation effort examined
above reflects a degree of deliberation, calculation, and self-
consciousness that is hard to find in any other example invoked in
informal amendment theory. Consider: a public avowal that the
proposed change to a core constitutional provision is dramatic and
unprecedented; the employment of a process of executive
reinterpretation that was a calculated circumvention of the formal
amendment procedure to effect the change, after first attempting and
failing to change the amendment procedure itself; political
interference in the institutions that might block the change; engaging
international law commitments to lock in the change before any
legislative involvement or public debate; unprecedented pressure and
interference in the media to attenuate media criticism; oblique
implementation of the change through revisions to existing
legislation; and, finally, the flagrant disregard for popular and
political opposition—it is an extraordinary illustration of pre-
meditated executive action to effect informal constitutional
amendment, for the very purpose of relaxing the constitutional
constraints on executive action.
Now, there will be some who would suggest that Roosevelt’s
actions were no less pre-meditated and calculating, and that he was
perhaps more disingenuous about the extent to which he understood
that he was trying to alter the constitutional system.
274
But we need
not settle that question here. Regardless of what we decide the
historical record may reveal about Roosevelt’s state of mind and
intentions, the fact is that time has operated to legitimize the changes
in any event—the third factor to which I will turn presently. But the
Japanese case brings the issue of deliberate agency into such stark
relief, virtually demanding that we ask and answer the question: can
274. Ackerman’s theory acknowledges, or even depends upon, a consciousness of
circumvention, but he does not provide the evidence that Roosevelt was deliberately
circumventing the amendment procedure. See Choudhry, supra note 47, at 197-208 (arguing
that Ackerman fails to support the idea of conscious or deliberate circumvention with
historical evidence). See generally A
CKERMAN, supra note 1. But then Dow is also severely
critical about how both Ackerman and Amar engage in a selective and result-oriented use of
history to make their arguments. See Dow, supra note 1, at 135.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 509
an informal amendment so deliberately implemented by a political
branch of government, particularly the executive, as a calculated
circumvention of the formal amendment procedure, ever be legitimate
at the time it was undertaken?
I would suggest that as a theoretical matter such pre-meditated
action to bring about an informal amendment lacks legitimacy ipso
facto. It is one thing to suggest that there may be some reason to
confer some degree of legitimacy upon constitutional changes, even
constitutional “revolutions”, which result from the dynamic
interaction of complex legal, political, and administrative forces, a
process that is inherently unpredictable and not susceptible to control
by any one branch or actor within the system. Even the process of
constitutional revolution through partisan entrenchment described by
Balkin and Levinson lacks the kind of controlled and pre-meditated
manipulation of specific constitutional provisions that is exhibited in
the Japanese case. It is true that in such revolutions the dominant
party, which is trying to entrench its constitutional ideology in the
judiciary through the appointments process, is acting in a self-
conscious and pre-mediated fashion. But Balkin and Levinson note
that overall the process of change that results is organic and
unpredictable, “in precisely the same way as coalitions in
multimember legislatures are unpredictable”.
275
In contrast, for an
executive to single-mindedly circumvent the formal amendment
procedure in order to change a core provision, one that was
specifically designed as a pre-commitment device to constrain the
executive, seems to make a mockery of the basic principles of
constitutionalism and the rule of law.
276
It undermines the normative
power of the entire constitutional system. It represents, in the most
concentrated form, all the problems against which the critics of
informal amendment theory rail. To say that this form of change too
could be legitimate at the time that it is undertaken, without some
other grounds for according it such legitimacy (such as, for argument
sake, a clear and explicit mandate from the people), is simply not to
take the constitution and constitutionalism seriously. As Dow argues,
275. See Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1068-69, 1082.
276. Richard Albert makes a similar argument regarding the illegitimacy of deliberate
attempts to establish constitutional conventions, as a means of circumventing difficult
amendment procedures. See Albert, Constitutional Amendment by Stealth, supra note 46, at
678, 713.
