93
JUST A JOKE: DEFAMATORY HUMOR
AND INCONGRUITY’S PROMISE
LAURA E. LITTLE
*
Can’t take a joke, eh? A little levity is good for body, mind, and soul,
y’know. Suing over THAT little schoolyard jab? I say you’re either “thin-
skinned or a self-important prig . . . .”
1
I. INTRODUCTION
At what point does a joke become a legal wrong, justifying resort to
defamation law? And at what point must a lawyer tell his or her client to
steer clear of humor—or at least keep jokes focused exclusively on public
figures, officials, and matters of clear public interest? The challenge of
drawing the line between protecting and restricting humor has dogged
United States courts for years. And what a difficult line it is to chart! First,
the line must navigate a stark value clash: the right of individuals and
groups to be free from attack on their property, dignity, and honor versus
the right of individuals to free expression. To make matters more
complicated—in fact, much more complicated—the line must not only
account for, but also respect, the artistry of comedy and its beneficial
contributions to society.
In regulating defamation, American courts deploy a familiar concept
for navigating the line between respecting humor and protecting individual
*
Copyright 2012 held by Laura E. Little, Professor of Law, Temple University’s
Beasley School of Law; B.A. 1979, University of Pennsylvania; J.D. 1985 Temple
University School of Law. I am grateful for the excellent research assistance of Theresa
Hearn, Alice Ko, and Jacob Nemon, as well as the helpful comments of my colleague
Professor Jaya Ramji-Nogales. I owe hearty thanks to Professors David Rolph, Barbara
McDonald, and Sally McCausland for their guidance on Australian defamation law, to
Jessica Milner Davis and Robert Phiddian for their insights on Australian humor, and to
Giovannantonio Forabosco for his general guidance on humor theory. This project
benefitted from faculty colloquia I presented on law and humor at University of Sydney, the
Australian National University, and Flinders University (Adelaide) in January and February
2010—as well as Rutgers University Law School in October 2010. Finally, I am particularly
indebted to Professor Jessica Milner Davis for her support for my research efforts in
Australia.
1. In a classic admonition about libel actions based on ridicule, Judge Learned Hand
declared that “a man must not be too thin-skinned or a self-important prig.” Burton v.
Crowell Publ’g Co., 82 F.2d 154, 155 (2d Cir. 1936) (Hand, J.).
94 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
reputations: the fact/opinion distinction. On one hand, if a joke can be
sorted down the “opinion chute,” then the humorist faces no civil liability.
If, on the other hand, the joke suggests false facts unfavorable to the
plaintiff, defamation liability can attach. Given the complexity and gravity
of the value clash that the fact/opinion distinction seeks to govern, we
should not be surprised that this distinction is not completely up to the task.
While it is an appropriate starting point, the fact/opinion concept needs to
be augmented to accomplish the required balance.
So, what are we to do? There is no quick fix for this problem, and we
need to keep working on it. In the meantime, however, insight comes from
a remote—and arguably unlikely—place: Australia. The remoteness is only
geographic, which provides little problem in today’s high-technology
world. The unlikelihood derives instead from Australia’s ties to the law of
Great Britain, and Australia’s decision so far not to protect or formalize
free speech values to the same extent as the United States. Several factors,
however, make meaningful guidance from Australia possible, not the least
of which is the confluence of two cherished Australian cultural traditions:
plain speaking and a great sense of humor. But I should not overstate the
case here. The Australian cases sometimes yield results that the United
States does not promote. Nonetheless, Australian cases provide a vehicle
for understanding what is at stake in defamatory humor cases and a foil for
identifying a valuable analytical approach.
2
In addition, most of the
Australian cases reach a result quite similar to that reached in cases in the
United States—minus the sometimes distracting and oversimplifying
language of First Amendment exceptionalism. In other words, qualities of
the Australian cases, particularly their straightforward candor and approach
to humor, provide a useful message for U.S. courts.
2. The citations to Australian cases throughout this article are formatted pursuant to
Table 2.2 in The Bluebook. See T
HE BLUEBOOK: A UNIFORM SYSTEM OF CITATION 280–81
tbl.T.2.2 (Columbia Law Review Ass’n et al. eds., 19th ed. 2010). However, where The
Bluebook fails to provide guidance—particularly with unreported Australian cases—the
citations are formatted according to the Third Edition of the Australian Guide to Legal
Citation, published by the Melbourne University Law Review Association. AUSTRALIAN
GUIDE TO LEGAL CITATION 52–55 (Melbourne University Law Review Ass’n ed., 3d ed.
2010), available at http://mulr.law.unimelb.edu.au/go/AGLC3. Pursuant to the Australian
Guide to Legal Citation, pinpoint citations for unreported Australian opinions refer to the
paragraph in the opinion, not a page number implemented by an unofficial reporter such as
WestLaw or LexisNexis; thus if the cited material appears in the first paragraph of the
opinion, the proper pinpoint citation is: “[1].” See id. at 53. Accordingly, an id. citation
referring an unreported Australian case is formatted as: “Id. [1].” In addition, when
quotations employ the Australian or British spellings, we have simply left the spelling as in
the original source rather than Americanizing it or noting the difference with “[sic].”
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 95
Happily, there is another, entirely separate source of guidance for
charting the line between reputation and humor protection: interdisciplinary
research on the humor process. Humor scholars have for centuries
identified important characteristics that tend to make a communication
funny.
3
This scholarship sheds light on when courts tend to use defamation
law to regulate humor, and provides normative guidance on when they
should regulate humor.
Before I get started with the task of mining Australian case law and
interdisciplinary scholarship for insights into how defamation law should
regulate comedy, I should lay on the table certain presumptions and values
that informed my research for this project. The first is my premise that
humor is presumptively beneficial to human society and should be
celebrated. The second premise—a related point—is that humor is
intimately tied to the creative process, which also should be celebrated and
fostered.
While these two premises are uncontroversial as a starting point, they
yield three more contestable, subsidiary presumptions. First is the idea that
the imagination necessary to create humor has a special moral force. I
embrace philosopher John Dewey’s statement that “[i]magination is the
chief instrument of the good. . . [and] is more moral than moralities.”
4
Imagination allows individuals to reach beyond themselves. When
combined with the genuine honesty often imbedded in humor, imagination
can allow humans to achieve a degree of selfless commentary that benefits
both the individual and the collective. My second presumption concerns the
creative source for humor, which I accept as derived from recognition and
appreciation of incongruity.
5
Humor theorists debate this proposition in
3. See Laura E. Little, Regulating Funny: Humor and the Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV.
1235 (2009) for my study using this interdisciplinary work to analyze contract, trademark,
and employment law.
Expanding on the study, this Article extends the interdisciplinary
thinking about humor into several new contexts: defamation law, First Amendment
protections, and transnational/comparative law analysis.
4. J
OHN DEWEY, ART AS EXPERIENCE 348 (1934).
5. See, e.g., P
AUL R. MCGHEE, HUMOR: ITS ORIGIN AND DEVELOPMENT 166–67
(1979) (stating “the production of humorous incongruities in fantasy probably fosters
development of creative thinking”); AVNER ZIV, PERSONALITY AND SENSE OF HUMOR 132
(1984) (“Correlations between humor and creativity are positive and statistically
significant.”) (internal citations omitted); Michael K. Cundall, Jr., Humor and the Limits of
Incongruity, 19 C
REATIVITY RES. J. 203, 204 (2007) ( “[A]s is the case for creativity,
originality is a prerequisite for good humor.”); Tony Veale, Figure-Ground Duality in
Humour: A Multi-Modal Perspective, 4 LODZ PAPERS PRAGMATICS 63, 64 (2008)
[hereinafter Figure-Ground Duality in Humour] (noting that the “cathartic effect” of
separating “layers of meaning” in the creative process “is . . . most keenly experienced and
appreciated in the realm of humorous creativity”).
96 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
their work, which I survey in Part II.
6
Finally, it is my belief that judicial
decisionmaking by necessity requires a court to make choices among value
preferences and that an important mechanism for regulating that process is
maintaining rules and mechanisms that foster judicial candor. When a court
is asked to regulate something as subjective as humor, justice can come
about only through the full disclosure of competing concerns.
American and Australian cases have long recognized the defamatory
potential of jokes. These cases have weaved into their analyses the classic
admonition from an 1831 Irish case: “If a man in jest conveys a serious
imputation, he jests at his peril.”
7
Apparently taking their cue from this
admonition, plaintiffs have energetically pursued defamation remedies for
injuries resulting from diverse types of humor, ranging from cartoons,
songs, and news stories to offhand quips.
8
After a spate of U.S. decisions in
the 1980s dealing with defamatory humor, legal scholars produced several
articles trying to untangle the doctrines courts invoked.
9
Although a steady
flow of the defamatory humor cases continue to make their way into U.S.
6. See infra notes 41–79 and accompanying text for a discussion of the debates
about the role of incongruity in producing humor.
7. Donoghue v. Hayes, (1831) Hayes Ir. Exch. Rep. 265, 266. See also Triggs v. Sun
Printing & Publ’g Ass’n, 71 N.E. 739, 742 (N.Y. 1904) (citing Donoghue’s proposition on
jesting at one’s peril); Salomone v. Macmillan Publ’g Co., 411 N.Y.S.2d 105, 109 (Sup. Ct.
1978) (same), rev’d on other grounds, 429 N.Y.S.2d 441 (App. Div. 1980); Entienne Pty
Ltd. v Festival City Broads. Pty Ltd. (2001) 79 SASR 19, 29 (Austl.) (same).
8. See infra notes 119–128 and accompanying text for a survey of United States
cases and notes 231–250 and accompanying text for a survey of Australian cases.
9. See, e.g., Harriette K. Dorsen, Satiric Appropriation and the Law of Libel,
Trademark, and Copyright: Remedies Without Wrongs, 65 B.U. L. REV. 923 (1985)
(focusing on particular problems of regulating satire); Donna Stricof Kramer, Drawing Fire:
The Proliferation of Libel Suits Against Cartoonists, 5 C
ARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 573
(1986) (surveying suits and suggesting protections for cartoonists); Robert C. Lind, The
Visual Artist and the Law of Defamation, 2 UCLA ENT. L. REV. 63 (1995) (reviewing legal
doctrines governing the visual artist as a defendant and a plaintiff);
Catherine L. Amspacher
& Randel Steven Springer, Note, Humor, Defamation, and Intentional Infliction of
Emotional Distress: The Potential Predicament for Private Figure Plaintiffs, 31 W
M. &
MARY L. REV. 701, 703–04 (1990) (reviewing tort suits based on humor and suggesting “an
analytical method by which courts can hold liable media defendants who, in the name of
humor, egregiously harass, humiliate, or falsely portray private figure plaintiffs”); Kenneth
M. Fitzgerald, Comment, Humor and the Law of Libel: Serious Protections for Attacks
Made in Jest, 40 F
ED. COMM. L.J. 377, 378 (1988) (outlining ways in which the author
believes that humor has achieved “near immunity from the law of libel”); Cary Dee
Glasberg, Case Note, Who Has the Last Laugh? A Look at Defamation in Humor, 9
LOY.
L.A. ENT. L. REV. 381 (1989) (evaluating the decision in Mendelson v. Carson and
proposing standard for evaluating defamation in humor cases); Leslie Kim Treiger,
Protecting Satire Against Libel Claims: A New Reading of the First Amendment’s Opinion
Privilege, 98
YALE L.J. 1215 (1989) (exploring how current First Amendment protections
for humor are inadequate to protect satire).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 97
courts, new legal scholarship on the issue—doctrinal or otherwise—has
dwindled during the new millennium.
10
This Article tries to fill the scholarship gap, using lessons from
interdisciplinary learning on humor and comparative analysis of Australian
cases. To lay the groundwork for the thesis that the fact/opinion distinction
is insufficient for the task of regulating defamatory humor in the United
States, the Article begins with a review of the interdisciplinary scholarship.
It then turns to American legal doctrine, which is grounded in both
common law defamation and First Amendment principles. Next, it reviews
the work of Australian courts, which have navigated the challenges of
defamatory humor largely without resort to any sort of fact/opinion
distinction. Rather, Australian courts have focused on the plaintiff’s harm,
essentially asking whether a jest sufficiently disparages the plaintiff as to
call for civil liability. While certainly not free from problems, this
approach, I conclude, is forthrightly consistent with the central goal of tort
law: repairing a wrong done.
11
As for the important First Amendment
values that need to be balanced against this goal, guidance comes from a
core concept found in interdisciplinary humor scholarship—incongruity.
The end of this Article explores how the incongruity concept helps to
calibrate an optimal balance of First Amendment concerns and the values
of human dignity, property, and honor reflected in defamation law. I
ultimately conclude that courts deciding whether to restrict defamation
liability for a particular communication are well served to evaluate the
communication’s presentation of incongruities.
10. Notable exceptions include: Lauren Gilbert, Mocking George: Political Satire as
“True Threat” in the Age of Global Terrorism, 58 U.
MIAMI L. REV. 843 (2004) (examining
attempts to regulate satire under legal provisions designed to protect national security);
Joseph H. King, Defamation Claims Based on Parody and Other Fanciful Communications
Not Intended to be Understood as Fact, 2008 U
TAH L. REV. 875 (proposing a four-part test
for determining whether a parody is protected opinion); Eric Scott Fulcher, Note, Rhetorical
Hyperbole and the Reasonable Person Standard: Drawing the Line Between Figurative
Expression and Factual Defamation, 38 G
A. L. REV. 717 (2004) (reviewing case law and
proposing a strategy for courts to determine whether a statement qualifies as “rhetorical
hyperbole”).
11. See, e.g., John Gardner, What is Tort Law for? Part 1: The Place of Corrective
Justice, U.
OF OXFORD LEGAL RES. PAPER SERIES 6–7 (Jan. 2010), available at
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1538342 (arguing that corrective justice
is a necessary but not sufficient justification for tort law); John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin
C. Zipursky, Torts as Wrongs, 88
TEX. L. REV. 917, 918–19 (2010) (arguing that the goal of
tort suits is to provide plaintiffs with an avenue for getting redress from those who have
inflicted a wrong on them).
98 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
II. INTERDISCIPLINARY HUMOR SCHOLARSHIP
Humor scholarship spans a myriad of disciplines, with philosophy,
literary theory, sociology, and psychology perhaps best represented. For
analyzing defamatory humor, three components of interdisciplinary humor
scholarship are particularly relevant: (1) inventories of humor types, (2)
theories of how humor operates, and (3) studies of humor’s instrumental
consequences (both beneficial and detrimental). I consider these
components in turn.
A. A
HUMOR INVENTORY
Scholars have invested considerable effort in categorizing varieties of
humor,
12
with major categories including formal jokes, wit, satire, sarcasm,
parody, puns, and practical joking.
13
Formal jokes, practical jokes, satire,
and parody most often serve as the vehicles for alleged defamation. Formal
jokes are “prepackaged humorous anecdotes that people memorize and pass
on to one another . . . .”
14
Practical jokes are normally defined as unkind
“tricks” played on a person.
15
Most commonly occurring in the defamation context are satire and
parody, two forms of humor that scholars often consider together. Both
tend to be aimed at derision,
16
to include ridicule, to operate without
subtlety,
17
and to have a “symbiotic relationship.”
18
As a matter of formal
definition, however, the two are quite separate: parody is “a manipulation
of pre-existing works, usually for comic effect[,]” while satire is “[an]
attack on some irritating aspect of the world.”
19
As these two definitions
suggest, joviality more often accompanies parody than satire, which is
often perceived as having a sharper edge than parody. Another important
12. Scholars have identified as many as twenty-one varieties of humor. Little, supra
note 3, at
1235–81 (surveying interdisciplinary humor scholarship and analyzing regulation
of humor through contract, trademark infringement, and employment discrimination
principles).
13.
JON E. ROECKELEIN, THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR 13 (2002).
14. R
OD A. MARTIN, THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR 11 (2007) [hereinafter THE
PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR].
15. Id. at 126.
16.
ROECKELEIN, supra note 13, at 59–61.
17. See Nicholas Garland, Political Cartooning, in L
AUGHING MATTERS: A SERIOUS
LOOK AT HUMOUR 76 (John Durant & Jonathan Miller eds., 1988).
18. Conal Condren et al., Defining Parody and Satire: Australian Copyright Law and
its New Exception, 13
MEDIA & ARTS L. REV. 273, 279 (2008) [hereinafter Condren 1].
19. Id.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 99
distinction between parody and satire is “intertextuality.”
20
Unlike satire,
parody overlaps with the text serving as the parody’s object. This overlap,
which allows the audience to recognize the original text within the
parody,
21
can occur in characteristics such as the qualities of a particular
genre (for example, poetry or popular song lyrics), or in specific words,
characters, or plot lines (for example, a character that resembles the Star
Wars character Jar Jar Binks, the plot of Goldilocks and the Three Bears, or
words that track Little Bear’s exclamation upon seeing Goldilocks in his
bed).
22
Yet despite parody’s distinctive intertextual quality, many works
exhibit both “parodic form and satiric purpose.”
23
For example, “Jonathan
Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels parodies travel books while also satirising
British politics and European civilisation[,]” and The Simpsons “parodies
TV situation comedy in general while also satirising middle America.”
24
B. M
AJOR THEORIES OF HUMOR
For years the gold standard for explaining what constitutes humor has
had a tripartite structure: superiority, release, and incongruity theories.
25
Scholars have recently expended considerable effort developing new
approaches to explaining why a communication is funny, but the three
classic theories retain considerable dominance. Each possesses a unique
heritage, yet the three are not mutually exclusive, and one can easily
20. SALVATORE ATTARDO, HUMOROUS TEXTS: A SEMANTIC AND PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS
71, 87 (Victor Raskin & Willibald Ruch eds., 2001) (describing parody’s connection to
intertextualism and defining the term: “A text [T1] will be said to have an intertextual
relation to another text [T2] when the processing of T1 would be incomplete without a
reference to T2.”); Peggy Zeglin Brand, Parody, in 3 E
NCYCLOPEDIA OF AESTHETICS 441,
442 (Michael Kelly ed., 1998) (describing intertextualism); Jerry Palmer, Parody and
Decorum: Permission to Mock, in BEYOND A JOKE 79, 81 (Sharon Lockyer & Michael
Pickering eds., 2005) [hereinafter Parody and Decorum] (referring to parody’s quality of
intertextuality).
21. See Parody and Decorum, supra note 20, at 82.
22. A
RTHUR ASA BERGER, BLIND MEN AND ELEPHANTS 74 (1995) (discussing style of
“authorship,” “genre,” and “specific text”).
23. Condren 1, supra note 18, at 279.
24. Id. at 280.
25. See, e.g., Tad Friend, What’s So Funny?, T
HE NEW YORKER, Nov. 11, 2002, at 78,
93 (describing three different theories, and identifying them as “history’s three favorite
comedy theories”). The following is a recent summary of the three theories:
The Renaissance brought Hobbes’s superiority theory (laughter marks the sudden
attainment of power over someone else), which gave way first to Kant’s incongruity
theory (laughter occurs when perceptions don’t conform to logical expectations),
and, finally, to Freud’s release theory (laughter releases pent-up nervous energy.)
Emily Eakin, If It’s Funny, You Laugh, But Why?, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 9, 2000, at B7.
100 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
combine them in explaining why a communication is funny. Indeed, as the
defamation case law reveals, a particular quip or joke often does not parse
naturally into distinct humor categories. Nonetheless, the three categories
of humor remain useful heuristics for analysis. For the purpose of clarity I
describe them separately immediately below.
As shown below, incongruity is a quality that is consistent throughout
humorous communications.
26
If, as I maintain below, the humorous quality
of a communication is relevant to whether the law should expose the
communication to defamation liability, then identifying incongruity in a
communication can play a key role for evaluating whether the
communication is funny and, thus, should be insulated from (or exposed to)
defamation liability. Superiority and release theories also have unique
contributions to understanding humor that focuses on different parts of
human experiences. Contemporary humor theorist Marta Dynel helpfully
explains: whereas incongruity theory focuses on cognitive processing of
jokes, superiority theory highlights social qualities of humor, and release
theory focuses on psychoanalytical phenomena.
27
Accordingly, superiority
and release theory both can shed light on whether humans would perceive a
communication as funny and—ultimately—worthy of insulation from (or
exposure to) legal regulation. Yet because funny communications do not
necessarily always exhibit qualities of superiority or release humor, the
theories take secondary importance to incongruity theory. I explore all
three theories in this section.
1. Superiority Theory
Superiority theory derives from ancient thinkers (Aristotle, Plato,
Socrates, and Cicero) who associated humor with the process of
aggressively disparaging others in order to enhance oneself.
28
Not
26. See infra notes 42–47 for further discussion of this proposition.
27.
MARTA DYNEL, HUMOROUS GARDEN-PATHS: A PRAGMATIC-COGNITIVE STUDY 42
(2009) [hereinafter HUMOROUS GARDEN-PATHS].
28. See, e.g., Antony J. Chapman & Hugh C. Foot, Introduction to H
UMOUR AND
LAUGHTER: THEORY, RESEARCH AND APPLICATIONS 1, 1 (Antony J. Chapman & Hugh C.
Foot eds., 1976) (observing that Cicero and Aristotle believed that laughter derives from
“shabbiness or deformity,” is “degrading” and has no place in the lives of civilized men);
Rod A. Martin, Humor and Laughter, in 4 E
NCYCLOPEDIA OF PSYCHOL. 202, 202–03 (Alan
E. Kazdin ed., 2000) [hereinafter Humor and Laughter]. Socrates advocated for society to
control laughter that “mocks authority” and “notions of truth and beauty.” MICHAEL BILLIG,
LAUGHTER AND RIDICULE: TOWARDS A SOCIAL CRITIQUE OF HUMOUR 41–42 (2005). As for
Plato, he took the view that humor was a weapon deployed by weak individuals when they
perceived themselves unlikely to face counterattack. Dolf Zillman & Joanne R. Cantor, A
Disposition Theory of Humour and Mirth, in H
UMOR AND LAUGHTER: THEORY, RESEARCH
AND
APPLICATIONS 94 (Antony J. Chapman & Hugh C. Foot eds., 1976) [hereinafter A
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 101
surprisingly, English philosopher Thomas Hobbes propounded an equally
negative view of humor; he is often named as the progenitor of superiority
theory itself.
29
Hobbes focused on humor’s association with egocentricity
and power, suggesting that a person finds amusement only if the
communication makes them feel personally successful or superior to
another.