510 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
one has to distinguish between the power to effect change from the
authority to effect change—and by implication, where there was no
authority, there can be no legitimacy for such change.
277
Now, it should be conceded that this argument could lead to
perverse incentives for governments to engage in greater duplicity
and subterfuge. Rather than being transparent and open as Abe has
been in his intentions and his acknowledgement of the nature of the
change, the government could have maintained that the planned
change was nothing more than an incremental evolution in meaning,
entirely consistent with the purpose, text, and history of the provision.
Indeed, one can envision a scenario in which the government avoided
any formal announcement of change along the lines of the Cabinet
Decision, but simply tried to implement changes through revisions to
national security legislation, with assertions that the revisions were
consistent with an evolving understanding of Article 9. The
constitutional system is surely not better served by that kind of
duplicitous government conduct, and yet condemning deliberate and
open efforts at informal change as prima facie illegitimate, would
actually incentivize such conduct and thereby undermine the integrity
of the system—or so the argument would go.
278
My response is that such duplicitous efforts would indeed be just
as illegitimate, and would add insult to injury through the additional
harm caused by the deceit. But it is beside the point. We ought not to
turn our face from calling out the evil of illegitimate government
action because we think it may make the government add deceit to its
sins. The real comparison I want to draw is between the deliberate
and calculated circumvention of the formal amendment procedure on
the one hand, and on the other hand the more organic and dynamic
change that results from the complex interaction of forces among the
different political branches of government, the bureaucracy, civil
society, and the judiciary. This latter form of change, which is more
in line with the kind of dialectic process described by Balkin,
279
and
the administrative constitutionalism described by Strauss,
280
for
instance, is not deliberate in the sense that there is no one entity that
277. See Dow, supra note 1, at 122.
278. My thanks to Rosalind Dixon for raising this issue in the presentation of the
project at the University of New South Wales conference, Aug. 12, 2016.
279. See supra Section I.B.
280. Id.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 511
planned for and orchestrated the change, and set out to circumvent the
amendment procedure in a pre-meditated and calculated fashion. In
this sense, in my view, such changes that occur organically are more
defensible, and have a better claim to some legitimacy, than the
deliberate and calculated change illustrated by the Japanese
reinterpretation. If the government were more duplicitous and covert
in its efforts, it would be harder to determine that it was deliberate and
calculated to be sure, and such duplicity would merit even more
severe criticism and opprobrium. But I do not think that this detracts
from the argument that deliberate efforts at significant constitutional
change are prima facie illegitimate.
Returning to the relationship between the deliberate nature of the
change and ratification by the public, Dow and others argue that even
if the majority of the people were to approve such an informal
amendment it would still be illegitimate. As discussed earlier Dow
and other critics argue that Ackerman and Amar, and other
proponents of the idea that expressions of the popular will can
legitimate informal amendment, are confusing majoritarianism and
popular sovereignty. They point out that the formal amendment
procedures provided for in constitutions like those of the US and
Japan, in requiring super-majorities of one kind or another, reflect the
idea that in the interest of protecting minority rights and entrenching
values, constraints, and pre-commitment devices, compromises to
majoritarian principles must be accepted—and these compromises
were themselves actually accepted in a ratification process that
represented an expression of popular sovereignty.
281
I find these arguments to be quite persuasive and well founded.
Yet I do not propose to resolve that debate here, but want to stake out
a more modest claim, and suggest that it is a claim that should be able
to command broader support than some of the critics’ arguments, and
also add some clarity to our thinking about the contours of legitimacy.
The claim is that it might be conceivable for a very explicit and
unequivocal expression of popular support for an informal
amendment, even one effected by a deliberate and pre-meditated
government effort, to confer some legitimacy upon the change—with
the proviso that changes to fundamental rights would be exempted
281. Dow, supra note 1, at 123-24.
512 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
from this exception.