30
Hobbes states in an oft-quoted passage: “Sudden Glory, is the
passion which maketh those Grimaces called LAUGHTER; and is caused
either by some sudden act of their own, that pleaseth them; or by the
apprehension of some deformed thing in another, by comparison whereof
they suddenly applaud themselves.”
31
2. Release Theory
Release theory identifies repressed pleasure
32
or anxiety
33
as humor’s
sources. Scholars credit Sigmund Freud and two English philosophers,
Alexander Bain and Herbert Spencer, with developing the theory.
34
Bain
and Spencer focused on humor’s ability to release nervous energy.
35
As
Bain explained, release results from humor’s embrace of “degradation” or
the “personal pleasure in naughtiness.”
36
Freud imported to this observation
his theory that jokes express taboo desires.
37
Particularly salient to
understanding defamatory humor is the connection Freud draws between
jokes and dreams. Freud hypothesized that both joking and dreaming work
by analogy or allusion, thereby sidestepping logic and literal meaning in
Disposition Theory of Humour and Mirth] (describing Plato’s observation about the
usefulness of the “the weak and helpless” as a “target of ridicule and a risk-free source of
social gaiety”).
29. 2
THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 48 (G.A.J. Rogers & Karl Schuhmann eds.,
Thoemmes Continuum 2003) (1651).
30. Id.
31. Id. According to Hobbes, one commonly finds this tendency in humans who
discern few “abilities in themselves” and “who are forced to keep themselves in their own
favour, by observing the imperfections of other men.” Id.
32. S
IGMUND FREUD, THE JOKE AND ITS RELATION TO THE UNCONSCIOUS (Joyce Crick
trans., Penguin Classics 2003) (1905).
33.
JOHN LIMON, STAND-UP COMEDY IN THEORY, OR, ABJECTION IN AMERICA 39 (2000)
(observing that a joke can release anxiety and fear about such matters as miscegenation and
homoeroticism). See also BILLIG, supra note 28, at 86 (referring to humor’s role in releasing
pressure).
34. Michael Billig traces the theory to a dispute between Bain and Spencer. B
ILLIG,
supra note 28, at 86 (referring to humor’s role in releasing pressure). See also MURRAY S.
DAVIS, WHATS SO FUNNY? 7 (1993) (identifying Freud and Spencer with the theory).
35. B
ILLIG, supra note 28, at 91.
36.
Id. at 93–97.
37. See F
REUD, supra note 32.
102 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
order to elude our conscious minds’ censors.
38
Freud noted jokes’ tendency
to focus on “bawdry” or “sexual facts and relations.”
39
Scholars building on
his work expanded the taboo, or sensitive topics, targeted by release humor
to include excretion, death, disability, and other negative aspects of the
human condition.
40
3. Incongruity Theory
A particular funny communication may or may not exhibit the
humorist’s need to relieve anxiety or express superiority. Yet nearly all
humor theorists agree that incongruity is a necessary condition for a
communication to be humorous.
41
For this reason, incongruity theory is by
far the most important of the three theories for identifying whether a
communication is funny and for evaluating whether its humor justifies
insulating it from legal liability.
Philosophers and other thinkers have long connected humor and
incongruity,
42
tracing the connection to Aristotle’s view of the comic as
derived from surprise and deception,
43
and finding the theory’s intellectual
38. FREUD, supra note 32, at 154 (observing that the technique of jokes includes
similar processes as “dream-work”: “the processes of condensation . . . displacement,
representation by absurdity or by the opposite, indirect representation”).
39. Id. at 92.
40. See, e.g., J
AMES M. COX, MARK TWAIN: THE FATE OF HUMOR vii, xv (Univ. of Mo.
Press 2002) (1966) (arguing that humorists make possible the release of “repressed tension
by exposing “the absence of meaning in existence”); Vassilis Saroglou & Lydwine Anciaux,
Liking Sick Humor: Coping Styles and Religion as Predictors, 17 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR
RES 257, 257– 66 (2004) (demonstrating a correlation between coping styles and
appreciation of jokes about disability, deformity, disease, and death).
41. See infra notes 42–47 and accompanying text for further discussion of this
proposition.
42. As of 1955, at least forty-six authors used the concept of incongruity in describing
and explaining humor. Giovannantonio Forabosco, Is the Concept of Incongruity Still a
Useful Construct for the Advancement of Humor Research?, 4 L
ODZ PAPERS PRAGMATICS
45, 46 (2008) [hereinafter Concept of Incongruity] (citing Wilma H. Grimes, A Theory of
Humor for Public Address: The Mirth Experience, 22 S
PEECH MONOGRAPHS 217, 218
(1955)).
43. Marta Dynel, Introduction to the Special Issue on Humour: A Modest Attempt at
Presenting Contemporary Linguistic Approaches to Humour Studies, 4 L
ODZ PAPERS
PRAGMATICS 1, 1 (2008) (observing that psychological, philosophical, and linguistic
literature observes that humor “invariably arises from incongruity”); Concept of
Incongruity,
supra note 42, at 46 (citing Aristotle’s definition of comic and explaining the
connection with the concept of incongruity). Incongruity theory is also attributed to the
rhetorical question posed by Roman poet Horace:If a painter chose to join a human head to
the neck of a horse, and to spread feathers of many a hue over limbs picked up now here
now there, so that what at the top is a lovely woman ends below in a black and ugly fish,
could you, my friends, if favoured with a private view, refrain from laughing? R
OBERT L.
LATTA, THE BASIC HUMOR PROCESS: A COGNITIVE SHIFT THEORY AND THE CASE AGAINST
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 103
pedigree in the work of philosophers Immanuel Kant and Arthur
Schopenhauer.
44
Although theorists propose a number of incongruity
definitions, they all share a common theme: the notion of joining two or
more otherwise diverse or contrary phenomenon. One theorist, for
example, describes incongruity as “something unexpected, out of context,
inappropriate, unreasonable, illogical, exaggerated,”
45
while others
emphasize joinder of opposites, concluding that incongruity suggests “a
conflict between what we perceive and our expectations.”
46
Despite some
variety in the approach and discussion of subcategories of incongruity,
humor theorists generally embrace the “terminological uniformity”
provided by the words “incongruity theories.”
47
Humorous incongruity manifests in a variety of ways. First,
incongruity can emerge simply because the familiar is placed in a foreign,
unfamiliar context.
48
More commonly, incongruity results from a sudden
altering of a point of view, such as where a humorous setting reflects both
the profound and the mundane
49
or where characters engage in role
reversal.
50
In a related manner, incongruity may result from confusion
about the context in which a term is used. This confusion, coupled with the
process of resolving it, often results in a fun or satisfying mental exercise.
Theorists suggest that the comedy in these techniques derives from surprise
(unforeseen insight), fulfilled expectations, or both.
51
INCONGRUITY 101 (1999) (quoting HORACE: SATIRES, EPISTLES AND ARS POETICA (G.P.
Goold, ed., H. Rushton Fairclough trans., Harvard Univ. Press 1991) (1926)).
44. Little, supra note 3, at 1245
(describing connection of the incongruity theory with
Kant and Schopenhauer).
45. M
CGHEE, supra note 5, at 10. See also Henry W. Cetola, Toward a Cognitive-
Appraisal Model of Humor Appreciation, 1 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 245, 245–46
(1988) (opining that “things that we find funny have to be somewhat unexpected,
ambiguous, illogical, or inappropriate”).
46. John Morreall, Funny Ha-Ha, Funny Strange, and Other Reactions to
Incongruity, in T
HE PHILOSOPHY OF LAUGHTER AND HUMOR 188, 188–89 (John Morreall ed.,
1987). See also J
OHN ALLEN PAULOS, MATHEMATICS AND HUMOR 9 (1980) (infusing the idea
of opposites into defining the element of incongruity in humor).
47. H
UMOROUS GARDEN-PATHS, supra note 27, at 45.
48. H
ENRI BERGSON, LAUGHTER: AN ESSAY ON THE MEANING OF THE COMIC 112
(Cloudesley Brereton & Fred Rothwell trans., Macmillan 1911) (1900).
49. Issac Asimov suggests that humor readily results where the alteration creates an
“anticlimax.” I
SAAC ASIMOV, TREASURY OF HUMOR 1 (1971).
50. B
ERGSON, supra note 48, at 94.
51. Mathematician John Allen Paulos created a taxonomy of “opposites” that are
contained in various humorous incongruities: expectation/surprise; mechanical/spiritual;
superiority/incompetence; balance/exaggeration; propriety/vulgarity. P
AULOS, supra note
46, at
9. See also Patricia Ewick & Susan S. Silbey, No Laughing Matter: Humor and
Contradictions, in Stories of Law, 50 D
EPAUL L. REV. 559, 561 (2000) (reasoning that
104 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
Building on the notion that incongruity works together with both
surprise and fulfilled expectations, several scholars have sought to identify
a general theory of verbal humor based on priming.
52
The priming theory
suggests that humor occurs when a listener is primed with a “script” and
tricked into applying the script in an incongruous situation. This creates an
interpretative difficulty that the listener may resolve only by replacing the
original script with a less obvious or salient one. Take, for example, the
following light bulb joke: “How many X’s does it take to change a light
bulb? 100—one to hold the bulb and ninety-nine to spin the room
around.”
53
In this joke, life experience informs the “primed” script (the
process of twisting a light bulb) and the joke inspires a reformulated script
(the process of twisting the room).
54
Twisting the room appears
incongruous because twisting is generally paired with the light bulb
function.
Thus emerges an important—albeit arguably ironic—insight:
incongruity operates as humor by reference to congruity. Professor
Giovannantonio Forabosco explains that the humor process requires an
“attention-shift . . . in which the project passes from the perception of
congruence to the perception of incongruity and, sometimes, vice versa,
with several shifts.”
55
Professor Tony Veale further explains how incongruity must work
within a field of congruity in order to yield humor using the following
example: “Consider . . . the four most primitive and fundamental drives
guiding the instinctive [behavior] of mammals . . . commonly known as the
humor’s “quality of suspense” results from placing “disparate elements . . . in competition”);
Victor Raskin & Salvatore Attardo, Non-Literalness and Non-Bona Fide in Language: An
Approach to Formal and Computational Treatments of Humor, 2 PRAGMATICS AND
COGNITION 31, 35–37 (1994) [hereinafter Non-Literalness and Non-Bona-Fide in
Language] (discussing a recoil effect and how listeners participate in joke telling by
anticipating and searching for joke ingredients in the speaker’s words).
52. See, e.g., Salvatore Attardo & Victor Raskin, Script Theory Revis(it)ed: Joke
Similarity and Joke Representational Model, 4 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 293, 331
(1991); Figure-Ground Duality in Humour, supra note 5, at 74. Theorist Marta Dynel
describes at least two different uses of incongruity humor that could be tied to the priming
theory. One approach, she maintains, ends with a “surprising red light.” HUMOROUS
GARDEN-PATHS, supra note 27, at 25. This is reflected in the following quip: “War does not
determine who is right but who is left.” Id. at 27. In another example, the priming takes
place in an “ambiguous lead up,” such as in the following example: “She has her looks from
her father. He’s a plastic surgeon.” Id. at 51.
53. Figure-Ground Duality in Humour, supra note 5, at
75.
54. Id.
55. Giovannantonio Forabosco, Cognitive Aspects of the Humor Process: The
Concept of Incongruity, 5 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 45, 60 (1992).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 105
four F’s, namely Fight, Flight, Feeding and Mating. “
56
The incongruity
here is that “mating” is not an “F-word.” Yet the word choice “mating” is
relevant, since it is, after all, a polite term for another F-word that would fit
quite aptly in the list. According to Veale, “We thus see past the
foregrounded Mating to grasp the backgrounded F-word that lies
underneath, and in doing so, preserve the validity of the phrase four F’s.”
57
Furthermore, Veale explains that the joke “relies on the complicity of the
audience, both in their understanding of the speaker’s desire to avoid any
mention of a vulgar word and in their desire to enjoy the frisson generated
by this four-letter Anglo-Saxon expletive.”
58
Consequently, Veale
continues, “the phrasing seems clever and cheeky, making the speaker (and
the audience) simultaneously innocent and guilty of violating a
commonplace taboo.”
59
The process described by Veale and Forabosco was also identified by
earlier thinkers, who characterized humor as making “sense in nonsense”
(Freud’s phrase)
60
or as containing a sort of “limited logic”
61
or “local
logic.”
62
Some thinkers further argue that in order for humor to succeed,
the listener needs to at least partially resolve the incongruities set up in a
humorous statement. The argument posits that without resolution—a return
to congruity after experiencing the joke’s incongruity—the listener’s
discomfort interferes with her perception of the communication as funny.
63
Several empirical studies suggest, however, that incongruity resolution is
not always essential for listeners to find a joke funny and satisfying,
64
particularly listeners with a high tolerance for ambiguity.
65
56. Figure-Ground Duality in Humour, supra note 5, at 73.
57. Id.
58. Id. at 73–74.
59. Id. at 74.
60.
FREUD, supra note 32, at 3–4.
61. Norman R.F. Maier, A Gestalt Theory of Humor, 23 B
RIT. J. PSYCHOL. 69, 72
(1932).
62. Z
IV, supra note 5, at 90. For a description of the mental discomfort inspired by
incongruity, see Benedict Carey, How Nonsense Sharpens the Intellect, N.Y.
TIMES, Oct. 5,
2009, at D1.
63. Forabosco, Cognitive Aspects, supra note 55, at
57 (arguing that without
resolution, “incongruity cannot be . . . used in the humor context” and the listener “would
remain perplexed, confused, disoriented, and perhaps in extreme cases even frightened”).
64. T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 68–73 (describing various studies
regarding the effect of incongruity resolution).
65. See, e.g., Willibald Ruch & Franz-Josef Hehl, A Two-Mode Model of Humor
Appreciation: Its Relation to Aesthetic Appreciation and Simplicity-Complexity of
Personality, in T
HE SENSE OF HUMOR: EXPLORATIONS OF A PERSONALITY CHARACTERISTIC
109, 127 (Willibald Ruch ed., 1998) (finding that tolerance for ambiguity correlates
106 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
A handful of thinkers who are skeptical of incongruity’s essential
relationship to humor provide further discord in contemporary
scholarship.
66
Despite the stridency of their work, the overwhelmingly
dominant view continues to hold that in order for a communication to have
humor potential it needs incongruity.
67
Moreover, a consensus also exists
about a specific, curious aspect of incongruity: some incongruity is simply
not funny. In other words, incongruity may be a necessary condition for
humor, but it is not a sufficient condition. Thus, some incongruities, such
as randomly connected concepts, “poetic metaphors, [and] magic tricks,”
68
positively with appreciation for humor with unresolved incongruity, bizarreness, and
absurdity, while conservative and authoritarian personality traits correlate positively only
with appreciating jokes that resolve incongruity); Willibald Ruch, Assessment of
Appreciation of Humor: Studies with the 3 WD Humor Test, in 9 A
DVANCES PERSONALITY
ASSESSMENT 27, 67 (Charles D. Spielberger & James N. Butcher eds., 1992) (finding that
tolerance for ambiguity correlates positively with appreciation for humor with unresolved
incongruity, bizarreness, and absurdity, while conservative and authoritarian personality
traits correlate positively only with appreciating jokes that resolve incongruity).
66. The most prominent challenge to incongruity’s essential role in the humor process
comes from Professor Gabriella Eichinger Ferro-Luzzi. Although asserting that incongruity
occurs frequently in humor, she maintains that it is not essential to producing humor.
Gabriella Eichinger Ferro-Luzzi, On Necessary Incongruities, 10 HUMOR: INTL J. HUMOR
RES. 117 (1997) [hereinafter On Necessary Incongruities]; Gabriella Eichinger Ferro-Luzzi,
Tamil Jokes and the Polythetic-Prototype Approach to Humor, 3
HUMOR: INTL J. HUMOR
RES. 147, 152 (1990). Other humor scholars take her work very seriously, but believe it to be
insufficiently theorized and insufficiently supported by examples. See, e.g,
ELLIOTT ORING,
ENGAGING HUMOR 8–10 (2003) (arguing that Eichinger Ferro-Luzzi’s analyses of jokes
seem “incomplete or off the mark” and that her examples are “questionable”); Concept of
Incongruity, supra note 42, at 55
(criticizing Eichinger Ferro-Luzzi’s use of a standard
“dictionary-based . . . definition” of incongruity rather than a theory-dependent use of the
term). Robert Latta also launched a broad-ranging attack on incongruity theory. LATTA,
supra note 43, at 99–234. But other humor theorists have vigorously criticized his work as
well. Concept of Incongruity, supra note 42, at 55
(stating that Latta’s “case against
incongruity” has “been radically criticized in a close and tough analysis”); Elliott Oring,
Book Review, 12
HUMOR: INTL J. HUMOR RES. 457, 457–59 (1999) (reviewing ROBERT L.
LATTA, THE BASIC HUMOR PROCESS: A COGNITIVE SHIFT THEORY AND THE CASE AGAINST
INCONGRUITY) (arguing that Latta’s alternative theory is not firmly grounded in
psychological literature and that Latta’s attempt to impose “a strict logical standard” on
incongruity is at odds with the nature of humor). For an intermediate position on the
incongruity debate, see Cundall, supra note 5, at
211 (acknowledging that humor perception
does require “recognition of an incongruity,” but also arguing that incongruity theory
“leaves too much of the act of perceiving humor unexplained”).
67. See, e.g., T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 72 (summarizing current
research and concluding that “some sort of incongruity (however defined) seems to be
necessary for all types of humor”).
68. Tony Veale, Incongruity in Humor: Root Cause or Epiphenomenon?, 17
HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 419, 424 (2004).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 107
may be insightful, quirky, illogical, or “irredeemably absurd,”
69
but not
funny. Take for example the concept of “being hit by a car while walking
on the sidewalk”
70
or arbitrary word pairings such as “tomato/carburetor.”
Incongruous? Yes. Funny? Hardly.
Even so, precisely what makes some incongruities funny and what
makes others not is elusive. Given that identifying incongruity is a key step
in segregating humor from non-humor, the process of trying to pinpoint
what makes certain incongruities funny is important both in a legal context
as well as nonlegal contexts where one might benefit from understanding
the operation of humor. As a starting point, one might say that—to be
funny—incongruities must be “motivated by, and understandable within,
the context of their use.”
71
Scholars have also long identified two other
conditions enabling humor to emerge from incongruity: the incongruity
“take[s] place in a playful and non-threatening context” or “occur[s]
suddenly.”
72
Yet another quality known to enhance comedic effect derives
from the social quality of humor. A listener often knows from a joke
teller’s cue that the joke teller seeks to make them laugh. Through
symbiotic mental cooperation with the joke teller, the listener anticipates
that a punch line is coming, doesn’t know what it will be, and experiences
both fulfillment and surprise when it arrives.
73
Where such conditions are
established, even the most mundane incongruity may give rise to
pleasurable comedic appreciation.
A recently articulated theory argues that humor results from
incongruity where a joke’s “engagement of the incongruity and search for
69. Figure-Ground Duality in Humour, supra note 5, at 73 (explaining how
“incongruity alone does not automatically produce either creativity or humour”). Cf. B
ILLIG,
supra note 28, at 76 (observing that one might conclude that incongruity often accompanies
comedy, but this alone does not “explain why the perception of incongruity should be
followed by a sense of pleasure and laughter”).
70. T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 64.
71. Figure-Ground Duality in Humour, supra note 5, at 73 (citing O
RING, supra note
66).
72. T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 64–65 (summarizing literature on
what “something extra” enables incongruity to be humor).
73. Non-Literalness and Non-Bona-Fide in Language, supra note 51, at 35–37
(analyzing how listeners participate in joke telling by anticipating and searching for joke
ingredients in the joke teller’s words). See also T
ED COHEN, JOKES: PHILOSOPHICAL
THOUGHTS ON JOKING MATTERS 28 (1999) (explaining that shared knowledge or experience
between joke teller and listener can provide a “foundation of the intimacy” that develops if a
joke “succeeds”).
108 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
its appropriateness is spurious rather than genuine.”
74
Professor Elliot
Oring, the proponent of this view, uses the following riddle to explain:
Q: Why should you always wear a watch in the desert?
A: Because a watch has springs (water sources) in it.
75
According to Oring, “springs” and “the desert” have an appropriate
relation because both are characterized by water (or lack of it). In the
riddle, however, the relation is linguistic only—and not legitimate—since
the type of springs that watches have do not give water.
76
If, on the other
hand, the juxtaposition of watch springs and the desert sought to
demonstrate some kind of genuine connection—as in a metaphor—it would
be wholly lacking in humor. That is not to say that this riddle is knee-
slappingly hilarious. The humor is in the nature of a pun, a type of humor
in which “the spuriousness of an . . . incongruity is . . . obvious and
transparent.”
77
This obviousness is why, Oring explains, “puns often elicit
groans rather than laughter.”
78
According to Oring, “Groans register the
recognition of the humor while devaluing it socially and intellectually.”
79
C. I
NSTRUMENTAL CONSEQUENCES OF HUMOR: HIGH PRAISE
Times are good for the joke. And no wonder—jokes have special
communicative potency and therapeutic effect, and foster human
organization. A good joke can build a human relationship and provide a
great deal of fun, pleasure, and happiness. Indeed, in this atomistic,
sometimes alienating era, humor (and its beneficial consequences) has a
particularly significant role to play for both individuals and collective
entities.
80
This potential is not lost on the world’s thinkers. They do,
however, measure their praise carefully. With some exceptions, social and
natural scientists as well as humanities theorists find the greatest value in
humor that is high in incongruity, mixed value for jokes associated with
74. ORING, supra note 66, at 5.
75. Id. at
3 (quoting MCGHEE, supra note 5, at 131–33).
76. Id. at
6.
77. Id. at
7.
78. Id.
79. Id. Oring further suggests that humor is labeled corny where it “flagrantly displays
its spurious devices.” Id. at 7.
80. See generally R
OBERT D. SACK, SACK ON DEFAMATION: LIBEL, SLANDER &
RELATED PROBLEMS § 5:5.2[G][1] (3d ed. 1999) (“Humor is an important medium of
legitimate expression and central to the well-being of individuals, society, and their
government”).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 109
release humor, and frequent problems with superiority humor.
81
Scholars
scrutinize humor’s double-edged quality, but expend most of their effort
cataloguing its positive consequences.
82
Why does all this matter to defamation cases? To begin, the primary
enterprise of law is of course to regulate human interaction. Within the
specific context of defamation, this regulation must account for sometimes
conflicting individual liberties (freedom of expression versus reputation
and human dignity) as well as collective social benefits of criticism that
might clash with individual reputational rights. I explore these matters in
detail in the Part IV below. As I will illustrate, the task of balancing the
various interests is particularly challenging in the context of humorous
communications that are alleged defamatory. As preparation for
understanding the interests relevant to this balance, we must heed the work
of nonlegal scholars in identifying humor’s individual and social
consequences.
1. Humors Consequences for Individuals
For individual well-being, scholars cast humor as an effective coping
device, which can afford altered and empowering perspectives to persons
confronting fearful, sad, or angry situations.
83
Studies document that humor
reduces stress by moderating stress-related emotions and physiological
changes.
84
81. See, e.g., MICHAEL BILLIG, LAUGHTER AND RIDICULE: TOWARDS A SOCIAL
CRITIQUE OF HUMOUR 57–85, 158-68 (2005) (describing connections among incongruity
humor, high social rank, education, and “gentlemanly laughter” and explaining both benefits
and dangers that Freud identified in “tendentious” humor concerning taboo topics); Nicholas
H. Kuiper et al., Humor s Not Always the Best Medicine: Specific Components of Sense of
Humor and Psychological Well-Being, HUMOR:INTL J. HUMOR RES. 135, 139–41 (2004)
(describing psychological analysis of humor based on superiority, which tends to be
“boorish,” based on a “mean-spirited and sarcastic style of poking fun at others,” and
“maladaptive”).
82. See Little, supra note 3, at 1252–54 (reviewing interdisciplinary scholarship
analyzing beneficial aspects of humor).
83. Kimberlianne Podlas, Respect My Authority! South Park’s Expression of Legal
Ideology and Contribution to Legal Culture, 11 V
AND. J. ENT. & TECH. L. 491, 512 (2009)
(“‘Comic relief’ can reduce anxiety associated with disconcerting topics and provide a safe
harbor in which to reaction to them.”); C
OHEN, supra note 73, at 40–41 (arguing that
laughing allows us to accept our limitations and to process “devastating and
incomprehensible matters”); Humor and Laughter, supra note 28, at 203 (noting how humor
alters perspective and increases coping abilities).
84. Humor and Laughter, supra note 28, at 204 (describing physiological and
emotional changes resulting from humor); R
OECKELEIN, supra note 13, at 58 (describing
how comedians transform tragedy into something pleasant and funny).
110 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
One particularly positive consequence is humor’s role in forging
social bonds among people. As described above, the joke-telling process
links the joke teller with the listener as they experience the joke unfold.
85
Moreover, shared humor often inspires a feeling that one is part of an
“intellectual in-crowd,” making listeners feel less defensive and more
positive about themselves.
86
This is particularly true for humor based on
previously shared experiences, or inside jokes.
87
Analysis of parody
suggests that a similar process occurs for collective audiences before whom
parody is performed or published; true parody works only with that part of
the audience that possesses preexisting knowledge of the parody’s object.
88
The verdict is more mixed for humor’s health effects, with studies
revealing an uncertain link between robust health and humor. Scholars for
many years proposed that laughter promoted beneficial emotional states
and decreased stress,
89
yet actual empirical support for a positive link
between humor and good physical health could be stronger.
90
One problem
in establishing the connection is the difficulty of distinguishing between the
85. See supra footnotes 73 and accompanying text for discussion of the dynamic
between joke teller and listener.
86. Katrina Triezenberg, Humor Enhancers in the Study of Humorous Literature, 17
HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 411, 413 (2004). See also Cundall, supra note 5, at 210
(explaining a joke-transaction theory under which jokes require “shared knowledge of the
subject matter and the notion of community”).
87. COHEN, supra note 73, at 40–41 (explaining that where a joke teller and listener
share a joke’s background, a “foundation of intimacy” can develop between them).
88. See, e.g., ATTARDO, supra note 20, at 87 (describing parody’s connection to a
preexisting text); Brand, supra note 20, at 442 (describing the interrelationship between
parody and preexisting text); Parody and Decorum, supra note 20, at 81.
89. Rod A. Martin, Sense of Humor and Physical Health: Theoretical Issues, Recent
Findings, and Future Directions, 17 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 1, 4–5 (2004). For a
more detailed review of this literature and its nuances, see T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR,
supra note 14, at 309–33.
90. See Nicholas Kuiper & Sorrel Nicholl, Thoughts on Feeling Better? Sense of
Humor and Physical Health, 17 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 37, 38 (2004) (reporting
that empirical evidence is “surprisingly weak” for the hypothesis that a greater sense of
humor is linked to better health). Significant support does exist, however, for the proposition
that humor increases pain tolerance. See, e.g, Karen Zweyer, Barbara Velker & Willibald
Ruch, Do Cheerfulness, Exhilaration, and Humor Production Moderate Pain Tolerance? A
FACS Study, 17 HUMOR:
INTL J. HUMOR RES. 85, 86–92 (2004) (describing past literature
on the correlation and reporting the results of a study in which pain tolerance increased after
watching a “funny film”); T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 331 (“[O]f all the
health benefits claimed for humor and laughter, the most consistent research support has
been found for the hypothesized analgesic effects.”).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 111
effects of humor and the effects of other positive emotions or effects, such
as mirth, playfulness, and optimism, which often accompany humor.
91
A common approach to the literature on the humor/health connection
distinguishes among humor styles, often using a binary matrix separating
“adaptive” humor styles from “maladaptive” humor styles.
92
Not
surprisingly, scholars often denominate superiority humor as maladaptive,
associating it with depression, anxiety, and aggressiveness.
93
By contrast,
they correlate socially adaptive humor with reduced anxiety and
depression, as well as increased self-esteem.
94
Empirical findings are
nuanced, however, suggesting that the effects of different humor vary
according to context. Thus, lighthearted humor (such as incongruity humor
and witticisms) might best enable the staff of a mental health facility to
deal with the challenges of the mentally ill.
95
By contrast, aggressive
superiority humor may be a more effective survival mechanism for
concentration camp prisoners.
96
As such, the adaptive/maladaptive formula
may be oversimplistic, since negative or superiority humor can result in
positive consequences, such as relieving one’s own stress
97
and bolstering
one’s own self-esteem,
98
while at the same time destroying personal
relationships and eliminating social support structure.
99
91. See, e.g., Jaak Panksepp & Jeff Burgdorf, “Laughing” Rats and the Evolutionary
Antecedents of Human Joy?, 79
PHYSIOLOGY & BEHAV. 533 (2003) (noting that positive
emotions such as joy and love may share the same brain circuits as humor).
92. See, e.g., Sense of Humor and Physical Health, supra note89, at 14 (describing a
“multidimensional approach” that differentiates aspects of humor that “are potentially
beneficial to well-being” from “those that are potentially detrimental”).
93. See, e.g., Nicholas A. Kuiper et al., Humor is Not Always the Best Medicine:
Specific Components of Sense of Humor and Psychological Well-Being, 17 HUMOR: I
NTL
J. HUMOR RES. 135, 135, 139–141 (2004).
94. Id. at 135–36,
160–62.
95. See, e.g., Joan Sayre, The Use of Aberrant Medical Humor by Psychiatric Unit
Staff, 22
ISSUES MENTAL HEALTH NURSING 669, 672 (2001) (suggesting that aggressive
humor toward patients may “create a nontherapeutic distancing from patient” and promote
cynicism and morale problems among psychiatric staff).
96. T
HE PSYCHOLOGY OF HUMOR, supra note 14, at 288–306 (2007) (summarizing
studies of context dependency on mental health effects of different humor types, including
report on humor evidenced in World War II concentration camps). The prevalence of
aggressive humor in the context of severe hardship, such as a concentration camp, may be
explained by the need to develop a form of hard-heartedness or a “suspension of sensibility”
necessary to cope with “the hostile and cruel content of many funny stories.” Concept of
Incongruity, supra note 42, at
56.
97. This is, after all, the underpinning of Freud’s theory of tendentious wit. F
REUD,
supra note 32, at 91–106 (cataloguing the function of “tendentious” jokes to release tension
about sex and excrement, hostilities toward others, and cynicism about social forces).
98. Lawrence La Fave, Jay Haddad & William A. Maesen, Superiority, Enhanced
Self-Esteem, and Perceived Incongruity Humour Theory, in H
UMOUR AND LAUGHTER:
112 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
2. Humors Consequences for Groups
Thinkers from many disciplines herald humor’s potential to contribute
to civilization on an aggregate level, enhancing both society and culture.
Throughout society, we celebrate humor as an art form and important
expressive mode.
100
Sociologists, anthropologists, folklorists, and others
find the raw material of humor crucial for studying and understanding
cross-cultural differences.
101
And, of course, humor has a key role in
regulating social norms, enabling powerful expressions of disapproval and
approval through gradations of wit ranging from sugar-coated quips to acid
barbs. In this way, humor provides a mechanism for social commentary—
allowing a commentator to “tell[] the truth with a laugh.”
102
As it does with individuals, negative humor can have subtle and
apparently contradictory effects on groups. Sharing or observing a
humorous repartee over words can assist a group in establishing or
exchanging their identity.
103
A group can reinforce its own identity by
sharing negative humor about its superiority to others, often at the expense
of others.
104
Likewise, humor can perform the apparently inconsistent role
of enabling “collaborative”
105
resolution of social tensions, while also
THEORY, RESEARCH, AND APPLICATIONS 63, 86 (Anthony J. Chapman & Hugh C. Foot eds.,
1976).
99. Sense of Humor and Physical Health, supra note89, at 16 (discussing the double-
edged relationship between humor and health).
100. Folklorist Elliott Oring, for example, describes his view on humor as follows: I
consider jokes and other forms of humorous expression to be meaningful and sometimes
significant communications. I also believe humorous expressions to be art. Some jokes are
truly beautiful, and those who create them, reshape them, and orally purvey them are often
genuine artists . . . . Humor and laughter are cultural universals. They are a condition of
humanity. Humor could be considered trivial only from a perspective that holds humanity
itself to be trivial.
ORING, supra note 66, at ix–x.
101. Examples are legion. Recent works spanning many different cultures include
C
HRISTIE DAVIES, JOKES AND THEIR RELATION TO SOCIETY (1998) (exploring jokes in a
number of cultures, including Polish, Chinese, Japanese, Irish, British, Australian, and
Palestinian); G
ISELINDE KUIPERS, GOOD HUMOR, BAD TASTE: A SOCIOLOGY OF THE JOKE
(2006) (exploring jokes in the context of primarily Dutch and United States culture).
102. H
ORACE, SATIRES § I.1.25–26 (P. Michael Brown trans., Aris & Phillips 1993).
103. Beth A. Quinn, The Paradox of Complaining: Law, Humor, and Harassment in
the Everyday Work World, 25 L
AW & SOC. INQUIRY 1151, 1165 (2000) (observing how the
insider humor resulting from a “common history of word play” can help establish group
solidarity).
104. See id. at 1165 (noting how a group can define itself by “degrading those who are
outside”) (emphasis added).
105. M
ICHAEL MULKAY, ON HUMOUR: ITS NATURE AND PLACE IN MODERN SOCIETY
152–53 (1988) (analyzing humor and social structure).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 113
damaging community structure by providing a platform for communal
“inconsistencies and irrationalities.”
106
This contradictory potential provides an especially challenging puzzle
in understanding the group dynamics of stereotype and discrimination. One
can easily imagine how humorous taunting based on racial, ethnic, or
gender characteristics can libel an entire group. Yet the taunting can
backfire by either overplaying or undermining the stereotypes that it trades
on.
107
Additionally—as in the circumstance where a group appropriates for
itself a derogatory term used by others to name the group—humor can suck
the power out of stereotypes. Humor can release inhibition or tension
related to group differences. As such, even negative humor is a positive
instrument for members of a disempowered group to assert themselves.
108
How does humor accomplish this? At least a partial explanation lies in
humor’s invitation for people to let down their guards and to reduce their
cognitive and emotional resistance to what others are saying.
109
As a result
of its defense-lowering potential, humor can provide a “safe harbor” for
individuals and groups to process sensitive subject matter.
110
Examples of two group contexts where scholars recognize humor’s
significant positive potential are education and the workplace. Recent
trends in education promote humor to raise student interest and reduce
anxiety about learning. Although empirical studies on the actual effect of
humor on learning are relatively sparse, research does suggest that
moderated humor in the classroom increases student interest, enjoyment
level, and perception of how much they learn.
111
As for joking in the
workplace, scholars recognize that superiority humor can damage
106. Id.
107. J
OSEPH BOSKIN, REBELLIOUS LAUGHTER: PEOPLES HUMOR IN AMERICAN CULTURE
38 (1997) (describing humor’s apparently contradictory potential of reinforcing “pejorative
images” and inverting stereotypes).
108. See, e.g., Charles Winick, The Social Contexts of Humor, 26 J.
COMM. 124, 126–
28 (1976) (describing how groups use humor to manage power conflicts); C
OHEN, supra
note 73, at 44 (describing how the disempowered often joke about their oppressors).
109. Podlas, supra note 83, at 512 (arguing that humor lowers “emotional (and
intellectual) defenses, thereby avoiding resistance” of listeners).
110. Id. (suggesting that humor creates this “safe harbor” by reducing anxiety).
111. Melissa Bekelja Wanzer & Ann Bainbridge Frymier, The Relationship Between
Student Perceptions of Instructor Humor and Students’ Reports of Learning, 48 C
OMM.
EDUC. 48, 55 (1999) (reporting on positive correlation between humor on one hand and
student enjoyment and learning perception on the other hand); Stephen B. Fortson &
William E. Brown, Best and Worst University Instructors: The Opinions of Graduate
Students, 32 C.
STUDENT J. 572, 573 (1998) (identifying correlation between teacher humor
and student opinions of their effectiveness).
114 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
cohesiveness and—when egregious—significantly damage employment
conditions for minority group members and women.
112
Nonetheless,
scholars identify humor’s substantial contributions to forging bonds
between coworkers, developing organizational identity, and enabling
employees to negotiate hierarchical relationships.
113
Lawsuits based on defamatory humor appear to occur more often in
the workplace
114
than in the educational context.
115
Even so, the results of
all defamatory humor suits that make their way into the court system send
an important message about the limits of appropriate humor deployed in all
group settings, including education and employment. I, thus, turn to a
general review of defamation suits that have the effect of regulating humor.
III. DEFAMATION LAW, THE FIRST AMENDMENT, AND HUMOR
REGULATION
Courts regulate humor all the time. The most obvious examples are
the criminal cases where courts decide whether to punish for joking about
112. For example, sexual harassment employment discrimination claims under 42
U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a) (2006) (Title VII) are often premised on a pattern of harassing humor.
In fact, the United States Department of Labor released a pamphlet admonishing that
actionable discrimination can result where a coworker’s sexual jokes make it hard for a
plaintiff to work. Sexual Harassment: Know Your Rights, U.S.
DEPT OF LABOR (1994),
available at http://www.empowermentzone.com/harass.txt. For a critique of the social
ramifications of this pamphlet, see DAVID E. BERNSTEIN, YOU CANT SAY THAT! THE
GROWING THREAT TO CIVIL LIBERTIES FROM ANTIDISCRIMINATION LAWS 26 (2003)
(describing the aforementioned pamphlet and taking the position that the hostile
environment sexual harassment law violates free speech principles); Eugene Volokh, What
Speech Does “Hostile Work Environment” Harassment Law Restrict?, 85 G
EO. L.J. 627,
633–37 (1997) (citing the pamphlet and arguing that sexual harassment law suppresses
“core protected speech”).
113. See, e.g., J
ERRY PALMER, TAKING HUMOUR SERIOUSLY 59 (1994) [hereinafter
T
AKING HUMOUR SERIOUSLY] (observing that humor “functions to ease tensions caused by
the contradiction between hierarchy and collegiality”); Joseph Alan Ullian, Joking at Work,
26 J.
COMM. 129, 129 (1976) (analyzing how banter and joking help organizations remain
stable in the face of change); Humor and Laughter, supra note 28, at 203 (noting humor’s
ability to strengthen human relationships and provide enhanced feelings of closeness within
working environments).
114. For a review of cases, see John Bruce Lewis & Gregory V. Mersol, Opinion and
Rhetorical Hyperbole in Workplace Defamation Actions: The Continuing Quest for
Meaningful Standards, 52 D
EPAUL L. REV. 19, 56–73 (2002).
115. Possible liability arising out of social networking sites may provide fertile ground
for such defamatory humor cases related to the school environment. In the meantime, there
are plenty of non-humor defamation cases arising in the context of education—with
Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1 (1990), being a prominent example. Milkovich
was a defamation suit based on alleged perjury by a high school wrestling coach.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 115
such matters as shooting the president
116
or bombing an airplane.
117
Courts
also regulate humor directly when asked to enjoin communication, such as
a song parody.
118
More indirectly, courts regulate humor when evaluating
civil liability claims, which can derive from humor-inflicted injury in a
broad range of contexts, such as contract, trademark infringement, and
employment discrimination, to name a few. Where a court endorses civil
liability, the resulting damage verdict sends a deterrent message to others
who consider making a similar joke. Tort actions to remedy dignitary
harms is one context in which plaintiffs frequently request that courts
impose damages and thereby send this deterrence message for hurtful
jokes.
119
Of all the dignitary harms, defamation is probably the most
common theory plaintiffs invoke to remedy hurt flowing from a joke.
When asked to regulate humor in the civil justice context, United
States courts occasionally acknowledge humor’s individual and social
benefits, which a damage judgment could discourage or undermine.
120
In
116. See 18 U.S.C. § 871 (2006) (criminalizing threats against the President); Watts v.
United States, 394 U.S. 705, 706–08 (1969) (finding that the defendant’s remarks did not
violate 18 U.S.C. § 871, and stressing the context of the remarks and that listeners reacted
with laughter).
117. See 49 U.S.C. § 46507 (2006) (criminalizing false information and threats in the
context of aviation); United States v. Cothran, 286 F.3d 173, 176 (3d Cir. 2002) (finding
that “[a] bad joke” could violate 49 U.S.C. § 46507). See generally Gilbert, supra note 10, at
864–66 (describing jokes ridiculing the Bush Administration that were subject to Secret
Service investigation).
118. See, e.g., Austl. Broad. Corp. v Hanson [1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998)
(Austl.) (enjoining as defamatory a song parody of a Member of the Queensland House of
Representatives).
119. Dignitary harms in which humor is frequently at issue include defamation, false
light, and invasion of privacy. Sometimes, right of publicity (which concerns a person’s
right to protect the commercial value of her or his own name) is also included in the list of
dignity harms. This right also arises in the humor context, particularly in the context of
parody and satire.
120. See, e.g., White v. Samsung Elecs. Am., Inc., 989 F.2d 1512, 1519 (9th Cir. 1993)
(asserting that “[p]arody, humor, irreverence are all vital components of the marketplace of
ideas”); L.L. Bean, Inc. v. Drake Publishers, Inc., 811 F.2d 26, 32 (1st Cir. 1987) (stating
that parody is “deserving of substantial freedom—both as entertainment and as a form of
social and literary criticism” (quoting Berlin v. E.C. Publ’ns, Inc., 329 F.2d 541 (2d Cir.
1964))); Elsmere Music, Inc. v. Nat’l Broad. Co., 623 F.2d 252, 253 (2d Cir. 1980) (per
curiam) (rejecting a copyright infringement claim, and proclaiming the belief “that, in
today’s world of often unrelieved solemnity, copyright law should be hospitable to the
humor of parody”); McIntyre v. Manhattan Ford, Lincoln-Mercury, Inc., 669 N.Y.S.2d 122,
124 (App. Div. 1997) (noting in the context of an employment discrimination case that
“good-natured [humor] . . . may relieve the tensions imposed by the pressures of daily life”);
Salomone v. Macmillan Publ’g Co., 411 N.Y.S.2d 105, 109 (Sup. Ct. 1978), rev’d on other
grounds, 429 N.Y.S.2d 441 (App. Div. 1980) (declaring that “[w]ithout humor[—]the
ability to recognize the ridiculous in any situation[—]there can be no perspective”).
116 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
connection with discussing humor’s advantages, courts sometimes (but not
always) frame their concerns in terms of free speech values. One area
where freedom of expression consistently features prominently in United
States cases, however, is defamation. This is unsurprising, given the long
established linkage between the First Amendment and defamation law, and
the repeated efforts of the United States Supreme Court to calibrate a
careful balance between reputational and free speech values.
121
In this section, I review efforts in the United States to use First
Amendment doctrine to limit the reach of state defamation actions
regulating humor, starting first with the basics of defamation liability and
then moving on to First Amendment case law. I critique the primary
doctrinal technique that United States courts use to accomplish this task,
specifically the fact/opinion distinction, and show its limitations. I then
survey Australian defamatory humor cases and glean lessons for United
States courts.
A. U
NITED STATES DEFAMATION LAW
Defamation is a tort theory designed to protect an individual’s interest
in preserving personal reputation.
122
As it is formally defined under state
common law in the United States, a defamatory statement “tends so to
harm the reputation of another as to lower him in the estimation of the
community or to deter third persons from associating or dealing with
him.”
123
The standard elements of the defamation cause of action, however,
require not only that the plaintiff show that a statement is defamatory, but
121. While not the first case concerning defamation and the First Amendment, New
York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964), stands as the beginning of the Court’s
contemporary efforts to strike this balance. See generally ERWIN CHEMERINSKY,
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: PRINCIPLES AND POLICES 1045 (3d ed. 2006) (citing NewYork Times
Co. v. Sullivan as the beginning of the Court’s effort to “balance the need to protect
reputation . . . with the desire to safeguard expression”).
122. In an influential law review article, Robert Post observed that reputation is a
complex concept and that defamation law has sought to protect a least three aspects:
“reputation as property, as honor, and as dignity.” Robert C. Post, The Social Foundations
of Defamation Law: Reputation and the Constitution, 74 C
ALIF. L. REV. 691, 693 (1986).
123. R
ESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 559 (1977). The state law landscape of
defamation law is relatively uniform. To the extent that variation exists in this area, the law
of New York and California is most pertinent to this paper, since these two entertainment
capitals generate the most defamatory humor opinions. Sometimes, states provide a fuller
picture of what constitutes defamation than the bare-boned Restatement defamation. See,
e.g., Frank v. Nat’l Broad. Co., 506 N.Y.S.2d 869, 871 (App. Div. 1986) (stating that
defamatory speech tends to expose the plaintiff “to public contempt, ridicule, aversion or
disgrace, or induce an evil opinion of him in the minds of right-thinking persons, and to
deprive him of their intercourse in society” (quoting Sydney v. MacFadden Newspaper
Publ’g Corp., 151 N.E. 209, 210 (N.Y. 1926))).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 117
also that the statement is false.