282
Suppose, for instance, that given the lack of a
two-thirds majority in both chambers of the Diet, the Abe government
had undertaken the changes we have described, but then conducted a
referendum on the very issue of the validity of the changes. It would
not have been in conformity with the Article 96 amending procedure,
but if a majority of the votes cast in the referendum on a clear
question were in favor of recognizing the change, the government
would arguably have a much stronger claim to legitimacy. Note that
this argument relies on a clear referendum on the issue, not a mere
election along the lines posited in Ackerman’s retrospective analysis
of past American changes. It might be argued that if there were such
expressions of popular support, after the kind of open public political
deliberation and contest that Ackerman’s theory contemplates, then in
such a case, but only in such case, a deliberate effort at informal
amendment might have some claim to legitimacy, once having been
so endorsed.
One further proviso to this argument is that to have any claim to
legitimacy, the informal constitutional change so endorsed by the
popular will must also be the kind of change that would have been
legitimate if brought about through the formal amendment process.
Thus far we have been proceeding on the assumption that any formal
amendment is ipso facto legitimate, but this is not necessarily true.
There are a number of theories, primarily in European constitutional
law systems, that suggest that attempts to amend certain fundamental
or core features of a constitution are illegitimate. Richard Albert, in a
forthcoming article, elaborates on such theories to argue that formal
amendments that are “self-conscious efforts to repudiate the essential
characteristics of the constitution” and which are inconsistent with the
constitution’s fundamental purpose and original framework,
constitute a constitutional dismemberment.
283
There is a thread in
282. My exception, if it were to allow for the informal amendment to fundamental
rights on the basis of mere majority vote in a referendum, would of course conjure up all the
issues surrounding Proposition 8 in California; and the arguments of Dow and others that
allowing for such informal amendment would eviscerate a constitution’s protections for
minority rights would be exactly right.
283. Richard Albert, Constitutional Dismemberment (Nov. 25, 2016) (unpublished
article, Boston College Law School Research Paper 424), available at
https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2875931); see also, Y
ANIV ROZNAI,
UNCONSTITUTIONAL CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENTS (forthcoming, 2017) (manuscript on
file with author).
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 513
Japanese constitutional discourse, relying on German constitutional
theory, that suggests that any amendments to Article 9 that
undermined the fundamental constitutional commitment to pacifism
would be impermissible and illegitimate,
284
and Albert picks up on
this in arguing that the current LDP efforts to amend Article 9 would
constitute a constitutional dismemberment.
285
In light of the analysis
of the substance of the reinterpretation above, and the argument that it
is fundamentally inconsistent with the established and accepted
understanding and purpose of Article 9, these theories would provide
one more ground for suggesting that the reinterpretation is
illegitimate. But for now, without delving into that analysis, I simply
flag this further proviso that for an informal constitutional change to
be legitimate, the change would have to have been legitimate if
effected through the formal amendment process.
Such is the relationship between deliberate agency and popular
will. The last factor to be considered is that of time. The most obvious
characteristic of time, as it relates to legitimacy, is that even those
constitutional changes that were hotly contested as being entirely
unauthorized at the time they were made, will gradually become
accepted over time—so long as the change is sustained and it
becomes entrenched. After the passage of sufficient time, they will at
some point enjoy a full measure legitimacy. While we may still
debate the extent to which some of the New Deal innovations were
authorized and legitimate constitutional moves, they have become
part of the constitutional system and so must be treated as legitimate
in practice. The reason for this is obvious, being that over time the
constitutional change becomes the foundation for new law, policy,
and jurisprudence. As it goes from being an innovative constitutional
construction to being the foundation for subsequent interpretation, as
well as the basis for other law and policy, the prospect of trying to
overturn it becomes increasingly costly and practically infeasible, to
the point where it becomes accepted, and eventually recognized as
legitimate. From this we might distil a general principle that informal
amendments will become legitimate with the passage of time. But the
significance of the concept does not end there—there is more to be
said about the concept of time as a factor of legitimacy.