124
Here lies the problem with regulating
defamatory humor: it does not fit easily into the paradigm of truth and
falsity. Humor is by definition not “serious,” thus suggesting that it
operates outside the realm of anything one could verify. Yet—as a
society—we also know that “many a truth is said in jest.”
United States courts and commentators have taken a variety of
approaches to the problem of fitting the round peg of humor into the square
hole of defamation. Some have said that at least one type of humor—
parody—is not capable of being defamatory, reasoning that defamation is
“mutually exclusive of parody.”
125
Some have alluded to the notion that all
humor deserves immunity from liability.
126
124. The Second Restatement sets forth the actual elements of defamation as follows:
To create liability for defamation there must be:
(a) a false and defamatory statement concerning another;
(b) an unprivileged publication to a third party;
(c) fault amounting at least to negligence on the part of the publisher; and
(d) either actionability of the statement irrespective of special harm or the existence
of special harm caused by the publication.
R
ESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 558 (1977).
125. 50 A
M. JUR. 2D Libel and Slander § 156 (2011). Here is the full statement of this
position:
By definition, defamation requires a false statement of fact; parody, to the degree it
is perceived as parody by its intended audience, conveys the message that it is not
the original and, therefore, cannot constitute a false statement of fact . . . . If a
parody could be actionable because, while recognizable as a joke, it conveyed an
unfavorable impression, very few journalistic parodies could survive. It is not for the
court to evaluate a parody as to whether it went too far, for the purposes of a libel
claim; as long as it is recognizable to the average reader as a joke, it must be
protected or parody must cease to exist.
Id. (footnotes omitted). The Indiana Court of Appeals specifically adopted this approach in
Hamilton v. Prewett, 860 N.E.2d 1234, 1244 (Ind. Ct. App. 2007). The court first
acknowledged that a humorous statement could be defamatory. Id. at 1245 (“A defendant
who couches a defamatory imputation of fact in humor cannot simply avoid liability by
dressing his wolfish words in humorous sheep’s clothing.”). The court nonetheless
identified parody as “another beast that goes beyond mere humor”). See also Garvelink v.
Detroit News, 522 N.W.2d 883, 887 (Mich. Ct. App. 1994) (stating that “even if the writer
is motivated by hatred or ill” a parody is still not to be actionable because it is “in the area of
public debate concerning public officials”).
126. For example, Robert Sack argues:
Although perhaps annoying or embarrassing, humorous statements will typically
have no substantial and permanent impact on reputation and therefore ought not to
be held to be defamatory. Incidental jibes and barbs may be humorous forms of
epithets or “mere name-calling” and are not actionable under settled law governing
such communications. And it is on these bases that most humor cases are decided.
Humor is usually understood to be humor and to convey no serious, objective factual
allegations about its target. Although perhaps annoying or embarrassing, humorous
118 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
The more common approach, however, has been for courts to
differentiate humor that merits defamation liability from humor that does
not. The common law privilege of fair comment long performed this
sorting process, insulating criticism relating to “matters of public concern”
from liability.
127
As lower courts applied this privilege, they also made a
distinction between humorous assertions that were based on fact (which
were actionable) and assertions based on opinion (which were not
actionable). The distinction developed into an important common law
concept. Courts further refined the concept, and the Restatement (Second)
of Torts
now provides that “‘[a] defamatory communication may consist of
a statement in the form of an opinion, but a statement of this nature is
actionable only if it implies the allegation of undisclosed defamatory facts
as the basis of the opinion.’”
128
The United States Supreme Court also found use for the distinction in
First Amendment doctrine; indeed, it is likely neither possible nor fruitful
to segregate constitutional and common law sources of the fact/opinion
distinction.
129
For common law purposes, however, it is important to note
that the comments to Restatement (Second) section 566 specifically apply
the fact/opinion distinction to humor, stating that “[h]umorous writings,
verses, cartoons or caricatures that carry a sting and cause adverse rather
statements will have no substantial impact on reputation and therefore ought not to
be held to be defamatory. Incidental jibes and barbs may be humorous forms of
epithets or “mere name-calling” and are not actionable under settled law governing
such communications. And it is on these bases that most humor cases are decided.
S
ACK, supra note 80, § 5:5.2[G][1] (footnotes omitted). See also Salomone v. Macmillan
Publ’g Co., 411 N.Y.S.2d 105, 108 (Sup. Ct. 1978), rev’d on other grounds, 429 N.Y.S.2d
441 (App. Div. 1980) (“Is there a recognized exception from the laws of libel when words
otherwise defamatory are uttered in a humorous context? Of course, common sense tells us
there must be.”); Freedlander v. Edens Broad., Inc., 734 F. Supp. 221, 228 & n.13 (E.D. Va.
1990) (concluding that song parody amounted to “comedic expression” and “a protected
form of free speech” whether or not the song constituted “protected opinion”).
127. R
ESTATEMENT (FIRST) OF TORTS § 606 (1938). Although the First Restatement
provides a uniform standard, lower courts varied in how they applied the fair comment
privilege. King, supra note 10, at 883–84. In his comprehensive study of parody cases,
Professor King reports that the Second Restatement’s section 566
provides an approach to
defamation that “subsume[s] the prior rule for fair comment, essentially obviating the need
for it.” Id. at
891–92.
128. King, supra note 10, at
891–92 (quoting RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 566
(1977)).
129. Id. at
882 (noting that the common law and constitutional sources for the
distinction are “intertwined”).
See also SACK, supra note 80, at § 5:5.2[G][1] (“Much humor
is a form of opinion or criticism protected under the common-law defense of ‘fair comment’
or the doctrines suggested by the Supreme Court cases: that there are ‘constitutional limits
on the type of speech which may be the subject of state defamation actions . . . .’”).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 119
than sympathetic or neutral merriment may be defamatory.”
130
Expanding
on this point, the comments to section 566 also state that no defamation
occurs where a communication evinces “a harsh judgment upon known or
assumed facts,” since—in that event—the communication “is no more than
an expression of opinion of the pure type . . . .”
131
B. F
IRST AMENDMENT DOCTRINE
The central challenge of regulating defamation actions is calibrating
the appropriate balance of reputational and free expression values. In
developing the First Amendment’s role in this balance, the Supreme Court
first targeted the identity of the defamation plaintiff, reasoning that the
United States’ commitment to robust debate on public issues justified
restricting defamation laws’ protection for public officials
132
and public
figures.
133
The Court then turned its focus to the subject matter of
defamation actions, holding that the First Amendment restricted defamation
actions by private figures based on “matters of public concern.”
134
For
similar reasons, the Court also excised expressions of “opinion” from
defamation liability.
135
Articulating a marketplace of ideas rationale in Gertz v. Robert Welch,
Inc., the Supreme Court counterposed to “opinion” the concept of false
factual statements.
136
The Gertz Court famously declared: “However
pernicious an opinion may seem, we depend for its correction not on the
conscience of judges and juries but on the competition of other ideas.”
137
After lower courts struggled with the scope of constitutional protection of
opinions for fifteen years, the Court took up the concept again in Milkovich
v. Lorain Journal Co.
138
While refusing to articulate a one-size-fits-all
definition of opinion or to create “an artificial dichotomy between
‘opinion’ and fact,” the Court found First Amendment “protection for
statements that cannot ‘reasonably [be] interpreted as stating actual
130. King, supra note 10, at 893 (quoting RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 566 cmt.
c (1977)).
131. Id. (quoting R
ESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 566 cmt. d (1977)).
132. See e.g., N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 270, 279–80 (1964)
(defamation action by public official).
133. See e.g., Curtis Publ’g Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. 130 (1967) (defamation action by
public figure).
134. Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U.S. 749 (1985).
135. Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323 (1974).
136. Id. at 340.
137. Id. at 339–40.
138. Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1 (1990).
120 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
facts.’”
139
One scholar has explained that, although the Court professed to
reject the fact/opinion dichotomy, the Court merely substituted that
“dichotomy . . . with a new dichotomy between ‘fact and non-fact.’”
140
A review of the core values animating the First Amendment sheds
light on what the Supreme Court was trying to achieve with these
dichotomies. Received wisdom suggests that in protecting free expression,
the First Amendment promotes truth seeking, democratic self-governance,
social tolerance, and individual autonomy.
141
On a simplistic level, one can
appreciate how courts can serve these values by protecting opinions (or
non-facts), whereas in some cases one can undermine the values by
allowing false facts to flourish in public debate. While opinions can be
countered with debate, the dissemination of known false facts does not
facilitate society’s search for truth. Likewise, expression of opinions can
assist voters in making informed electoral choices and governmental
officials in making well-considered policy decisions.
142
False facts, however, can hinder wise governmental choices. Allowing
the free flow of all opinions models open-mindedness; similarly,
expression of personal opinion also advances individual autonomy and a
robust sense of personhood. While allowing communication of false facts
may also foster personal autonomy and tolerance of the speaker, the false
facts impose a countervailing toll on both autonomy and tolerance of the
individual about whom the facts concern. The damage to reputation
expresses intolerance toward the individual and detracts from the
individual’s sense of personhood.
143
139. Id. at 20 (quoting Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 50 (1988)). The focus
on factual accuracy in defamation is somewhat unique for First Amendment analysis.
Indeed, Frederick Schauer has forcefully and persuasively argued that First Amendment
doctrine is too tolerant of factual inaccuracy. Frederick Schauer, Facts and the First
Amendment, 57 UCLA
L. REV. 897, 918–19 (2010) (bemoaning tolerance of First
Amendment theory and doctrine for “widespread public factual falsit[ies]”). Outside of the
defamation context, the First Amendment protects factual falsity—particularly in the area of
public debate. See id. at 915 (concluding that, given the extension of the New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan actual malice standard to public figures, the current state of constitutional
doctrine does not allow governmental regulation of statements of “public non-commercial
factual falsity”); Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U.S. 45, 61 (1982) (holding that the only remedies
available against false or misleading campaign speech would be those that satisfied the New
York Times Co. v. Sullivan actual malice standard).
140. 1 R
ODNEY SMOLLA, LAW OF DEFAMATION § 6:21 (2d ed. 2011).
141. C
HEMERINSKY, supra note 121, at 925–30 (reviewing various interests animating
First Amendment doctrine).
142. Id. at 926 (discussing free speech’s role in ensuring a functioning democracy).
143. See id. at 929–30 (discussing the complexities of free speech’s role in advancing
“personhood and autonomy” as well as “promoting tolerance”). Alluding to the conflicting
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 121
Concomitantly with its efforts to demarcate the scope of opinion
protection, the Supreme Court also tracked concern with First Amendment
values in reckoning with the appropriate level of protection for colorful
language. The first cases in this area dealt with name-calling rather than
jokes.
144
Nonetheless, the cases directly wrestled with the type of vivid
language jokesters often use. First, in Greenbelt Cooperative Publishing
Assocationn v. Bresler, the Court held that that a newspaper story alleging
“blackmail” could not be the basis for defamation liability because “even
the most careless reader must have perceived that the word was no more
than rhetorical hyperbole, a vigorous epithet . . . .”
145
Likewise, the Court
in Old Dominion Branch No. 496, National Association of Letter Carriers
v. Austin found First Amendment protection for the description “scab” as
applied to nonunion members, explaining that the term is “merely
rhetorical hyperbole, a lusty and imaginative expression of the
contempt . . . .”
146
Finally, in a case that explicitly grappled with humor, Hustler
Magazine v. Falwell, the Court found that Reverend Jerry Falwell could not
recover in tort for a parody, unless he showed that the defendant acted with
knowledge of the falsity of facts asserted in the communication or with
reckless disregard for the truth or falsity of any facts asserted.
147
In the
course of its reasoning, the Court celebrated the role of parodies in our
cultural tradition, noting that our national “political discourse would have
been considerably poorer without them.”
148
Drawing from earlier First
Amendment precedent focusing on the relationship between defamation
and falsehoods, the Court held that the parody in the case could not have
reasonably been interpreted as asserting “actual facts about [Falwell] or
interest of the speaker and the subject of the speech, Rodney Smolla argues that an
“intelligent argument concerning the fact/opinion distinction cannot be marshalled without
resort to discussion” of the distinction’s attempt to protect reputation, while preserving an
opportunity for robust criticism. S
MOLLA, supra note 140, at § 6:21.
144. Greenbelt Coop. Publ’g Ass’n v. Bresler, 398 U.S. 6, 13–14 (1970).
145. Id. at 13–14.
146. Old Dominion Branch No. 496, Nat’l Ass’n of Letter Carriers v. Austin, 418 U.S.
264, 286 (1974).
147. Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 56 (1988). Hustler concerned the tort
of intentional infliction of emotional distress, but the Court treated the First Amendment
issues as one would have expected it to in a defamation case. Cf. Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S.
Ct. 1207 (2011) (confirming First Amendment obstacles to recovery for intentional
infliction of emotional distress involving a matter of public concern rather than a public
figure).
148. Hustler, 485 U.S. at 55.
122 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
actual events in which he participated.”
149
The Court thus reinforced the
principle that the First Amendment shields from liability communications
that are not reasonably interpreted as factual in nature.
C. T
HE FACT/OPINION DISTINCTION
1. Lower Court Experience
Following the lead of the Supreme Court, as well as common sense
notions of good judging, lower courts generally go out of their way to
avoid making an explicit value judgment about the humor at issue in
defamation suits. Courts protest that they are not deciding whether a
putative joke works as comedy,
150
and that the First Amendment does not
cast them in the role of “polic[ing] bad taste.”
151
Explaining this hands-off
approach, one court cited humor’s “intensely subjective” nature and
observed that “[b]lank looks or even active loathing may be engendered by
a statement or cartoon that evokes howls of laughter from another. What is
amusing or funny in the eyes of one person may be cruel and tasteless to
someone else.”
152
Given these limitations, lower courts in the United States evaluate
allegedly defamatory humor with the eyeglasses of the reasonable reader or
fact finder, a hypothetical entity whose virtues are routinely celebrated by
courts.
153
In deciding whether a reasonable reader or fact finder would
149. Id. at 52, 57.
150. See, e.g., Polygram Records, Inc. v. Superior Court, 216 Cal. Rptr. 252, 259 (Ct.
App. 1985) (explaining that the “proper focus of judicial inquiry . . . is not whether the
allegedly defamatory statement succeeds as comedy, nor whether its audience thought it to
be humorous . . .”); New Times, Inc. v. Isaacks, 146 S.W.3d 144, 158 (Tex. 2004)
(explaining that the proper legal question is not whether “all readers actually . . . ‘got the
joke’”); Salomone v. MacMillan Publ’g Co., 411 N.Y.S.2d 105, 109 (Sup. Ct. 1978)
(adopting the proposition in a defamation action that judges should not act as
“literary . . . critic[s]”), rev’d on other grounds, 429 N.Y.S.2d 441 (App. Div. 1980). Cf.
Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 583 (1994) (observing in the context of
a copyright claim that the “First Amendment protections do not apply only to those who
speak clearly, whose jokes are funny, and whose parodies succeed”); Univ. of Notre Dame
Du Lac v. Twentieth Century-Fox Film Corp., 256 N.Y.S.2d 301, 307 (App. Div.)
(observing in the context of an unfair competition action that judges should “not import the
role of literary or dramatic critic into our functioning as Judges in this case . . . . Whether
[the humor] is good burlesque or bad, penetrating satire or blundering buffoonery, is not for
us to decide”), aff’d by order, 207 N.E.2d 508 (N.Y. 1965).
151. New Times, Inc., 146 S.W.3d at 166. See S.F. Bay Guardian, Inc. v. Superior
Court, 21 Cal. Rptr. 2d 464, 468 (Ct. App. 1993) (stating that the court’s role is not to
decide whether a joke “went ‘too far’”).
152. Salomone, 411 N.Y.S.2d at 109.
153. As the court explained in Patrick v. Superior Court, a reasonable reader “[i]s no
dullard. He or she does not represent the lowest common denominator, but reasonable
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 123
interpret the communication as suggesting actual facts, lower courts often
rely on the line of Supreme Court cases dealing with exaggeration,
deciding whether to assign the label “rhetorical hyperbole” or “vigorous
epithet” to the putative joke.
154
Sometimes, however, lower courts focus on
the fact/opinion distinction, without reliance on either the hyperbole or
epithet characterization.
155
In at least one instance, a court concluded that a
song parody contained sufficient rhetorical hyperbole and indication of
comedic expression that it merited protection from liability, whether or not
it constituted protected opinion.
156
When drawing from the fact/opinion distinction, courts ask whether
the humor contains material that a reasonable reader or fact finder could
interpret as suggesting actual facts.
157
The notion is that humor suggests
intelligence and learning. He or she can tell the difference between satire and sincerity.”
Patrick v. Superior Court, 27 Cal. Rptr. 2d 883, 887 (Ct. App. 1994). See also New Times,
Inc., 146 S.W.3d at 158 (describing a reasonable reader as one who exercises care and
prudence, and explaining that “[i]ntelligent, well-read people act unreasonably from time to
time, whereas the hypothetical reasonable reader . . . does not”).
154. See, e.g., Keller v. Miami Herald Publ’g Co., 778 F.2d 711, 716 (11th Cir. 1985)
(evaluating an editorial cartoon referring to a nursing home as a haunted house by reference
to the fact/opinion dichotomy as well as by reference to “hyperbole, exaggeration, and
caricature”); Pring v. Penthouse Int’l, Ltd., 695 F.2d 438, 441 (10th Cir. 1982) (evaluating a
beauty contest spoof by reference to rhetorical hyperbole case law and deciding that the
spoof could not be interpreted as providing actual facts since the spoof presented
“impossibility and fantasy within a fanciful story”); Hamilton v. Prewett, 860 N.E.2d 1234,
1245–47 (Ind. Ct. App. 2007) (deciding whether parody is protected as hyperbole and
asserting that parody “is speech that one cannot reasonably believe to be fact because of its
exaggerated nature”); Newman v. Delahunty, 681 A.2d 671, 683–84 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law
Div. 1994) (evaluating campaign literature for defamation liability by reference to whether
it expressed facts or was “rhetorical hyperbole” or a “vigorous epithet”); Ferreri v. Plain
Dealer Publ’g Co., 756 N.E.2d 712, 721–22 (Ohio Ct. App. 2001) (explaining that a cartoon
may be defamatory only if a “reasonable person” would conclude that it contained a factual
assertion rather than “exaggeration and hyperbole”).
155. See, e.g., Couch v. San Juan Unified Sch. Dist., 39 Cal. Rptr. 2d 848 (Ct. App.
1995) (deciding that mock examination in a student newspaper could not be interpreted as
suggesting actual fact or anything other than parody); McKimm v. Ohio Elections Comm’n,
729 N.E.2d 364, 371–72 (Ohio 2000) (evaluating whether election literature cartoons could
be interpreted by reasonable reader as asserting facts); New Times, 146 S.W.3d at 158
(evaluating whether a newspaper spoof was subject to defamation liability by analyzing
whether the publication could reasonably be understood as describing real facts).
156. Freedlander v. Edens Broad., Inc., 734 F. Supp. 221, 228 n.13 (E.D. Va. 1990)
(“Having found that the song is a comedic expression based on fact, the Court deems it
unnecessary to pursue defendant’s argument that the song constitutes protected opinion.”).
157. See, e.g., Knievel v. ESPN, 393 F.3d 1068, 1071, 1077–78 (9th Cir. filed Jan. 4,
2005) (finding that a photograph with the caption “Evel Knievel proves that you’re never
too old to be a pimp” could not reasonably be interpreted as actual fact); Dworkin v. Hustler
Magazine Inc., 867 F.2d 1188, 1193–94 (9th Cir. 1989) (dismissing a defamation claim by
an anti-pornography advocate depicted in a Hustler cartoon because a reasonable reader
124 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
real facts and is thus capable of defamatory meaning and threatening
reputational values. A contrary conclusion, that humor does not suggest
real facts, brings the communication into the opinion realm, which is more
clearly protected by free expression values.
2. The Limitations of the Fact/Opinion Distinction
So we see that the fact/opinion dichotomy is not only well-intended,
but also reflects an intelligent effort to accommodate First Amendment
values. Nonetheless, courts are having a devil of a time trying to chart a
predictable line between fact and opinion. Indeed, one scholar proclaims
that there are “as many tests for identifying opinion as there are home
remedies for hiccups.”
158
Although the Supreme Court’s instruction that
courts evaluate whether an assertion includes provably false facts seems
relatively straightforward,
159
lower courts have indulged an impulse to
develop complicated multifactor tests.
160
Understandably, courts are drawn to determinate doctrines that appear
definitional and well designed for consistent application. No doubt the tests
that have emerged in this area reflect that impulse. Yetas in all matters
related to defining truthanalysis becomes highly abstract and contested
as soon as one puts sincere intellectual effort into the inquiry. To provide
just one example of the crystalline distinctions that have emerged, much
ink has been poured over whether the First Amendment protects only
could not interpret the cartoon as conveying a statement of fact); Sagan v. Apple Computer,
Inc., 874 F. Supp. 1072, 1075–76 (C.D. Cal 1994) (explaining in a defamation action based
on changing computer code name from “Carl Sagan” to “Butt-Head Astronomer” that using
“the figurative term ‘Butt-Head’” undermines the possibility that “a reasonable fact finder
could conclude that the published statements imply a provably false factual assertion”);
Filippo v. Lee Publ’ns, Inc., 485 F. Supp. 2d 969, 980 (N.D. Ind. 2007) (stating that under
Indiana law a cartoon can be defamatory only if a reasonable factfinder could conclude that
it implies “objectively verifiable or testable facts”); Ferreri v. Plain Dealer Publ’g Co., 756
N.E.2d 712, 721–22 (Ohio Ct. App. 2001) (explaining that a cartoon may be defamatory
only if a reasonable person would conclude that it contained a factual assertion rather than
“exaggeration and hyperbole”). Cf. Collins v. Creative Loafing Savannah, Inc., 592 S.E.2d
170, 174–75 (Ga. Ct. App. 2003) (stating in the context of a defamatory cartoon that a court
should inquire as to how “the average reader” would construe the communication).
158. S
MOLLA, supra note 140, at § 6:1.
159. Id. §
6:21 (describing the Supreme Court’s “rather single-minded emphasis on
whether the assertions that give rise to the suit are ‘provable as false’” as “a relatively
narrow and mechanistic formula”).
160. For reviews of various tests, see Gregory G. Sarno, Annotation, Libel or Slander:
Defamation by Statement Made in Jest, 57 A.L.R.4
TH 520 §§ 5, 7 (1987 & Supp. 2011)
(humor cases); Fulcher, supra note 10, at 737–44
(primarily humor cases); King, supra note
10, at 913–29
(general defamation cases and parody cases); Treiger, supra note 9, at 1221–
26
(general defamation cases and satire cases).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 125
“pure, evaluative opinion” and not “pure, deductive opinion, which is
provable as true or false on the basis of objective evidence . . . .”