284. See, e.g., ASHIBE, supra note 48, at 365-68
285. Albert, Constitutional Dismemberment, supra note 283, at 11-16.
514 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
Consider the fact that most formal amendments are immediately
legitimate. They require no passage of time whatsoever to exercise a
full claim to legitimacy—precisely because they are promulgated in
accordance with the procedures authorized and mandated by the
constitution.
286
Similarly, interpretive developments that are largely
uncontroversial, which are accepted by all as falling within the range
of possible meanings for the provision in question, likewise command
almost immediate legitimacy. Where the authority for a constitutional
change is apparent and agreed, time is irrelevant to the legitimacy of
the change. Constitutional authority is equivalent to immediate and
corresponding legitimacy. As we move along the spectrum away from
full authority, however, towards more contested interpretive
developments, time will begin to play a role. Authority and legitimacy
may be contested at the outset, and the level of legitimacy will be as
low as the perceived level of constitutional authority at the time of the
change—but if the change is sustained and entrenched, over time it
will have an increasingly strong claim to de facto validity and thus
legitimacy. This is all the more true for informal amendments, where
the legitimacy of the change is even more contested and questionable
at the outset, but may gradually increase over time if the change
remains entrenched. The (limited or even non-existent) formal
authority for the change does not change, but acceptance, de facto
validity, and hence legitimacy, will begin to increase over time. This
may be so even when the apparent legitimacy is a result more of
begrudging acquiescence than genuine acceptance or approval.
287
In
this way we might say that time is what separates legitimacy from
authority. Legitimacy originally flows from, and is coextensive with,
286. Noting, of course, the exceptions referred to earlier, supra note 283. Authors such
as Strauss might argue that this proposition needs to be further qualified somewhat, and that
some amendments, such as the 18th Amendment, were not immediately legitimate. But my
argument is that all formal amendments have at least an immediate claim to legitimacy by
reason that they were promulgated in accordance with formal constitutional authority. See
Strauss, supra note 1.
287. One analogy for this might be a building that is constructed in violation of zoning
or architectural regulations. Over time, as other structures are built alongside and on top of it,
structurally reliant upon it, the cost and difficulty of demolishing or otherwise brining it into
compliance becomes too high, and it comes to be accepted, and subsequent development upon
it is seen as legitimate, even as the absence for initial authority to build it remains apparent.
Thanks to Mahesh Daas for the analogy, and Richard Albert for similar arguments on
acquiescence versus acceptance. See also supra note 54 and Part I more generally.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 515
the constitutional authority, but over time the two concepts begin to
diverge.
If we were to try to conceptualize this graphically, it begins to
look quite different from the model evoked by the traditional
discussion of informal amendments described in Part I. In those
accounts, informal amendments tend to be characterized as being
somewhere in the middle of a simple spectrum, bordered by
legitimate interpretive developments at one end, and formal
amendments at the other—with the form of change developing from
the incremental at one end, through more radical informal change in
the middle, to full formal amendment at the other end. While none of
the accounts develop or explain this spectrum in detail, the inference
is that movement along the spectrum reflects the magnitude of the
changes at any given point, but this tends to be confusing—for while
magnitude increases uniformly from interpretive change through to
formal amendment, authority is weakest in the middle, for informal
amendment.
In the re-conceptualization explored here, however, the focus is
explicitly on legitimacy and authority—with the additional dimension
of time—and this tends to re-order the types of change, and clarifies
the relationships. Thus, we might conceptualize it with authority
forming the X-axis and legitimacy forming the Y-axis, in which
constitutional change would form a linear plot from left to right—the
higher the authority for a constitutional change the higher the
legitimacy, and the lower the authority the lower the legitimacy.
Formal amendment would be at the far right of the axis, and the most
flagrant and questionable efforts at constitutional change at the origin,
with zero authority and zero legitimacy. As changes move left along
the X-axis from the high of formal amendment, meaning that the
constitutional authority for such changes is declining, their legitimacy
on the Y-axis correspondingly declines.