161
The problem gets even worse in humor cases. Following the same
methodology as in non-humor contexts, lower courts examine a putative
joke to determine whether it meets the Milkovich standard: whether the
joke could “reasonably be interpreted as stating actual facts.”
162
Yet
complications arise because humor is better than other modes of
communication at concealing the possible truthfulness of its message.
Why? To begin with, humor’s technique does not operate in the realm of
fact; it operates in the realm of laughter. More specifically, humor works
through incongruity, and by definition, incongruity does not reflect the
constellation of facts and circumstances we readily experience but instead
presents a reality we do not anticipate.
163
As philosopher Immanuel Kant
said, “Jest must contain something that is capable of deceiving for a
moment.
164
Parody presents a particularly difficult challenge when it comes to the
problem of segregating fact from non-fact. Although definitions of parody
differ, theorists generally agree that a parody must resemble the object of
161. See, e.g., Kathryn Dix Sowle, A Matter of Opinion: Milkovich Four Years Later,
3 WM. & MARY BILL RTS. J. 467, 474 (1994).
162. Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1, 2 (1990). See King, supra note 10, at
915 (reasoning that the various lower court tests in parody cases “ultimately” focus on this
Milkovich test). For a similar argument about the difficulties of applying Milkovich in the
context of sexual innuendo and teasing of women, see Lisa R. Pruitt, Her Own Good Name:
Two Centuries of Talk about Chastity, 63 MD. L. REV. 401, 523–28 (2004).
163. One humor theorist explained the matters as follows: humor needs an element of
the ridiculous, and the “ridiculous is logical only within the bounds of certain facts. It
appears logical in a certain setting, but as soon as we get out of the setting and take other
facts into consideration, the logic is lost. Humour, therefore, may be inconsistent with
reality as a whole.” Maier, supra note 61, at 72.
Of course, for the incongruity to work as
humor, it must build on a shared understanding of the world. See supra notes 48–60and
accompanying text.
164. I
MMANUEL KANT, THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGMENT 225 (J.H. Bernard trans.,
Prometheus Books 2000) (1892). See also Gregory R. Naron, Note, With Malice Toward
All: The Political Cartoon and the Law of Libel, 15 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 93, 100
(1991) (observing that given that a cartoonist works in the realm of “truthful
misrepresentation,” the notion of evaluating the truth of a cartoon is inherently questionable
(quoting BOHUN LYNCH, A HISTORY OF CARICATURE 2 (1927))). In his treatise, Judge Robert
Sack paints a picture of humor as largely lacking serious, factual content:
Although perhaps annoying or embarrassing, humorous statements will have no
substantial impact on reputation and therefore ought not to be held to be defamatory.
Incidental jibes and barbs may be humorous forms of epithets or ‘mere name-
calling’ and are not actionable under settled law governing such communications.
And it is on these bases that most humor cases are decided.
S
ACK, supra note 80, at § 5.5.2.7.1:5.2 (internal citation omitted).
126 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
the parody (the “original”), yet deviate sufficiently from the original, to cue
the reader that a spoof is at play. Thus, parody skirts the line between the
“fact” of the original, and the “opinion” represented by the ultimate
message of the spoof. Artful parodies do this in a sneaky way: “The very
nature of parody . . . is to catch the reader off guard at first glance, after
which the ‘victim’ recognizes that the joke is on him to the extent that it
caught him unaware.”
165
One prominent theory is particularly helpful in delineating the
parameters of this problem of identifying facts underlying or suggested in
humor. This theory is known as the semantic script theory identified by
humor scholar Victor Raskin.
166
According to Raskin, a text is humorous if
it is compatible with “two different scripts,” which are “opposite.”
167
A
term of art in semantics, the concept of a “script” is illustrated in the
following joke: “‘Is the doctor at home?’ the patient asked in his bronchial
whisper. ‘No,’ the doctor’s young and pretty wife whispered in reply.
‘Come right in.’”
168
Raskin identifies two scripts that are compatible with the joke (the
script of “doctor” and the script of “lover”), explaining that the scripts are
opposite in the sense that one presents a sexual inference and the other does
not.
169
Although the joke clearly implicates release theory, Raskin’s
interpretation of the joke also evokes incongruity theory, because the
interpretation suggests that “opposite” scripts are necessary conditions for
the humor. For example, one could explain the joke using incongruity
theory by pointing out that the patient would not need to enter the doctor’s
home if the doctor were not present to provide for treatment.
170
165. S.F. Bay Guardian, Inc. v. Superior Court, 21 Cal. Rptr. 2d 464, 466 (Ct. App.
1993). See, e.g., Louis Vuitton Malletier S.A. v. Haute Diggity Dog, LLC, 507 F.3d 252,
260 (4th Cir. 2007) (“A parody must convey two simultaneous—and contradictory—
messages: that it is the original, but also that it is not the original and is instead a parody.”
(internal quotation marks omitted)); Andrew Watt, Parody and Post-Modernism: The Story
of Negativland, 25 C
OLUM. J.L. & ARTS 171, 187 (2002) (noting that a judge evaluating
parody must decide “what the original work represented and what the parody was saying
about the original work”).
166. A
TTARDO, supra note 20, at 1 (citing VICTOR RASKIN, SEMANTIC MECHANISMS OF
HUMOR 99 (D. Reidel Publ’g Co. 1985) (1944)).
167. Id. (quoting R
ASKIN, supra note166, at 99).
168. Id. at 21 (citing R
ASKIN, supra note166, at 117–27).
169. Id. at 1 (citing R
ASKIN, supra note166, at 21–22).
170. As support for the proposition that the script theory of opposites is aligned with
incongruity theory, consider the following explanation of incongruity in humor offered by
Professor John Allen Paulos:
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 127
Why do the opposite scripts present a problem for mining “facts” in a
joke? The humor works only to the extent that there are two sufficiently
plausible, dueling realities at play in the joke. As we hear the joke, we
ponder whether the jokester really means to suggest that the doctor’s wife
wishes to have sex with the patient.
Having pointed out the significant amount of untruth present in
humor, I acknowledge that humor often serves as a medium for providing a
highly factual message. Indeed, humor sometimes pitches a potent message
that speaks truth to power or could not otherwise be easily delivered in a
serious way.
171
The tricky part is that this factual message is often covert:
the nugget of truth may be hidden as a kind of time-release barb or
embedded in an ambiguous joke that is subject to a considerable range of
interpretations.
172
In the doctor joke above, for example, one suspects that
the true message is the doctor’s wife’s attempt at infidelity. But is this just
a joke?
[A] necessary ingredient of humor is that two . . . incongruous ways of viewing
something (a person, a sentence, a situation) be juxtaposed. In other words, for
something to be funny, some unusual, inappropriate, or odds aspects of it must be
perceived together and compared. We have seen that different writers have
emphasized different oppositions: expectation versus surprise, the mechanical versus
the spiritual, superiority versus incompetence, balance versus exaggeration, and
propriety versus vulgarity.
P
AULOS, supra note 46, at 9.
171. Salomone v. MacMillan Publ’g Co., 411 N.Y.S.2d 105, 108 (Sup. Ct. 1978), rev’d
on other grounds, 429 N.Y.S.2d 441 (App. Div. 1980) (“Laughter can soften the blows dealt
by a cruel world, or can sharpen the cutting edge of truth.”). Moreover, the actual humor in
a communication may derive from its naughtiness in pointing out something hurtfully
hurtful and true about an individual. In one study, scholars argued that the hurtfulness is
capable of humor because of circumstances that allow it to operate as a benign violation of
some sort of norm. See A. Peter McGraw & Caleb Warren, Benign Violations: Making
Immoral Behavior Funny, 20 PSYCHOL. SCI. 1 (2010) (suggesting three conditions that can
make a norm violation capable of humor: “(a) the presence of an alternative norm
suggesting that the situation is acceptable, (b) weak commitment to the violated norm, and
(c) psychological distance from the violation.”).
172. See Maier, supra note 61, at 72 (explaining that humor operates in the realm of the
ridiculous and “[b]ecause the ridiculous has only a limited logic, it is easy for us to take it
lightly”). As Professor Kimberlianne Podlas thoughtfully explains, humor can act as a
“Trojan Horse,” which possesses “communicative abilities that serious commentary lacks.”
Podlas, supra note 83, at 511–12. She further explains:
[B]ecause a joke is subject to interpretation, it can disguise a comedian’s true
meaning. Depending on the context, the same comment can be funny or mean,
insightful or inappropriate. As a result, it can be difficult to see where humor ends
and ridicule begins. This provides a joke with a degree of insulation. Consequently,
and somewhat ironically, humor enables one to make serious points that could not
be made in a serious tone.
Id. at 513 (internal citation omitted).
128 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
Matters do not get any better if we cast aside this notion of humor’s
dueling scripts. Indeed, whether humor is in the picture or not, determining
whether something is “a fact” invariably presents a metaphysical challenge.
In some theoretical circles, even suggesting that hard “facts” exist in
counterpoise to something like “values” is cause for a snicker.
173
Leaving
that debate aside, one can see that some phenomena can comfortably be
asserted as fact—”there are more people in China than in New
Jersey . . . Elvis Presley is dead . . . the square root of eighty-one is
nine”
174
—while other phenomena depend on questions of social
construction that quickly muddy the characterization.
175
Although some
humor does play off the first category of fact, humor often involves the
latter category—which is difficult to characterize.
The philosophical challenges of defining “fact” are not unique to the
humor context. Yet at least two reasons suggest that humor enhances the
challenge. The first is humor’s tendency to work by obfuscation, metaphor,
and stealth.
176
This is a point that Freud emphasized in his analysis of
humor’s connection with dreaming.
177
Freud hypothesized that both joking
and dreaming work by analogy or allusion, thereby sidestepping logic and
literal meaning in order to elude the censors of our conscious minds.
178
When operating in this context, humor works outside the bipolar world of
fact/non-fact. Other times, of course, humor actually works within the
realm of fact, albeit concealing or disguising its factual message. While the
fact/opinion paradigm is better suited to this use of humor, the challenge is,
nonetheless, great where the disguise is particularly effective or the
apparently truthful message is ambiguous.
173. Schauer, supra note 139, at 900 (observing that embracing a distinction between
fact and value would “[i]n some circles . . . be an embarrassing thing to admit”). See
generally H
ILARY PUTNAM, The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy, in THE COLLAPSE OF
THE
FACT/VALUE DICHOTOMY AND OTHER ESSAYS 7, 28–30 (2004) (arguing that something
could be both a fact and a value—and that both share overlapping realms); M
ARTIN
HEIDEGGER, BEING AND TIME 125 (Joan Stambaugh trans., SUNY Press 1996) (1927)
(rejecting a distinction between facts and values).
174. Schauer, supra note 139, 900–01(listing examples of facts).
175. J
OHN R. SEARLE, THE CONSTRUCTION OF SOCIAL REALITY 1–2 (Penguin Books
1996) (1995); Lawrence Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, 62 U.
CHI. L. REV. 943,
949 n.19 (1995) (reviewing various approaches to social meaning construction).
176. Cf. F
REUD, supra note 32, at 154.
177. Id.
178. Id. (observing that the technique of jokes includes similar processes as “dream-
work”: “the processes of condensation . . . displacement, representation by absurdity or by
the opposite, indirect representation”).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 129
A related challenge is humor’s tendency to operate in socially
contested areas. As Professor Lawrence Lessig explains, not all “facts” are
created equal.
179
Some facts work well within a First Amendment
marketplace of ideas paradigm because of their ability to be verified in
nature (such as the square root of eighty-one).
180
Others (such as the
common characteristics of demographic groups or the personality strengths
of an individual) are contingent on social definition.
181
For this latter
category, a “fact” (such as what tasks women are best suited for doing in
the workplace) depends on what society has to say about the matter.
182
Because of its unique ability to help individuals communicate about
sensitive social topics, humor often crops up when those topics are
discussed and—when it does so—can cause controversy that is not always
susceptible to any precise factual litmus test.
Aside from general philosophical problems of defining “fact” in a
humorous communication, one also encounters difficulties segregating fact
from non-fact because of humor’s dependence on the unique context in
which it arises. What is funny in one social context may be tragic or sad in
another. For example, we might be willing to laugh at slapstick depicting
an unknown older woman who falls, but are aghast at such a depiction if
we know the woman.
183
Classic interdisciplinary works on humor have
explained that humorous subject matter must be “objective”—meaning that
the recipient of a joke will not perceive it as funny if the recipient reacts to
the subject matter subjectively by perceiving sympathy or other feeling.
184
This complex relationship between objective and subjective perceptions
within humor makes the determination of “fact” even more problematic
than it is outside the humor context. The complex relationship also
highlights the limitations of the legal doctrine that focuses on a reasonable
reader or fact finder. Because subjectivity plays a strong role in the
perception and appreciation of humor, an objective reasonableness test is
either inadequate for the matters it seeks to regulate or downright
misguided.
179. See Lessig, supra note 175, at 1036–37.
180.
Id. at 1037.
181. Id.
182. Id. at 1036–37 (discussing how different facts fare differently in the idea
marketplace).
183. Maier, supra note 61, at 71.
184. B
ERGSON, supra note 48, at 139; Maier, supra note 61, at 71 (explaining the
connection between humor appreciation and lack of subjective feelings).
130 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
One final reason why the fact/opinion distinction is problematic is that
it sends arguably perverse incentives to humorists attempting to avoid
defamation liability. The message of the fact/opinion distinction is that
potential defendants wishing to avoid defamation damages judgments need
to stay in the “opinion chute.” So what can they do to ensure that?
According to existing state common law and First Amendment doctrine, it
is certainly helpful if they include as many outrageously false, hyperbolic,
or vigorous epithets as possible to describe the object of the
communication.
185
Having pointed out these significant problems of deciding defamatory
humor cases by reference to “facts,” I do not advocate dropping the
fact/opinion dichotomy altogether. Until another approach suggests itself,
the deeply entrenched dichotomy provides the best starting point that we
have for accommodating the important social values implicated in this type
of litigation. My intention here is to expose the complexities inherent in the
dichotomy and to suggest refining the law’s approach to the dichotomy as
much as possible. To that end, I turn now to the contributions of Australian
courts. I follow that discussion with some upbeat thoughts about the
promise of incongruity theory.
D. A
USTRALIAS CONTRIBUTION: AUSTRALIAN DEFAMATION LAW AND
ITS LESSON FOR THE UNITED STATES
Australian cases have a two-fold importance for United States
jokesters: (1) the Australian cases directly regulate those foreign humorists
who cast their jokes into Australia’s regulatory net, and (2) the Australian
cases inform regulation in United States courts. While I use Australian
experience in this article for the latter lesson, I advise those engaging in
edgy humor—particularly on the Internet—to take note of Australia’s far-
reaching regulation of defamation and to become familiar with its
parameters.
186
But as I say, my primary enterprise here is to use the
185. See M. Kevin Smith, Note, Constitutional Law—Satire, Defamation, and the
Believability Rule as a Bar to Recovery—Falwell v. Flynt, 797 F.2d 1270 (4th Cir. 1986),
22 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 915, 915, 928–29 (1987) (reasoning that the focus on facts
encourages speakers to increase intentional falsehoods to insulate themselves from
defamation recovery). This problem of encouraging greater hyperbole or epithets likely
operates most often in jokes laced heavily with superiority humor.
186. One could also say, of course, that Australian defamation law calls for significant
attention because—as a general matter—Australia is an important global partner for the
United States. Even leaving aside the cultural and ideological kinship between the United
States and Australia, Australia is economically and strategically important to the United
States. The economic importance of Australia may not be readily apparent, since, despite
signing a free trade agreement with Australia in 2004, the United States has received only
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 131
Australian cases as a foil: to highlight qualities in the Australian case law
from which United States courts might benefit or—alternatively—avoid.
187
marginal direct benefit. See Chris Nyland & Russell Smyth, Australian Roadmaps to
Globalism: Explaining the Shift from Multilateralism to Imperial Preference, in
G
LOBALIZATION IN THE ASIAN REGION: IMPACTS AND CONSEQUENCES 117, 119–20 (Gloria
Davies & Chris Nyland eds., 2004). Nonetheless, the United States has a strong, indirect
economic interest in Australia, given Australia’s ties with key Asian trade players, like
China, India, and Japan. See B
RUCE VAUGHN, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., RL 33010,
A
USTRALIA: BACKGROUND AND U.S. RELATIONS 16–18 (2008). These countries, for their
part, rely on Australia for access to raw materials. See id. at 12. From the point of view of
politics and international security, the United States also considers Australia (along with
Japan) to be an important partner, given its shared democratic traditions and strategically
significant geographic position near China and the Korean Peninsula. See id. at
8–9, 11–13.
187. Comparative law is practically useful for expanding the horizons of law and
treating similar legal problems that challenge multiple legal systems. See generally Laura E.
Little, Transnational Guidance in Terrorism Cases, 38 G
EO. WASH. U. INTL L. REV. 1, 6–18
(2006) (reviewing reasons why use of transnational materials promotes good judging
methodology and is consistent with the constitutional role of United States courts, even if
only to demonstrate what does not transfer well to United States jurisprudence). What I
advocate here is to pursue what Professor Vicki Jackson might call “engagement” with
Australian law rather than “convergence” with Australian law. V
ICKI C. JACKSON,
CONSTITUTIONAL ENGAGEMENT IN A TRANSNATIONAL ERA 11–12, 39, 71 (2010). In
democratic countries where “the relative social, historical, and religious circumstances
create a common ideological basis, it is possible to refer to a foreign legal system for a
source of comparison and inspiration.” Aharon Barak, A Judge on Judging: The Role of a
Supreme Court in Democracy, 116 HARV. L. REV. 16, 110–11 (2002). Legal cross-
fertilization, or the borrowing of legal experiences, is common in practice in
Commonwealth and former Commonwealth countries with common law systems. Id. at 114.
See, e.g., Mark C. Rahdert, Comparative Constitutional Advocacy, 56 A
M. U. L. REV. 553,
554–62, 576–77 (2007) (favoring using comparative constitutional materials as persuasive
authority and instruction on basic concepts such as liberty, equal protection, and privacy).
That is not to say that one should embark on the comparative enterprise lightly or with an
inclination to make broad generalizations. See Annelise Riles, Wigmore’s Treasure Box:
Comparative Law in the Era of Information, 40 HARV. INT'L L.J. 221, 252–53 (1999)
(questioning whether comparative law can function as a source of legal inspiration since
more of the foreign law’s context is left out than is included in a comparative analysis). One
must be mindful that the more detailed the scale of the inquiry, the more likely one will
encounter increased complication and more variables to take into account. Id. Such
information overload can make real comparison at different levels of generality well-nigh
impossible. Id. See also Teemu Ruskola, Legal Orientalism, 101 M
ICH. L. REV. 179, 190
(2002) (doubting whether some modern comparativists do more than try to confirm the
universality of their legal system or to indict other legal systems for what they lack).
Mindful of the risks of the comparative law enterprise, I try to confine my look at Australian
law to a search for ideas and lessons. I do note that Australia’s and America’s shared legal
heritage in the English common law combined with its sometimes path-breaking High Court
rulings makes Australia an intelligent source to look for tested legal innovation. That
Australia’s federal structure of government and judiciary largely resembles that of the
United States indicates that America can learn much from the Australian laboratory. See
generally Kathleen E. Foley, Australian Judicial Review, 6 W
ASH. U. GLOB. STUD. L. REV.
281, 290–91 (2007) (describing the operation of Australian judicial review and the powers
of the Australian High Court). Since gaining its autonomy from the British appeals system
132 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
To serve these goals, this section starts first with a description of
Australia’s regulatory tentacles within a global context. It next reviews
general principles of Australia’s speech protection and defamation law.
Finally, it ends with an analysis of Australia’s defamatory humor cases and
their lessons for courts in the United States.
1. Br-r-r-r: Australian Defamation Laws’ Global Chill
For those concerned with possible exposure to defamation liability,
Sydney rivals London for the reputation of “a town named sue.”
188
Indeed,
as long as twenty-five years ago, Sydney was dubiously honored as the
“defamation capital of the world.”
189
While defamation practice in Sydney
is particularly robust,
190
other parts of the Australian court system enjoy
similarly lively and significant defamation dockets.
191
The impact is not limited to domestic defendants. In 2002, the High
Court of Australia struck fear in the hearts of publishers throughout the
world with its decision in Dow Jones & Co. v Gutnick.
192
Applying a
choice of law rule based on lex loci deliciti (law of the place of the tort
governs), the High Court allowed a resident of the state of Victoria to
proceed in a defamation action against Dow Jones for material uploaded
onto the Internet in the United States. Uniform legislation enacted after the
Gutnick decision left open liability exposure and uncertainties for foreign
in 1986, the Australian High Court has robustly reviewed cutting-edge legal issues, giving
Australian law increasing relevance in a globalized world. See id. at 284, 305. Moreover, the
two countries share deep-seated cultural values such as “almost strident egalitarianism, deep
suspicion of authority, [and] laconic and even self-deprecating humour.” See Michael
Coper, Three Good Things and Three Not-So-Good Things About the Australian Legal
System, I
NTL ASSN OF LAW SCHS. 2 (Oct. 17–19, 2007),
http://www.ialsnet.org/meetings/enriching/coper.pdf.
188. Sarah Lyall, England, Long a Libel Mecca, Reviews Laws, N.Y.
TIMES, Dec. 11,
2009, at A1 (associating that name with London).
189. Michael Newcity, The Sociology of Defamation in Australia and the United
States, 26 T
EX. INTL L.J. 1, 11 n.46, 64 (1991). See also Andrew Hemming, Is Defamation
the ‘Galapagos Islands Division’ of the Australian Law of Torts?, 11 U.
NOTRE DAME
AUSTL. L. REV. 84, 110–11 (2009) (stating that “[w]hether Sydney continues to wear the
crown as the defamation capital remains an open question”).
190. Indeed, courts in Sydney have a special docket dedicated to defamation cases. See
David Levine, Defamation Practice: Change and Reform, Lawlink New South Wales (Mar.
16, 2001), www.lawlink.nsw.gov.au/lawlink/supreme_court/ll_sc.nsf/vwPrint1/SCO_speech
_levine_160301.
191. See, e.g., A
NDREW T. KENYON, DEFAMATION: COMPARATIVE LAW AND PRACTICE
2, 165–93 (2006) (describing detailed and well-developed defamation practice in Victoria).