516 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
Fig. 1. – Legitimacy and Authority of Constitutional Change.
Time, however, adds a third dimension to this model. Imagine
that there is a Z-axis that represents the passage of time. Then we
would get a three dimensional figure (which is much more difficult to
visualize or to graph—the figures here are merely two-dimensional
slices of the three-dimensional model), in which changes that had a
low level of both authority and legitimacy at the moment of change,
say T1, would experience an increase in legitimacy as the increment
of time increases, from its low starting point at T1 when legitimacy
and authority exactly corresponded, to a point at T5, when legitimacy
has increased to some robust number, while authority has remained
constant (low or zero) over time.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 517
Fig. 2. – Legitimacy and Authority - Divergence Over Time
This new conceptualization of the relationship among
legitimacy, authority, and time, helps to illustrate a couple of
significant features of the kind of deliberate informal change we have
been discussing. The first is that it illustrates the intuition that the
more unauthorized and illegitimate a constitutional change is at the
outset, the longer the passage of time that will be required for it to
achieve a level of legitimacy for de facto acceptance. This intuition
can be explained by the hypothesis that the more contested a
constitutional change may be, the more heated the opposition and thus
the more resistance there will be to allowing new laws, policies, or
judicial decisions that would depend upon the change as a foundation.
There will, therefore, be some measure of uncertainty and instability
surrounding the change, which will create a drag on the process of it
being legitimated. This in turn will create a longer period of time
during which opponents may try to overturn the change before it
becomes entrenched. Thus, when applied to the arguments above,
This depicts only the Y and Z axes, and thus a different two-dimensional slice of the
three dimensional graph that would include the X and Y axes depicted in Figure 1. The units of
time here could be decades, though of course the increase in legitimacy would not be linear,
uniform, or at the same rate over time for different constitutional changes—both figures are
highly simplified renditions merely designed to help visualize the relationships.
518 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
about the prima facie illegitimacy of the deliberate informal
amendment efforts of the Abe government, we may predict that the
reinterpretation will become legitimate over time, but it is starting at a
lower point and thus should take more time to attain a robust level of
legitimacy and acceptance than some contested interpretive
development arising from a judicial decision.
This re-conceptualization also helps to graphically highlight
another perspective from which to view the illegitimacy of the claim
that deliberate and calculated informal amendment efforts are
effectively trying to make. The architects of the deliberate informal
amendment are in effect attempting to obtain the immediate
legitimacy accorded to formal amendments, while circumventing the
formal amendment procedure itself. It is an attempt to obtain
immediate legitimacy for a change with neither the constitutional
authority that would confer such legitimacy, nor the passage of time
that might confer such legitimacy in the absence of authority.
288
It
provides yet another argument for the proposition that deliberate
efforts at informal amendment lack the necessary prerequisites for
any valid claim to legitimacy, at least at the time they are undertaken.
One last related point needs to be made about how we should
think about the legitimacy of informal amendments. It relates to
questions about the precedential value of past informal amendments
that have gained legitimacy over time. For instance, let us suppose
that we accept that some of the constitutional changes in American
constitutional history were indeed informal amendments, as
Ackerman and others have classified them, but we reject that they
were legitimate at the time they were made—either because we do not
accept that there was any explicit popular ratification of the change,
or because we reject other aspects of the process by which they were
made—but we do recognize and accept that the changes have become
legitimate over time. Could that past change ever be invoked by a
government as a precedent that justifies its current efforts to
implement a constitutional change through a similar process, and in
circumvention of the formal amendment procedure? In other words,
could such justification grounded in precedent weaken or qualify the
argument made earlier, that deliberate and intentional efforts to
engage in informal amendment are prima facie illegitimate? I think
288. My thanks to David Rubenstein for this insight.
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 519
not. Even if we are forced to concede that informal amendments may
occur, and that such past changes may have become legitimate over
time even though they lacked authority and legitimacy at the time
they were made, that provides no justification or authority for
governments who seek to implement such changes in the present. In
sum, explicit ratification may possibly cure the illegitimacy of
deliberate agency, and time will likely legitimate unauthorized
changes, but governments cannot reach back in time for precedents to
justify their deliberate efforts to implement informal amendments. In
concrete terms, Prime Minister Abe cannot invoke Roosevelt’s New
Deal programs (to the extent we think some of those constituted
informal amendments) as a justification for the reinterpretation of
Article 9.