192. Dow Jones & Co. v Gutnick (2002) 210 CLR 575 (Austl.).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 133
defendants who publish material overseas
193
—thus maintaining significant
incentives for libel tourism and potentially excessive self-censorship on the
part of publishers.
194
Australia continues to provide incentives for libel plaintiffs to file suit
there because of its relatively plaintiff-friendly defamation laws, as well as
personal jurisdiction and choice of law principles that allow extraterritorial
application of Australian law on foreign defendants who make statements
outside of Australia.
195
With Great Britain potentially responding to United
States’ libel tourism restrictions by making the country less hospitable to
defamation plaintiffs,
196
Australia could take on even greater importance
for those forum shopping for an attractive place to file a defamation suit. In
its potential to chill the expression of humorists uploading materials from
elsewhere in the world, Australian law requires attention.
197
2. Australian Defamation Law: A General Overview
Australian judges and legal scholars are deeply self-critical of
Australia’s current defamation laws.
198
Commenting on what he perceived
193. Belinda Robilliard, Jurisdiction and Choice of Law Rules for Defamation Actions
in Australia Following the Gutnick Case and the Uniform Defamation Legislation, 14
A
USTL. INTL L.J. 185, 193, 197–198 (2007) (discussing uncertainty and exposure for
defamation defendants under uniform defamation legislation).
The potential exposure from
Gutnick, however, can easily be overstated. For example, liability was restricted to damages
accrued within the state of Victoria, and principles of abuse of process limit plaintiffs’
ability to file repeated lawsuits in multiple jurisdictions based on the same matter. See, e.g.,
David Rolph, The Message, Not the Medium: Defamation, Publication and the Internet in
Dow Jones & Co. Inc. v. Gutnick, 24 S
YDNEY L. REV. 263, 275 (2002) (discussing
limitations on liability made possible under Gutnick).
194. Robilliard, supra note 193, at 193, 198 (explaining how a defendant with strict
liability exposure—such as the case of defamation liability in Australia—will distort the
level of precautions taken).
195. Michelle A. Wyant, Confronting the Limits of the First Amendment: A Proactive
Approach for Media Defendants Facing Liability Abroad, 9
SAN DIEGO INTL L.J. 367, 393–
400
(2008) (explaining how the intersection of Australia’s lex loci delecti choice of law rule
and its recognition of a separate cause of action for each publication allows its defamation
laws to have extraterritorial reach).
196. Lyall,
supra note 188 (describing Great Britain’s serious consideration of such a
legislative change).
197. For a description of how a joke publication can result in a chilling foreign
judgment on a U.S. newspaper, see Michael Socha, Double Standard: A Comparison of
British and American Defamation Law, 23 P
ENN. ST. INTL L. REV. 471 (2004) (describing
the potential chilling effect of a defamation judgment against Dow Jones in British courts).
For a discussion of the chilling effect of Australian defamation law for humorists within
Australia, see Elizabeth Handsley & Robert Phiddian, Political Cartoonists and the Law, in
C
OMIC COMMENTATORS 73–74 (Robert Phiddian & Haydon Manning, eds., 2008).
198. See, e.g., Ruth McColl, Forward to P
ATRICK GEORGE, DEFAMATION LAW IN
AUSTRALIA xv–xvi (2006) (stating that “Australian courts have resisted calls for the law of
134 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
as the unevolved status of Australian defamation law, one judge described
it as the “Galapagos Island Division of the law of torts.”
199
He bemoaned
defamation law’s “esoteric customs,” which perpetuate “distinctions
between inferences upon inferences.”
200
While this description suggests a
dismal prognosis for the future of Australian defamation law, others are
more sanguine,
201
finding hope in the Uniform Defamation Laws enacted
throughout the country in 2006.
202
Perhaps the most salient feature of Australian defamation laws (for
this Article’s purposes) is their relative lack of constraint: they operate
unfettered by any constitutional analogue to the First Amendment. Silence
on free speech rights is not confined to that category of civil liberties, since
the Australian Constitution reflects almost no mention of individual rights
as a general matter.
203
Australian law’s approach reflects a belief that social
cohesion and public order should trump freedom of speech where speech
might threaten a breach of the peace.
204
defamation to adapt to the global . . . world”); Tony Fitzgerald, Telling the Truth, Laughing,
92 M
EDIA INTL AUSTL. 11, 16 (1999) (asserting that “[d]efamation law in Australia is in a
mess”); Roger S. Magnusson, Freedom of Speech in Australian Defamation Law: Ridicule,
Satire and Other Challenges, 9 TORTS L.J. 269, 272–74 (2001) (commenting on the
“volatility” of defamation laws governing Australia’s media); David Rolph, Critique of the
Uniform Defamation Act, 16 T
ORTS L.J. 207, 247 (2008) (opining that Australian
defamation law bears the hallmarks of historical accident, comparative neglect, and
piecemeal reform).
199. Justice David Ipp, Themes in the Law of Torts, 81 AUSTL. L.J. 609, 614 (2007).
200. Id.
201. See, e.g., Hemming, supra note 189, at 84 (maintaining that “conjuring up images
of giant turtle and arcane procedures in relation to defamation is to indulge hyperbole and
gives insufficient credit to” Australia’s new uniform defamation laws).
202. Paul Svilans, The Uniform Defamation Laws, (New South Wales Young Lawyers
CLE Seminar Papers 2006) (reporting that most states and territories enacted the uniform
law on January 1, 2006, and at that time the Northern Territory was expected to follow
shortly thereafter).
203. Magnusson, supra note 198, at 275 (maintaining that “constitutional protection in
Australia confers no private rights, but operates as a limitation upon legislative and
executive power” to ensure effective representational government).
204. See, e.g., Melinda Jones, Free Speech Revisited: The Implication of Lange and
Levy, 4 A
USTL. J. HUM. RTS. 188, 203 (1997). A powerful example of the willingness of
Australian regulators to restrict humor appears in a legislative committee report relating
exemptions to the Australian racial vilification laws. The committee report expressed
concern about the exemption from liability under the federal racial vilification act for
communications for artistic purposes. See Judith Bannister, It’s Not What You Say but the
Way That You Say It: Australian Hate Speech Laws and the Exemption of “Reasonable”
Expression, 36 F
LA. ST. U. L. REV. 23, 33 (2008) (observing that in an artistic performance a
“comedian can . . . tell blatantly racist jokes[,] . . . but those some [sic] jokes told by an
ordinary citizen in a public place . . . could render him/her subject to civil proceedings”
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 135
Nonetheless, the Australian High Court has found an implied
constitutional freedom of political communication.
205
In language
reminiscent of United States free speech rhetoric, the High Court cited the
central role that political communication plays in the functioning of the
representative government explicitly described in the written Australian
Constitution.
206
As originally articulated, the qualified freedom extends to
protect public communications about politics.
207
Judges have been reluctant
to protect the freedom rigorously, choosing instead to defer to legislative
judgments and to decline opportunities to expand the categories of
protected communications.
208
Thus, communications within the ambit of
(citing S. LEGAL AND CONSTITUTIONAL LEGIS. COMM., REPORT ON RACIAL HATRED BILL
1994, MINORITY REPORT, at 6 (1995))).
205. Under the Anglo-Australian approach adopted from the common law, this
protection is accurately regarded as a freedom and not a right. See Douglas v. Hello! Ltd.,
[2005] EWCA (Civ) 595, [64] (Eng.), in which Justice Brooke discussed the freedom/right
distinction. The distinction generally means that a citizen may be free to say what he or she
likes, but does not have a protected right to do so. Under this freedom-based approach,
existing laws such as those proscribing defamation or contempt of court provide robust
constraints on speech, with protections like the implied freedom of political communications
providing only a negative limitation on the laws rather than a positive right of Australians to
converse about political or governmental matters. For a discussion of the ramifications of
this negative conceptualization of the freedom, see Adrienne Stone, The Comparative
Constitutional Law of Freedom of Expression, in R
ESEARCH HANDBOOK IN COMPARATIVE
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (Rosalind Dixon & Tom Ginsburg eds., publication forthcoming),
available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1633231.
206. Lange v Austl. Broad. Corp. (1997) 189 CLR 520 (Austl.).
207. Id. at 112. The High Court made clear that the freedom was unavailable if the
plaintiff established that the publication was inspired by ill will or other improper motive.
Id. at 117–18.
208. James Stellios, Using Federalism to Protect Political Communication:
Implications from Federal Representative Government, 31 M
ELB. U. L. REV. 239, 240, 245
(2007). The High Justices have said that free speech protections in Australia differ from
those in the United States in that Australian protections protect only political discourse as
“an indispensable element in ensuring the efficacious working of representative democracy
and government[,]” not “freedom of expression generally as a fundamental human right.”
Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times (1994) 182 CLR 104, 125 (Austl.). Another
example of Australia’s inclination to restrict this protection is federal and state racial
vilification laws, at least some of which have been held to be an appropriate restriction on
communications relating to political and governmental matters. See Bannister, supra note
204, at
26 (citing decisions of an Australian federal court as well as the Victoria Court of
Appeal).
A possible exception to the High Court’s inclination to read the scope of political
communication restrictively is Coleman v Power (2004) 220 CLR 1 (Austl.), in which the
High Court quashed the conviction of a political activist for using “threatening, abusive, or
insulting words.” See Adrienne Stone & Simon Evans, Australia: Freedom of Speech and
Insult in the High Court of Australia, 4 I
NTL J. CONST. L. 677, 678 (2006) (noting that the
Coleman majority did not accept that the state may “mandate civility in political
communication”).
136 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
Australian constitutional protection continue to include only those “that are
somehow related to government and political matters.”
209
Although the
Australian High Court has adopted a variation of the American actual
malice standard in such cases, an Australian defamation plaintiff must
establish that the publication was “actuated by . . . ill will or other improper
motive”
210
only after the defendant has asserted the privilege and
established that the publication was reasonable.
As for free speech protection in the context of defamation, defamation
law itself is thought to calibrate the appropriate balance between expressive
freedom and reputation protection.
211
The law monitors this balance
through the cause of action elements and a series of elaborate defenses. A
look at the various definitions for “defamatory” appearing in Australian
cases powerfully illustrates how this balance favors reputation more than
United States law does.
212
First, a defamatory publication is one that “is
calculated to injure the reputation of another, by exposing him to hatred,
contempt, or ridicule.”
213
A publication can also be defamatory where “it
tends to make the plaintiff be shunned and avoided . . . without any moral
discredit” prompted by the plaintiff
214
or where it tends “to lower the
plaintiff in the estimation of right-thinking [members of society
generally.]”
215
Also indicative of the plaintiff-oriented balance is the strict
liability nature of the tort: “[A] defendant may be liable even though no
209. William Buss, Constitutional Words About Words: Protected Speech and
“Fighting Words” Under the Australian and American Constitutions,
15 TRANSNATL L. &
CONTEMP. PROBS. 489, 494 (2006).
210. Lange v Austl. Broad. Corp. (1997) 189 CLR 520, 574 (Austl.). See Wyant, supra
note 195, at 388 (describing Australian rules and observing that a plaintiff under United
States defamation laws would need to establish actual malice in every such case).
211. D
AVID ROLPH, REPUTATION, CELEBRITY AND DEFAMATION LAW 1 (2008) (stating
that tort law “purports to strike a balance between freedom of speech and protection of
reputation”). Some Australian judges have frankly questioned the value of freedom of
expression and freedom of the press, particularly in media cases over the last fifteen years.
See, e.g., Austl. Broad. Corp. v. O’Neill (2006) 227 CLR 57, 114–16 (Judge Heydon); Austl.
Broad. Corp. v. Lenah Game Meats (2001) 208 CLR 199, 300–09 (Judge Callinan); Ballina
Shire Council v. Ringland (1994) 33 NSWLR 680 (Austl. (Judge Mahoney).
212. P
ATRICK GEORGE, DEFAMATION LAW IN AUSTRALIA 154–55 (2006) (summarizing
the common law definitions of defamatory, which are deemed unaffected by the Uniform
Act).
213. Id. (citing Parmiter v. Coupland, (1840) 151 Eng. Rep. 340 (Exch. of Pleas) 342).
214. Id. (citing Youssoupoff v. MGM Pictures, Ltd., (1934) 1 T.L.R. 581 (EWCA) at
587 (Eng.)).
215. Id. (citing Sim v. Stretch, (1936) 2 All E.R. 1237 at 1240 (Eng.)).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 137
injury to reputation was intended and the defendant acted with reasonable
care . . . .”
216
The free speech side of the balance is represented by elaborate
defenses, set forth in detail in the Uniform Defamation Act.
217
Most
pertinent here is the defense of “honest opinion”—which may in some
cases protect opinion-based humor. Although the “honest opinion” defense
substantially mirrors a preexisting defense from Anglo-Australian common
law known as the defense of fair comment, defendants encountered
substantial difficulty in successfully asserting the common law fair
comment defense.
218
The current provision under the Uniform Act tries to
broaden protections against expressions of comment or opinion, although it
limits the defense to a “matter of public interest”
219
and circumstances
where the opinion is based on material that is “substantially true or
published on an occasion of absolute, qualified, or fair report privilege.”
220
One can see that the privilege operates quite differently than the
fact/opinion dichotomy in United States law; the honest opinion privilege is
available under Australian law only if the opinion actually has a factual
underpinning or is otherwise protected by another privilege.
Prior to the Uniform Defamation Act, the notion of a defamatory
“imputation” was a key concept for a defamation plaintiff in certain
Australian jurisdictions.
221
Pleading rules imposed on the plaintiff a duty to
identify the precise defamatory meaning that one might impute to the
216. Robilliard, supra note 193, at 193, 197–98 (discussing uncertainty and exposure
for defamation defendants under uniform defamation legislation).
217. See Defamation Act 2005 (NSW) ss 24–33 (Austl.), reprinted in G
EORGE, supra
note 212, at 450–58.
218. Andrew T. Kenyon, Perfecting Polly Peck: Defences of Truth and Opinion in
Australian Defamation Law and Practice, 29
SYDNEY L. REV. 651, 680 (2007) (describing
prior practice under the defense). See also Handsley & Phiddian, supra note 197, at 68–73
(discussing fair comment and honest opinion as these defenses pertain to political cartoons).
219. Kenyon, supra note 218, at 680 (quoting Australia’s uniform defamation law).
220. Id. (describing uniform defamation law and reforms the law sought to implement).
221. The concept of an imputation was part of the cause of action for defamation in the
largest source of defamation jurisprudence—New South Wales—and an important
component of defamation codes in Queensland and Tasmania. See, e.g., Defamation Act
1974 (NSW). s 9 (Austl.) (earlier provision, now repealed, detailing the imputation
requirement). Pleading particular imputations were less important in other Australian
jurisdictions, where the communication as a whole—not the imputations contained within
it—provided the cause of action. See G
EORGE, supra note 212, at 142–49 (discussing
variation in the requirement of pleading imputations across Australian jurisdictions). The
word “imputation” appears in older United States materials as well, although it is not clear
that spawned complex procedural requirements as it did in Australia.
138 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
defendant’s communication.
222
Although the concept of an imputation
would seem to have the salutary effect of crystallizing the precise point of
controversy between the parties, the requirement multiplied complexities in
litigating defamation cases and the Uniform Defamation Act omitted it.
223
The imputation requirement nonetheless remains an important part of
precedent, providing the vocabulary for conceptualizing how a
communication might be understood as defamatory.
Interpretation of the defendant’s communication is for the jury, which
should evaluate whether the plaintiff’s asserted imputations are reasonable
under community standards.
224
Juries must follow the rule that the
“defendant’s actual intention (as opposed to what was understood to be his
intention from what he had published) is irrelevant to the meaning in fact
conveyed.”
225
Importantly though—for the purposes of humor cases—the
jury must undertake its interpretative role in light of human discourse and
expressive patterns. Reminiscent of the United States Supreme Court’s
“rhetorical hyperbole” exception to defamation liability,
226
one Australian
court explained:
[P]eople not unfrequently use words, and are understood to use words, not
in their natural sense, or as conveying the imputation which, in ordinary
circumstances, and apart from their surroundings, they would convey, but
extravagantly, and in a manner which would be understood by those who
hear or read them as not conveying the grave imputation suggested by a
mere consideration of the words themselves.
227
Similarly reminiscent of the United States Supreme Court’s “vigorous
epithet” exception to defamation liability,
228
another line of Australian
cases allows “vulgar abuse” to escape liability.
229
One commentator
222. GEORGE, supra note 212, at 142.
223. Id. at 149. It is, however, still considered good pleading practice for a plaintiff to
particularize imputations upon which the plaintiff relies. Id.
224. O’Hara v Channel Seven Sydney Pty Ltd., [2007] NSWDC 81 (14 September
2007) [23–28] (Austl.) (discussing case law establishing that questions of interpretation as
to allegedly defamatory material are questions for a jury). For a formula of this concept in
the context of a classic humor case, see Donoghue v. Hayes, (1831) Hayes Ir. Exch. Rep.
265, 266 (“The whole question is, whether the jocularity was in the mind of the defendant
alone, or was shared by the bystanders.”).
225. Anderson v Mirror Newspaper Ltd. (No. 1) (1986) 6 NSWLR 99 (Austl.).
226. See supra notes 134–38 and accompanying text for further discussion of this
exception.
227. Austl. Newspaper Co. v. Bennett, [1894] A.C. 284, 287 (Eng.).
228. See supra notes 134–38 and accompanying text for further discussion of this
exception.
229. Magnusson, supra note 198.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 139
explained that, “‘[v]ulgar abuse’ escapes liability not because it is nonsense
or because it is vulgar, but frequently because it is so excessive, irrational
and disproportionate that the imputations conveyed would not be taken
seriously, and so cannot reasonably be said to arise.”
230
3. Disparagement Versus Ridicule: Australian Defamatory Humor Cases
By evaluating whether a joke might suggest some unflattering fact
about the plaintiff, Australian defamatory humor cases resemble their
counterparts in the United States. Given Australia’s greater emphasis on
reputational interests, one might expect this parallel analysis to yield
liability for Australian defendants more often than in the United States.
231
Interestingly, however, the cases do not really bear this out. What is a
striking difference from the United States is Australia’s continued
commitment to defamation protection for plaintiffs who are simply exposed
to ridicule, even where defendants’ communications contains little, if
anything, suggesting an unflattering fact. The ridicule test is conceptually
distinct from the tests for defamatory meaning based on disparagement,
because ridicule does not necessarily suggest to others that the ridicule’s
object (the plaintiff) possesses any characteristic, or has taken any action,
that would lower others’ esteem for the plaintiff.
232
Although the
“disparagement” versus “ridicule” labels are mine, Australian courts have
occasionally explicitly described the distinction these labels represent.
233
The following examples of Australian defamatory humor decisions
illustrate these various observations.
a. Disparagement Cases
The broad sweep of Australia’s defamation definitions, and its
comparatively constrained protection of free speech values, suggest that
230. Id. at 284.
231. Seeing analytical overlap in approaches, I only partly embrace the position of
Richard Creech, who concluded his comparative study of United States and Australian libel
cases as follows: “In the end, the American and Australian approaches to the analysis of
defamatory language appear to be irreconcilable, as each is the product of a different
societal judgment regarding the relative worth of free speech compared to a person’s
reputational interest.” Richard L. Creech, Dow Jones and the Defamatory Defendant Down
Under: A Comparison of Australian and American Approaches to Libelous Language in
Cyberspace, 22 J.
MARSHALL J. COMPUTER & INFO. L. 553, 566 (2004).
232. Magnusson, supra note 198, at 280.
233. See, e.g., Darbyshir v Daily Examiner Pty Ltd. (Unreported, Supreme Court of
New South Wales, Levine J, 29 August 1997) (Austl.) (discussing whether advertisement
had an adverse reflection upon the reputation of the plaintiff or could hold her up to
ridicule).
140 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
Australian cases evaluating whether a joke amounts to disparagement
would be far more protective of the plaintiff, and more restrictive of humor,
than United States cases are. But the results are not so clear. Of the
relatively small universe of Australian decisions dealing with defamatory
humor,
234
many come out in favor of the jokester. For example, in Seidler
v. Fairfax, an allegedly defamatory cartoon depicted a barren landscape
containing austere, person-sized structures.
235
Some of the structures were
completely filled with a person being served sandwiches at the structure’s
front and excreting feces out the structure’s back.
236
The cartoon’s caption
said “Harry Seidler Retirement Park.”
237
The cartoon apparently sought to
comment on “the dehumanizing . . . modernist architecture” of Australian
architect Harry Seidler.
238
Seidler lost at the defamation trial about the
cartoon because the jury found the requisite elements of a fair comment
defense, including finding that the cartoon was an expression of opinion
and that the opinion was based on “proper material for comment.”
239
The
appellate court affirmed, despite Seidler’s argument that the fair comment
defense should be unavailable because the cartoon inaccurately suggested
that he had designed a retirement park.
240
Explaining that the jury was free
to find the retirement park reference to be fictitious, one appellate judge
explained that a cartoon on a subject of public interest is “bound by its
nature to traffic in exaggeration, caricature, allegory and fiction” and that
the “ordinary reader would understand that cartoons are often not to be
taken literally.”
241
234. Since “humor” is not a legal category, I had to evaluate whether a particular
defamation case presented an issue dealing with humor, rather than straightforward ridicule
or some other expression with no comedic effect or intent. In one disparagement case filed
by a federal election candidate, however, the defendant comedian formally asserted “humor”
as a defense. Steve Larkin, Court Jester: Mick Molloy to Use Humour as a Defence in
Defamation Case, S
YDNEY MORNING HERALD, Apr. 27, 2010,
http://www.smh.com.au/entertainment/court-jester-mick-molloy-to-use-humour-as-a-
defence-in-defamation-case-20100427-tp2i.html.
235. Seidler v Fairfax [1986] Aust Torts Reports ¶
80–002, 67,473–67,475 (Austl.).
236. Id. at 67, 475.
237. Id.
238. John McCallum, Comedy and Constraint: Lenny Bruce, Bernard Manning,
Pauline Pantsdown and Bill Hicks, in SERIOUS FROLIC: ESSAYS ON AUSTRALIAN HUMOUR
202, 215 (Fran De Groen & Peter Kirkpatrick eds., 2009).
239. Seidler v Fairfax [1986] Aust Torts Reports
¶¶ 80–002, 67,475 (Austl.).