So we are left with the conclusion that a deliberate informal
amendment is prima facie illegitimate, unless, possibly, it is ratified
by a very explicit and genuine expression of popular consent; but that
they will nonetheless be legitimated by the passage of time if they are
not quickly repudiated. It is perhaps a rather depressing conclusion.
But it brings us back to Balkin and Levinson’s argument for the
opposition of high politics. In their discussion of constitutional
revolution through partisan entrenchment, Balkin and Levinson argue
that the best response to such revolutionary change is to criticize the
institutions of change in terms of what they call “high politics”. By
high politics they mean the competing visions of the constitution, its
fundamental values and principles, differing narratives of the nation’s
political and constitutional history, and contested conceptions of who
“we the people” are as a nation.
289
Moreover, the protest and
opposition to the revolutionary change must be made not narrowly at
the institution most directly responsible for the change (the Supreme
Court in their US-based argument), but more broadly to the political
parties, civil society, and the public at large. It is a battle for the hearts
and minds of the nation as a whole. Applying this to the Japanese
context, there may be some time in which to engage in such a battle
of high politics, before the passage of time entrenches and legitimizes
the purported constitutional change to Article 9—but the clock is
running. Time is of the essence.
289. Balkin & Levinson, supra note 1, at 1062.
520 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2
CONCLUSION
This article has suggested that more work needs to be done to
clarify the contours of legitimacy in our thinking about informal
constitutional amendment. The discussion has focused on three
different concepts that I have suggested are factors in determining the
legitimacy of an informal amendment, namely: the extent to which
there is deliberate agency in orchestrating the change; the extent to
which there has been a genuinely contested and explicit popular
ratification of the change; and the passage of time. In considering the
element of time, this examination has suggested that time is one factor
that separates the concept of constitutional authority and that of
legitimacy, as time will tend to legitimize a change even as the
constitutional authority for the change remains constant. This
distinction helps us to re-conceptualize the relationship among
authority, legitimacy and time in thinking about constitutional change,
and provides some support for the hypothesis that even the most
unauthorized constitutional change may become legitimate over time
if it can be sustained.
Using an examination of the Japanese reinterpretation as case
study that brings these issues into stark relief, I have argued that
informal amendments that are undertaken with deliberate intent to
effect what amounts to a constitutional amendment, in a manner
calculated to circumvent the formal amendment procedure, are prima
facie illegitimate at the time. This is in contrast to the kinds of
informal amendments that can arise as unorchestrated and typically
unpredictable consequences of the operation of interrelated and
complex political, policy, legal and popular forces. I have argued that
such deliberate informal amendment might possibly be cured by a
genuine and very explicit expression of popular will, such as a special
referendum on a clear question about the amendment, and only in the
context of genuine political contestation and open public deliberation.
In this regard, the study reveals a possibly overlooked insight in
Ackerman’s theory. While his critics are right that public ratification
is difficult to infer from normal elections, and that public ratification
may not alone be sufficient for legitimacy, it is surely a necessary
condition for the legitimacy of informal amendments at the time they
occur, particularly where they are undertaken with deliberate agency.
Finally, I have suggested that because deliberate informal
amendments suffer from so little constitutional authority and
legitimacy at the time they occur, that both descriptively and
2017] REINTERPRETING JAPAN'S WAR POWERS 521
normatively they should take a longer time than other contested
changes to be legitimized by the passage of time.
522 FORDHAM INTERNATIONAL LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 40:2