240. Id.
241. Id. at 67,476. One might argue that the reasoning here is contradictory: on one
hand the court says that the cartoon is not to be taken literally, and on the other hand the
court suggests that it is a serious comment (the fair comment defense acknowledges that the
communication can make a literal, defamatory suggestion about the plaintiff). The bottom
line, however, was a humor-protecting result. See generally Austl. Broad. Corp. v Hanson
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 141
The court reached a similarly humor-friendly result in Coleman &
Anor v. John Fairfax Publications Pty Ltd., an action brought by a coach in
Australia’s National Rugby League for an article that blamed the team’s
poor results on the coach’s “being put in child care as a toddler.”
242
The
article quoted a “psychologist” as saying the coach’s “somewhat fractured
relationship with his mother as a child hasn’t provided him with adequate
communication and intimacy skills.”
243
Rejecting the defamation claim, the
court reasoned that a reasonable reader would find nothing in the article’s
contents “to be taken seriously,” adding that the article was “self-evidently
absurd” and simply a “joke” that neither conveyed anything “disparaging,”
nor would inspire anyone to shun or avoid the plaintiff.
244
The humor-protecting orientation guiding Coleman and Seidler
appears in other disparagement cases as well.
245
I note, however, that four
[1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998) (Austl.); McCallum, supra note 238, at 215
(contrasting Seidler with a case in which the court was more hostile to the humor).
242. Coleman v John Fairfax Publ’ns Pty Ltd. [2003] NSWSC 564 (25 June 2003)
[Appendix A] (Austl.).
243. Id.
244. Id. at [22]–[23].
245. See, e.g., Falkenberg v Nationwide News Pty Ltd. (Unreported, Supreme Court of
New South Wales, Levine J, 16 December 1994) 3–4 (Austl.). The Falkenberg plaintiff
sued over a Gary Larson “The Far Side” cartoon captioned “Graffiti in Hell,” which
depicted the devil in a rage because of the apparently sweet picture and statement “Satan is a
warm and tender guy” written on the wall. Id. at [2]. The wall also had the following
written: “For a pleasant conversation call Satan 5551232.” Id. This, it turned out, was the
phone number for plaintiffs, Daniel and Rosemary Falkenberg, who received many phone
calls from readers who saw the cartoon in an Australian newspaper. Id. at [2]. These
plaintiffs asserted four imputations based on the premise that they are akin to a devil who
tries to attract telephone conversations. Id. at [2]. The court concluded that it was incapable
of defaming Rosemary because the devil is depicted as a woman. Id. at [7]. As for Daniel,
the court also determined that the cartoon was not capable of conveying the imputations. Id.
at [8]. The court added that the appropriate test is “the ordinary reasonable reader, knowing
the relevant facts and not what must have been a great deal of weird people who merely
called the telephone number.” Id.
The British case, Berkoff v. Burchill [1997] E.M.L.R. 139 (U.K.), a case which
strongly influenced Australian defamation cases, is also aligned with the type of result one
would likely see in the United States. In that case, a journalist described Steven Berkoff, an
actor and director, as follows: “Film directors, from [Alfred] Hitchcock to [Steven] Berkoff,
are notoriously hideous-looking people . . .” and in a review of Frankenstein, she described
the new look for the monster, stating, “it’s a lot like Stephen [sic] Berkoff, only marginally
better looking.” Id. at 141. In oft-quoted language, one judge stated: “Many a true word is
spoken in jest. Many a false one too. But chaff and banter are not defamatory, and even
serious imputations are not actionable if no one would take them to be meant seriously.” Id.
at 152 (Millett, L.J., dissenting). He added:
The line between mockery and defamation may sometimes be difficult to draw.
When it is it should be left to the jury to draw it . . . . A decision that it is an
actionable wrong to describe a man as “hideously ugly” would be an unwarranted
142 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
defamation cases arising from disparagement humor come out the other
way—in support of the plaintiff. Nonetheless, the facts in two of the four
cases so strongly support a plaintiff’s win that one would expect a similar
result in the United States.
246
Importantly, both cases reckon forthrightly
restriction on free speech. And if a bald statement to this effect would not be capable
of being defamatory, I do not see how a humorously exaggerated observation to the
like effect could be. People must be allowed to poke fun at one another without fear
of litigation. It is one thing to ridicule a man; it is another to expose him to ridicule.
Miss Burchill made a cheap joke at Mr. Berkoff’s expense; she may thereby have
demeaned herself, but I do not believe that she defamed Mr. Berkoff.
Id. at 153. See also John v. Guardian News & Media Ltd., [2008] EWHC (QB) 3006, [47]
(Eng.) (following Berkoff, a court in Great Britain concluded that a mock “diary entry” by
Singer Sir Elton John was a form of teasing that could not be reasonably read to contain a
serious allegation).
246. One case, Entienne Pty Ltd. v Festival City Broad. Pty Ltd. (2001) 79 SASR 19
(Austl.), was based on a parody weather report in which the radio host referred to a local
street as a place to score drugs and referred to a “flash man” (a term used to refer to a drug
peddler) on the street. Although considerable media reports had stated that the street was
indeed a place to buy drugs, the tone of the parodied weather report was jocular. Allegedly
unbeknownst to the radio host, the street did have a gelateria known as “Flash Gelateria.”
The owner of the store sued. Id. at 24. The Entienne trial judge held that “a reasonable
listener . . . would be fully aware that the whole program intended to be and was a comic
program of complete nonsense. The only part of the program which makes sense is the
initial giving of the temperature.” Id. at 25. The appellate court agreed that the general
presentation was intended to be “a comic, nonsensical spoof.” Id. at 29. Nonetheless, the
appellate court allowed the appeal, noting that the segment was “built on a substratum of
fact.” Id. at 31. Although clearly a parody, the court concluded, the skit “incorporated
factual material” and conveyed the imputation that the plaintiff was indeed a drug dealer. Id.
The second case, Darbyshir v Daily Examiner Pty Ltd. (Unreported, Supreme Court of New
South Wales, Levine J, 29 August 1997) [2] (Austl.), concerned a spoof advertisement about
a plaintiff who practiced law. The plaintiff submitted imputations stating that the ad
conveyed the impression that as a lawyer, she was an unprincipled, predatory vulture. Id. at
[2]. The Supreme Court of New South Wales rejected the argument that advertisement was
incapable of being defamatory because it was a “joke.” Id. at [10]. The court emphasized
that even if it was clearly a joke, the advertisement was still capable of holding plaintiff up
to ridicule and could thus adversely reflect on the plaintiff’s reputation. Id.
Two other cases present harder calls for predicting how a court in the United States would
come out given the same facts. In one, McGuiness v J. T. Publ’g Austl. Pty Ltd. [1999]
NSWSC 471 (21 May 1999) (Austl.), the defendant’s parody insinuated that the plaintiff
would relish “emptying his service revolver into another” and the court concluded this had a
disparaging ring. Id. [8]. In the second case, Cornes v Ten Grp. Pty Ltd. [2011] SASC 104
(5 July 2011) [1]–[2] (Austl.), the plaintiffs brought a defamation action on the basis of a
comment by a talk show interviewer during an interview of a footballer. After discussion of
the footballer’s sex life and relationship with an actress, the interviewer discussed the
plaintiff’s praise of the footballer and stated: “And apparently you slept with her, too.” Id. at
[4].
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 143
with the injuries to the plaintiffs’ reputational interests, which swayed the
courts’ decisions.
247
A third case favoring the plaintiff breaks from the pattern: the court in
that case not only showed an unsympathetic approach to satire, but also
limited the defense of fair comment on governmental and political matters
in a way one would likely never expect to see reproduced in the United
States.
248
In the final case, the court not only failed to see the humor in
what could quite reasonably be taken as a jaunty, spur-of-the-moment
quip,
249
but also channeled the plaintiff’s theory of liability toward
disparagement (and away from ridicule, which it described as the less
serious theory of defamation).
250
What accounts for the general similarity in results between Australian
and United States disparagement cases? I hazard a possible explanation:
Australian culture’s commitment to humor and modesty. As a society,
247. Entienne Pty Ltd. v Festival City Broad. Pty Ltd. (2001) 79 SASR 19 (Austl.)
evaluated the damage inflicted by the drug dealing insinuation and Darbyshir v Daily
Examiner Pty Ltd. [1997] NSWSC1027 (29 August 1997) (Austl.), discussed how the
plaintiff’s reputation as a lawyer would suffer from the defendant’s defamatory message.
248. The plaintiff in the case, chairman of a political party known as Australian
National Action, sued about an article satirizing his racist views. Brander v Ryan [2000]
SALR 234, 235 (Austl.). The article contained statements about the propensity of plaintiff,
Michael Brander, for effeminate and juvenile behavior:
It’s Little Mikey and the big bad racists
How did little Mikey Brander get to be the leader of the racist gang National
Action?
Did he beat all the other, bigger NA chaps in a peeing contest or something?
It is hard to imagine how you can piddle higher than everyone else if you sit down to
take a pee. . . .
Hey, loosen up, guys! Even political revolutionaries with a brittle potential for
violence can still get in touch with the inner child. Follow your leader.
Id. In evaluating whether the defense applied, the court imposed a reasonableness standard
in evaluating whether the defendant reasonably believed that the plaintiff possessed these
qualities. Applying the reasonableness standard, the court ultimately concluded that the
plaintiff had made out the imputations that plaintiff “did not hold his political views
sincerely” and that he was motivated by “juvenile attention seeking.” Id. at 246–47. As one
commentator pointed out, this reasonableness requirement is ill-fitted for evaluating satire,
which operates by exaggeration and distortion, not congruence with reality. Magnusson,
supra note198, at 289 (observing that satire “exaggerates and distorts perspectives in order
to make its point. Rarely will a defendant hold an honest belief in the truth of the inflated,
“literal” imputations the plaintiff is likely to find most offensive.”).
249. Cornes v Ten Grp. Pty Ltd. (Unreported, Supreme Court of South Australia, Peek
J, 5 July 2011) (Austl.). Although the statement, “[a]nd apparently you slept with her, too,”
was spontaneous and part of a jocular, lighthearted interchange, id. at [5], the court
concluded that that the context suggested that it was “informative material,” id. at [42].
250. Id. at [81].
144 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
Australia not only treasures laughter, but also uses deprecating humor as
“an acculturating ritual.”
251
Australia’s affinity with laughter in general
and deprecating humor in particular is often associated with the unique
challenges of survival posed by the history and climate of the country.
252
Indeed, one scholar even noted Australian capacity for sardonic humor as
an important factor enabling Australian prisoners of war to survive
captivity more successfully than prisoners from other nations.
253
In a totally different context—during debates over liberalization of
Australia’s copyright laws to accommodate parody and satire—the
Minister for Justice told the Senate that the new exception to the Copyright
Act for both satire and parody would “ensure ‘that Australia’s fine tradition
of poking fun at itself and others will not be unnecessarily restricted.’”
254
Along the same vein, an Australian judge has explained that humor in
Australia has exploited “the larrikinism in the national character to release
us from rigidity and to push the boundaries of tolerance.”
255
Larrikinism is
the name associated with the Australian tradition of irreverent and self-
deprecating humor.
256
Onetime Attorney General Phillip Ruddock (who
later became a Member of Parliament) has opined that, “Australians have
always had an irreverent streak. . . . An integral part of their armoury is
parody and satire—or, if you prefer, ‘taking the micky’ [sic] out of
someone.”
257
Taking the mickey includes “baiting others, particularly the
obviously ‘other,’ with joking, teasing and insult.”
258
To overcome this
treatment effectively, the object of the joke is advised to acknowledge the
251. Jessica Milner Davis, ‘Aussie’ Humour and Laughter: Joking as an Acculturating
Ritual, in
SERIOUS FROLIC: ESSAYS ON AUSTLALIAN HUMOUR 31 (Fran De Groen & Peter
Kirkpatrick eds., 2009).
252. See, e.g., Gerry Turcotte, The Alternative Traditions: An Introduction to
Australian Humour, 10 T
HALIA: STUDS. LITERARY HUMOUR 3, 4–5 (1989), quoted in Davis,
supra note 251, at
31 (observing that “Australia’s humorists are still laughing as part of a
survival process” and noting that joke collectors often nominate as their favorites “a wry
narrative, often with an outback setting”).
253. Fran De Groen, Risus Sardonicus, in S
ERIOUS FROLIC: ESSAYS ON AUSTRLALIAN
HUMOUR 69, 77 (Fran De Groen & Peter Kirkpatrick eds., 2009).
254. Conal Condren et al., Defining Parody and Satire: Australian Copyright Law and
Its New Exception: Part 2—Advancing Ordinary Definitions, 13 M
EDIA & ARTS L. REV.
401, 403 (2008) (quoting Parliamentary Debates, Senate, 29 Nov. 2006, 112 (Christopher
Martin Ellison, Senator) (Austl.)).
255. Fitzgerald, supra note 198, at 14.
256. Australian Humour—Larrikin, C
ONVICTCREATIONS.COM,
http://www.convictcreations.com/culture/comedy.htm (last visited Oct. 23, 2011).
257. Jessica Milner Davis, ‘Taking the Mickey’: A Brave Australian Tradition, 4 T
HE
FINE PRINT 20, 22 (2007).
258. Id.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 145
skill of the joke and . . . well . . . to return the favor.
259
In the end, the result
is generally a few bruises that heal themselves, a stronger bond (and sense
of equality) among participants in the exchange, a feeling of membership in
a shared culture, and the mental stimulation of lively repartee.
American culture, of course, also features a key role for humor,
260
and
certainly an important component of that humor includes American love of
irreverence and dislike of arrogance.
261
Yet potent features of Australian
society captured in the term ‘larrikinism’ seem more defining of the
national character than in what has become an increasingly diverse and
atomistic American culture.
262
Thus, one might see why results in
Australian disparagement cases are similar to those in the United States. In
striking the balance between reputation and free speech, Australia generally
259. Id. (explaining that “the only truly effective response is to accept that the mickey
has indeed been taken, to appreciate its skill and to reply in kind”).
260. See, e.g., K
UIPERS, supra note 101, at 222–23, 228, which reports on a study
comparing Dutch and American reactions to jokes. The author concludes that Americans
perceive a good sense of humor as key to a person’s moral quality (Americans believe one
needs to have a sense of humor, particularly about oneself) and that Americans are more
“omnivorous” in appreciating and using humor.
261. As Professor Joseph Boskin explains: “It is explicitly declared that its historical
dimension is boundless, its character egalitarian, its breadth all-encompassing, and its
expression open and innovative. An oft-stated remark is that political irreverence is, and
peristently [sic] remains, a distinctive American trait that subjects every form of power to
humorous scrutiny and/or comedic skepticism.” Joseph Boskin, American Political Humor:
Touchables and Taboos, 11 I
NTL POL. SCI. REV. 473 (1990). See also ORING, supra note 66,
at 101 (describing how humorous invective toward another person was “an art
form . . . conceived of as poetic speech” in the American Frontier).
262. Scholars sometimes trace Australia’s defiant style of humor to the original
convicts banished to Australia, who used humor to prove they were more likeable than those
who shipped them to the Australian continent. While many might characterize contemporary
Australians as restrained and “proper,” the larrikin continues to be a stereotype with which
Australians often self identify. See, e.g., The Larrikin Legacy, C
ONVICTCREATIONS.COM,
http://www.convictcreations.com/history/larrikin.htm (last visited Oct. 23, 2011). Larrikins
are self-deprecating and make jokes about things that should not be laughed at in good
company. Making a joke at a mate’s expense signals a sense of comfort in the strength of a
relationship. Australian Humour–Larrikan, supra note 256.
One might make a case for the proposition that the attitudes of Australia and the United
States are converging. The lineage for American humor, however, differs from the
Australian tradition that gave rise to larrikinism: American attitudes toward humor arose in
the context of different experiences in the country’s original settlement (including slavery
and rehabilitation), longer initial periods of immigration, vast regional biases among the
states, and possibly wider disparity in attitudes between urban and rural dwellers. This early
diversity in the United States gave rise to diverse humor styles. As Constance Rourke wrote
in 1931: Although “[h]umor has been a fashioning instrument in America, cleaving its way
through the national life . . . [no] single unmistakable type emerged; the American character
is still split into many characters.” C
ONSTANCE ROURKE, AMERICAN HUMOR: A STUDY OF
THE
NATIONAL CHARACTER 231–32 (The N.Y. Review of Books 2004) (1931).
146 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
weighs reputation more heavily than the United States does; however,
Australia has a particularly strong factor that tips the scales for free speech:
the nation’s commitment to a “serious frolic.”
263
From a doctrinal
viewpoint, Australia has reached these results without slavish reliance on
the problem-ridden fact/opinion dichotomy. I explore this important
observation later. First, however, is another line of Australian defamatory
humor cases that requires attention.
b. Ridicule Cases
While Australian and United States disparagement cases both tend to
protect humor, the outcome of contemporary ridicule cases differ.
Australian cases from the last few decades reflect the notion that humor at
“the expense” of the plaintiff—humor that “exposed” the plaintiff to
ridicule—is actionable as defamation without apparent regard for whether
the humor suggests anything factually unflattering about the plaintiff.
264
In
fact, the District Court of New South Wales suggested that the theory has
greater currency now than in earlier points in the development of
defamation law. Specifically, the court stated that “the concept of an
imputation which holds a person up to ridicule did not receive much
judicial attention” until a 1991 decision in which the defendant had
published a photograph of “the plaintiff, a footballer, in which it is was
possible to see his penis.”
265
The court held that the photograph (which
263. The term comes from a recent scholarly study of Australian humor, SERIOUS
FROLIC: ESSAYS ON AUSTRALIAN HUMOUR (Fran De Groen & Peter Kirkpatrick eds., 2009).
264. For example, in Anderson v Gregory [2008] QCA 419 (23 December 2008)
(Austl.), the court explained that although the defendant may have intended a photograph as
a joke, the joke occurred at the plaintiff’s expense and thus exposed him to ridicule.
Specifically the Anderson court found that it was the juxtaposition of plaintiff’s visage on a
T-shirt next to the words “I beat anorexia” that exposed the plaintiff to ridicule. The court
explained that a “humourous context may in some circumstance serve to render otherwise
defamatory words harmless.” Id. at [6]. Similarly in Wild v John Fairfax Publ’n Pty Ltd.
[1997] NSWSC *1 (Unreported, Levine, J, 8 Aug. 1997) (Austl.), the plaintiff’s visage was
juxtaposed next to a photograph of female buttocks with the captions, “They like to watch”
and “In defence of female voyeurism and sexist ads.” The court found this is capable of
defamatory meaning because it gives rise to imputations that would render him liable to
“hatred, ridicule, or contempt” and “to be shunned and avoided.” Id. at *8. See also Brander
v Ryan [2000] SASC 446, 245 (Austl.) (stating that “it may be inferred from the [satirical]
article itself that the defendants were intending to hold the plaintiff up to ridicule.”).
265. O’Hara v Channel Seven Sydney Pty Ltd.,[2007] NSWDC 81 (14 September
2007) [16] (Austl.)(citing Ettingshausen v Austl. Consol. Press Ltd. (1991) 23 NSWLR
443).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 147
brought amusement to many who viewed it)
266
was capable of defaming
the plaintiff, because it could subject “the entirely blameless plaintiff to a
more than trivial degree of ridicule.”
267
Australian case law attributes the pedigree for this theory of
defamation liability to a Judge Learned Hand opinion from the United
States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit in the 1930s.
268
Ironically or
not, that case concerned a photograph featuring an optical illusion
representing the male plaintiff indulging in “indecent exposure.”
269
It
appears, however, that this theory of defamation liability is no longer
robust in the United States. This is possibly because it clashes with
subsequent First Amendment jurisprudence requiring the plaintiff to prove
266. Not surprisingly, the trial in this case also generated amusement when Hughes,
counsel for the plaintiff cross-examined Martyn, the editor of the publication that ran the
picture:
H
UGHES: It is a penis isn’t it?
M
ARTYN: I assume if it is in that part of the body, may be it could be or it might not
be.
H
UGHES: What else could it be . . . is it a duck?
R
EPUTATION, CELEBRITY AND DEFAMATION LAW, supra note 211, at 151 (describing the
interchange as “one of the most famous pieces of cross-examination in Australian legal
history.”). The interchange here is apparently an example of trans-Tasman ribbing, tied to
the specifics of New Zealand pronunciation, which to the Australian ear interchanges the
sounds duck and dick (Martyn is a New Zealander).
267. O’Hara v Channel Seven Sydney Pty Ltd.,[2007] NSWDC 81 (14 September
2007) [16] (Austl.). In a case similar to Ettingshausen (the footballer’s penis case) the court
used the ridicule rationale to impose defamation liability on a man who fraudulently
submitted a naked picture of his ex-girlfriend, the plaintiff, a magazine in which it was
subsequently published. Shepherd v Walsh [2001] QSC (Unreported, Jones J, 6 September
2001) (Austl.). See R
EPUTATION, CELEBRITY AND DEFAMATION LAW, supra note 211, at
151–67
for analysis of Shepherd v Walsh and another instance where defamation liability
was threatened for publishing a photograph of exposed body parts.
268. See, e.g., O’Hara v Channel Seven Sydney Pty Ltd.,[2007] NSWDC 81 (14
September 2007) [16] (Austl.) (citing Burton v. Crowell Publ’g Co., 82 F.2d 154 (2d Cir.
1936)).
269. Burton v. Crowell Publ’g Co., 82 F.2d 154, 154 (2d Cir. 1936) (reporting that the
plaintiff alleged that the photograph suggested he was “physically deformed and mentally
perverted”). The case does not name the body part involved, but the description suggests
that the photograph depicted that the plaintiff’s penis as “grotesque, monstrous, and
obscene.” Id. For another, older example of this concern with ridicule, see Triggs v. Sun
Printing & Publ’g Ass’n, 71 N.E. 739, 742 (N.Y. 1904) (quoting Donoghue v. Hayes,
(1831) Hayes Ir. Exch. Rep. 265, 266), which found statements that were “calculated . . . to
injure the plaintiff’s reputation, and to expose him to public contempt, ridicule, or shame” to
be libelous per se. For a discussion of older United States cases, see generally Eric Scott
Fulcher, Note, Rhetorical Hyperbole and the Reasonable Person Standard: Drawing the
Line Between Figurative Expression and Factual Defamation, 38 G
A. L. REV. 717, 726
(2004).
148 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
falsity in defamation actions,
270
or because plaintiffs have found that
invasion of privacy doctrine is more amendable to such tort claims.
271
A central impulse behind these ridicule cases seems to reflect a desire
to remedy damage to the plaintiff’s dignity.
272
Indeed, ever since Professor
Robert Post’s classic work, The Social Foundations of Defamation Law:
Reputation and the Constitution, identified the specific components of
reputation implicated by defamation law, few would dispute that dignity—
along with property and honor—are possible human interests that a
defamatory communication can damage.
273
Post describes dignity as a
private concept that operates in a public sphere and encompasses “the
respect (and self-respect) that arises from full membership in society.”
274
He explains that “[p]ersons who are socially acceptable will be included
within the forms of respect that constitute social dignity.”
275
When that
social dignity is damaged, a court might rehabilitate it with a defamation
270. In Philadelphia Newspapers, Inc. v. Hepps, 475 U.S. 767, 777 (1986), the
Supreme Court held that the First Amendment requires plaintiffs to prove falsity in a
defamation action “against a media defendant for speech of public concern.” In a subsequent
decision, justices writing in separate opinions concluded that this holding should not be
confined to media defendants. See Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472
U.S. 749, 773 (1985) (White, J., concurring). Although one might argue that something like
inadvertent nudity is not a matter of public concern, Philadelphia Newspapers and Dun &
Bradstreet offer a disincentive for plaintiffs to choose defamation when trying to frame a
tort cause of action.
271. See, e.g., Daily Times Democrat v. Graham, 162 So.2d 474 (Ala. 1964)
(recognizing invasion of privacy cause of action where reporter took photograph of
plaintiff’s skirt being blown above her waist at a fun house); R
ESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF
TORTS §652 (1977) (providing that “[o]ne who intentionally intrudes, physically or
otherwise, upon the solitude or seclusion of another or his private affairs or concerns, is
subject to liability to the other for invasion of his privacy, if the intrusion would be highly
offensive to a reasonable person”).
272. R
OLPH, supra note 211, at 147. Indeed, one explanation for these cases is that they
arise in the defamation context, because Australia lacks the privacy tort that might remedy
similar violations under American law. See Peter Bartlett, Privacy Down Under, 3 J. INTL
MEDIA & ENT. L. 145, 163 (2010) (discussing lack of general protection of individual
privacy under Australian law).
273. Post, supra note 122, at 693. Post describes the interests of property and honor as
follows: property is “understood to be a form of ‘capital’ since it ‘creates funds’ and the
potential for ‘patronage and support.’” Id. at 694 (quoting J
OEL HAWES, LECTURES
ADDRESSED TO THE YOUNG MEN OF HARTFORD AND NEW HAVEN 112 (Oliver D. Cooke &
Co.1828)). According to Post, honor “can be forfeited by improper behavior, but . . . cannot
be individually created.” Id. at 70. Honor, he explains, “is a matter of either fulfilling or
failing to fulfill the requirements of one’s social position.” Id.
274. Id. at
711.
275. Id.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 149
remedy by “authoritatively determin[ing] that the defendant’s departure
from the rules of civility was unjustified.”
276
Under Post’s analysis, one is hardly surprised that contemporary
United States courts seem uninterested in using defamation liability to
remedy injury to dignity. In Post’s view, that portion of reputation
representing dignity clashes with “the essential premise of constitutional
autonomy.”
277
And what is that central premise? It is “the right to differ as
to things that touch the heart of the existing order.”
278
United States courts
might be more comfortable curtailing the right to challenge “the existing
order” when the plaintiff’s cause of action features an individual right
possessing comparable constitutional pedigree—such as privacy. This
would explain the inclination of United States courts to allow invasion of
privacy actions to remedy damages to dignity.
279
United States case law was the raw material for Post’s analysis. In a
parallel study of Australian cases, Professor David Rolph points out that
Post’s conceptualization fails to account for “a significant rights-based
jurisprudence in common law countries, such as Canada, the United
Kingdom and New Zealand, [which manifests] a concern for individual
reputation as a dignitary right.”
280
International instruments such as the International Covenant for
Political and Civil Rights and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
also reflect this emphasis on individual dignity.
281
Yet this observation
does not explain Australia’s approach to ridicule cases, since Australian
courts and law makers have not formally developed such a rights-based
jurisprudence.
282
Nonetheless, Australia’s embrace of international law and
overlapping legal traditions with those countries that share its enthusiasm
for international law may provide some explanation for its adherence to a
conception of defamation that protects against invasion on individual
276. Id. at 712–31.
277. Id. at 737.
278. Id. at 737–38
(citing W. V. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943)).
279. For a review of such actions, see R
ESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §652 (1977)
(annotations). For a contrary suggestion, arguing that American courts are sometimes
reluctant to use privacy torts in place defamation, see supra note 198.
280. R
OLPH, supra note 211, at 30.
281. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, art. 17, Dec. 16, 1966, 999
U.N.T.S. 171 (linking protection of reputation to sanctity of privacy); Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 (III) A, U.N. Doc. A/RES/217(III) (Dec. 10, 1948).
282.
ROLPH, supra note 211, at 30. The ridicule cases may, however, be viewed as an
attempt to remedy an invasion of privacy—which of course protects a form of human
dignity with analytical kinship to the individual to reputation.
150 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
dignity. Moreover, what is even clearer is that (sadly for many of us) the
United States has not embraced such enthusiasm for international
definitions of human rights. One can, then, credibly explain at least some of
the gulf between the United States and Australia by pointing to a different
approach to the individual right of human dignity.
c. Hanson v. Australian Broadcasting Corp.: A Category of its Own
One prominent Australian defamatory humor case does not fit neatly
into the disparagement/ridicule paradigm: Hanson v. Australian
Broadcasting Corp.
283
Although unusual, this case should not be dismissed
as simply sui generis. Hanson deserves serious attention because of its
prominence in the fabric of Australian defamation lore and its capacity to
shed light on the difficulties of regulating defamatory humor.
The Hanson plaintiff, Pauline Hanson, was a member of the
Australian House of Representatives who advocated such policies as
governmental barriers for prospective immigrants to Australia, pride in
Australian nationalism, and eliminating special government assistance for
aboriginal people.
284
She brought the defamation suit to enjoin a musical
composition entitled “Back Door Man” from being broadcast on national
radio, and—remarkably from the standpoint of an American jurist—she
succeeded in getting her requested injunction.
285
The challenged broadcast
was created with sound tracks of Hanson’s own words, stringing together
snippets of her speeches to provide the song’s lyrics. The lyrics are a
nonsensical ramble, including such statements as: “I’m a back door man”;
“I’m a homosexual”; “I’ve called for a homosexual government”; “I’m
proud that I’m not straight”; “I’m not human”; “I like trees and I like
shrubs and plants”; “I’m a backdoor man for the Klu [sic] Klux Klan with a
very horrendous plan. I’m a very caring potato.”
286
Invoking concern with
political speech, the Australian Broadcasting Corporation fought the
injunction request by arguing that the sexual and Ku Klux Klan references
in the song alluded “in a satirical or ironic sense to
283. See Austl. Broad. Corp. v Hanson [1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998) (Austl.).
284. L.M.
BOGAD, ELECTORAL GUERILLA THEATRE: RADICAL RIDICULE AND SOCIAL
MOVEMENTS 167–68 (2005); Geoffrey Stokes, One Nation and Australian Populism, in THE
RISE AND FALL OF ONE NATION 23, 27–29 (Michael Leach, Geoffrey Stokes & Ian Ward
eds., 2000).
285. The case is also remarkable under Australian law itself, which shares the
American aversion to prior restraint of speech. See David Rolph, Showing Restraint:
Interlocutory Injunctions in Defamation Cases, 14 M
EDIA & ARTS L. REV. 255 (2009).
286. Austl. Broad. Corp. v Hanson [1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998) [2] (Austl.).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 151
[Hanson’s] . . . conservative political views”
287
as a House of
Representatives member. Rejecting this contention, the Queensland
appellate court found nothing in the song relating to discussion of public
matters “fundamental to our democratic society.”
288
The appellate court
approvingly cited the lower court’s conclusion that the song was
defamatory because it asserted that she was a pedophile and a
homosexual.
289
By the measure of the courts’ reasoning, Hanson is a disparagement
case: the song defamed Pauline Hanson because it suggested that she
possessed ‘unsavory’ characteristics such as homosexual and pedophilic
tendencies. But is that really how the courts interpreted the song? Is that
really the wrong the courts sought to remedy? Several reasons suggest
otherwise. To begin with, the suggestion that Hanson possesses these
tendencies is extravagantly far from any facts known about her. Hanson
was well known to believe that homosexuality is unnatural.
290
Second, the
creator of the song—Simon Hunt—had explained that he used a satirical
strategy in the lyrics similar to that used by Weimar satirists in Berlin
cabarets, who found it necessary to find alternatives to usual exaggeration
strategies in satirizing Adolf Hitler’s views.
291
Hunt said that like these
Hitler satirists, he sought to reveal the “ridiculousness of [Hanson’s] style
of argumentation by using it in retaliation to different matters.”
292
As such,
whatever one says about the decision, the courts clearly did not embrace
the song on the terms it was intended—on a literal level it was nonsense,
yet on a deeper, rhetorical level it was a serious comment on Hanson’s
communication style and politics.
287. Id. at 4.
288. Id. at 6.
289. Id. at 5.
290. See Magnusson, supra note198, at 285. Commentators were somewhat
dumbfounded by the courts’ suggestion that the song should in any way be taken as
suggesting anything factual. See M
ARGO KINGSTON, OFF THE RAILS: THE PAULINE HANSON
TRIP 194 (1999) (observing that after the judgment in the Hanson case, “a posse of Sydney
defamation lawyers and academics lampooned its reasoning”); Elizabeth Handsley & Gary
Davis, Case Notes, Defamation and Satire: Hanson v. Australian Broadcasting Corporation,
2000 TLJ
LEXIS 12 (2000) (reasoning that “many of the statements in the song were just so
silly, either on their face or in the context [of being heard in Mrs. Hanson’s voice], that the
listener would have been on notice that the song was not to be taken literally”); Magnusson,
supra note198, at 286 (explaining that the song’s satire derives in part from “the insertion in
Hanson’s own voice, of seemingly random and incoherent non sequiturs. They provide a
biting critique of Hanson’s speech patterns and interview style.”).
291. Magnusson, supra note 198, at 284–85.
292. Handsley & Davis, supra note 290, at 4 (paraphrasing Simon Hunt).
152 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
The appellate court also treated the defendant to a “tails I win, heads
you lose” approach to the defendant’s “fair comment” defense. On one
hand, the court rejected the defendant’s averment that the song constituted
a good faith comment on a subject of public interest, noting that sexual
preferences were matters of private, not public, interest.
293
The court also
reasoned, however, that the defendant’s arguments were internally
inconsistent since the defendant relied on a defense designed to protect
serious matters of public debate, yet maintained that the song itself should
be “dismissed as a piece of derisory fun or nonsense not to be taken in any
degree seriously.”
294
As commentators have argued, this reasoning handed
the defendant the worst of all worlds: “[T]he material was taken literally
and seriously for the purpose of determining whether it was irresistibly
defamatory, and rejected as a piece of nonsense for the purpose of
determining the potential availability of the [fair comment] defense.”
295
What besides literal disparagement of Pauline Hanson might have
concerned the courts? Could it be a perceived attack on her dignity? The
Hanson court’s reference to the “private matters” of sexual preference adds
credence to this interpretation—as does the court’s embrace of a strained
reading of the alleged untruths in the song.
296
Hanson may thus be taken on
its own terms as a disparagement case or conceived of as a ridicule case.
And, as suggested earlier, one could also simply dismiss the case as a
293. Austl. Broad. Corp. v Hanson [1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998) [5] (Austl.).
294. Id.
295. Handsley & Davis, supra note 290, at 22. See also Magnusson, supra note 198, at
282 (reasoning that where “the imputation of ridicule arises from particular words that can
be regarded as either expressing an opinion or asserting a fact, the quality of ‘ridicule’ will
often arise from exaggerated or false meanings in ways that would defeat the defences of
truth or fair comment”).
296. Reading the Hanson decision as concerned with avoiding ridicule and attacks on
the dignity of an elected politician might shed light on another phenomenon in Australian
defamation practice that was documented before the decision: at one time, Australian
politicians represented proportionally greater percentage of defamation plaintiffs than
elected politicians represent among United States defamation plaintiffs. See Newcity, supra
note 189, at 25–26
(observing that “[w]hereas Australian elected officials initiate
proportionally more defamation suits than do their American counterparts, Australian
nonelected public officials bring a smaller portion of defamation suits than do American
nonelected officials”). One surmises that Australian politicians pursue their lawsuits with
the expectation of successfully vindicating their alleged injury. A ready explanation for the
disparity is the formal obstacle in the United States (missing in Australia) of New York
Times, Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964), and its actual malice standard. Yet the High
Court adopted a similar approach to New York Times, Co. v. Sullivan in 1997. See Lange v
Austl. Broad. Corp. (1997) 189 CLR 520, 548–49 (Austl.). One wonders whether the
statistics would come out differently today.
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 153
sport—albeit a sport with interesting insights into defamatory humor
regulation.
4. Australian Lessons for the United States
Australian defamation cases have a variety of lessons for United
States defamatory humor cases. Some of the disputes would have come out
quite differently in the United States and stand as an example of what not
to do. Certainly a prior restraint like that issued in Hanson would be
inimical to First Amendment doctrine, as would unfettered defamation
liability asserted by a public official such as Pauline Hanson on a matter
with such obvious political content. The courts’ handling of the humor
defense is also not worthy of imitation, since the reasoning suggests that
humor cannot convey serious political messages.
297
To treat humor in this
way is not only to fail to understand the subtleties of political discourse, but
also to denigrate the skill and artistry of humorists.
298
The Australian ridicule cases are also not a particularly useful
paradigm for United States courts seeking guidance with defamatory
humor. The Australian cases’ solicitude for dignitary interests likely
clashes with the First Amendment doctrine’s current orientation toward
restricting defamation liability by giving wide berth to dissent from the
settled order. Were United States courts to track the Australian ridicule
cases in developing defamation doctrine, one can imagine the cries of
criticism bemoaning the loss of the First Amendment’s force in protecting
unpopular ideas.
That is not to say that protecting dignity, which is often given short
shrift as Americans struggle with such questions as whether and how to
regulate racist or hate speech, is not a worthy concept. Yet the context of
humorous ridicule does not present the best setting for venturing an
experiment with regulating communication’s potential for harming human
dignity. For many cases, a cause of action already exists in the United
States to remedy such harms: invasion of privacy.
299
To add defamation as
297. McCallum, supra note 238, at 214 (arguing that as framed in Hanson, the humor
defense suggests that “comedy itself is a ridiculous activity that has earned no right to be
taken seriously . . . [and] implies that comedy is inevitably constrained by its own absurdity
and can never operate in the real world of political and intellectual discourse”).
298. Id. at 215 (arguing that humor defense is “a denigration of the work of any
artist . . . challenging such basic principles of comic practice as recognition-humour,
identification and comic distance from painful realities”).
299. I do not, however, want to overstate the availability of invasion of privacy as a
theory of liability. As Professor Rodney Smolla has pointed out, United States courts
actually seem to prefer defamation to other dignitary torts—at least where defamation
liability is available. My point, however, is that defamation is not really a viable option in
154 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
a theory of liability would pick a fight with the First Amendment where the
fight might not be necessary to correct a wrong done. Moreover, the United
States has experienced dramatic social, political, and legal controversy over
regulating speech where attacks on dignity are mixed with actual threats to
safety.
300
The magnitude of these controversies suggests that allowing
defamation doctrine to regulate attacks on dignity alone would be unwise,
whether or not those attacks manifest as humor or attempts at humor.
A more apt context for United States courts to consider a more
nuanced understanding of dignity and other forms of reputation is that of
disparagement cases, where humor inflicts harm on the plaintiff by
suggesting something negative about the plaintiff’s character or actions. It
is here that the Australian disparagement cases might provide useful
lessons. In the disparagement context, Australian courts often reached the
same humor-protecting results as one would expect in United States courts.
Yet the Australian courts arrived at the results without the obfuscation and
difficulties of First Amendment doctrine governing fact and opinion.
this context, so we should simply leave in place invasion of privacy actions where existing
law would support them in meritorious cases. See Rodney A. Smolla, Accounting for the
Slow Growth of American Privacy Law, 27 N
OVA L. REV. 289, 292–96 (2002) (stating that
“false light” right of privacy causes of action have been “devoured” by defamation actions).
Smolla explains that the commonly asserted distinction that defamation compensates for
reputational damage while false light is for emotional harm is largely academic and blurred
in real world defamation practice. Courts are permissive in allowing plaintiffs to recover for
essentially internal emotional injuries in defamation actions. Id. at 294.
300. See, e.g., C. Edwin Baker, Autonomy and Hate Speech, in E
XTREME SPEECH AND
DEMOCRACY 139, 147 (Ivan Hare & James Weinstein eds., 2009) (arguing that regulators
should restrict hate speech only upon an empirical showing of such matters as virulent
racism or genocidal practices such that the need to protect individuals from the harm of hate
speech outweighs the societal benefits of autonomy and the protection of democracy that
come with absolute free speech); Mari J. Matsuda, Legal Storytelling: Public Response to
Racist Speech: Considering the Victim’s Story, 87 M
ICH. L. REV. 2320, 2336–38, 2351–53
(1989) (describing how the United States has protected such activities as Ku Klux Klan
marches, but has heretofore been reluctant to protect against the effect of hate speech on
victims, which can include physiological symptoms, emotional distress, and psychological
effects that prompt victims to “quit jobs, forgo [sic] education . . . avoid certain public
places, curtail their own exercise of speech rights, and otherwise modify their behavior and
demeanor”); Ronald Turner, Regulating Hate Speech and the First Amendment: The
Attractions of, and Objections to, an Explicit Harms-Based Analysis, 29 I
ND. L. REV. 257,
294–97 (1995) (pointing out that the United States has avoided regulating hate speech even
though it can cause individuals the same humiliation, damage to reputation, and emotional
torment that victims of dignitary torts suffer); Jeremy Waldron, Dignity and Defamation:
The Visibility of Hate, 123 H
ARV. L. REV. 1596, 1636 (2010) (arguing that a free speech
exception should be fashioned to protect against the brutal spirit murder resulting from hate
speech and pointing out that the values of autonomy of personal expression and democracy
do not merit protecting other damaging forms of expression, such as child pornography).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 155
The fact/opinion dichotomy is a well-intentioned mechanism for
seeking to identify when a communication suggests an untruth that inflicts
harm on the plaintiff. Yet it is riddled with difficulties in application in the
humor context and often displaces discussion of the individual reputational
interests implicated in a case. Although I do not advocate abandoning the
dichotomy altogether, I do suggest that analysis would benefit if courts
explicitly considered the harm to the plaintiff’s reputation that may go
unremedied if the defamation case fails.
301
The fact/opinion dichotomy
might continue to play a role in the decision so long as it does not obfuscate
the reputational injury and courts are mindful of the dichotomy’s
significant limitations in understanding humor’s impact.
The First Amendment is key to the political, governmental, and social
systems in the United States, but it is not a shorthand or a replacement for
justice. First Amendment doctrine should not hijack discussion of all
factors relevant to whether a court should regulate communication. Candor
and good judicial decision-making in the United States would be served by
explicit discussion of all aspects of the plaintiff’s reputation threatened by
the defendant’s attempt at a joke. This, it seems, is the most forthright
approach to evaluating how and when to accommodate the corrective
justice goals at play when our system of civil justice recognizes a cause of
action for defamation.
IV. INCONGRUITY’S PROMISE
We have seen, thus far, several mechanisms for guiding United States
courts in the difficult task of regulating defamatory humor. When used
judiciously, the First Amendment and common law doctrines governing the
fact/opinion distinction help take account of important interests associated
with free expression, such as truth seeking, individual autonomy, social
tolerance, and democratic self-governance.
302
Next, experience from other
301. This approach is arguably consistent with public opinion. A recent study by the
First Amendment Center concludes that “a significant percentage of Americans are reluctant
to give full First Amendment protection to comedic speech, art or performances that could
potentially insult or offend others. There appears to be a willingness to give up a little
liberty in exchange for fewer hurt feelings.” Kenneth A. Paulson, Comedy and Freedom of
Speech, F
REEDOM FORUM (2002), available at
http://www.freedomforum.org/publications/first/sofa/2002/ComedyandFreedomofSpeech.pd
f. The two topics that the study found Americans most comfortable with regulating were
humor that was offensive to racial groups (with 63 percent believing government should
prevent such comments in public) and to religious groups (with 58 percent believing
government should prevent such comments in public). See id.
302. See supra notes 141–149 and accompanying text for further discussion of these
values, which are reviewed generally in C
HEMERINSKY, supra note 121, at 925–32.
156 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
countries, such as Australia, provides the framework for more nuanced
consideration of reputational interests. While the First Amendment remains
a mainstay of American civil liberties and government, justice provides
counsel that explicit consideration of a defamation plaintiff’s various
reputational injuries is necessary, and the Australian cases demonstrate an
important angle on that process.
Fortunately, courts have yet another important mechanism for
evaluating whether to regulate defamatory humor: interdisciplinary
understanding of humor’s various permutations. In particular, the three
categories of humor—superiority humor, release humor, and incongruity
humor—provide a useful rubric for courts deciding whether to use civil
remedies in defamation actions to regulate humor. In using these
categories, courts must tread carefully, since the categories are not
mutually exclusive and the characterization of a particular joke requires a
large measure of subjective interpretation. Nonetheless, the characterization
process can help courts evaluate the social interests in protecting the joke
from regulation. By focusing on what type of humor is involved in a
challenged communication, the court can more knowledgeably evaluate the
conflicting interests, considering both the nature and scope of the plaintiff’s
injury as well as the nature and scope of the defendant’s misconduct.
Of the three categories, superiority humor is probably the most
straightforward. If a court concludes that the primary purpose of a joke is to
disparage others to the jokester’s advantage, the court can comfortably
conclude that the joke strikes at the heart of tort law’s goal: providing an
avenue of civil recourse to remedy a tortious injury inflicted to benefit the
wrongdoer.
303
The court may ultimately determine that First Amendment
considerations mandate avoiding liability. For example, the Supreme Court
often cites parody and satire as humor forms worthy of constitutional
protection.
304
If, however, a court decides to insulate the superiority humor
303. See, e.g., Goldberg & Zipursky, supra note 11, at 918 (arguing that the goal of tort
suits is to provide plaintiffs with an avenue for getting redress from those who have inflicted
a wrong on them). Goldberg and Zipursky focus their energy on analyzing the importance of
a “wrongs-based” view of tort law rather than a “loss-based” view. See id. at 946. It is not
necessary for me to enter a debate about this distinction, since the distinction is not crucial
to identifying a useful role for characterizing the type of humor involved in a defamation
action. The character of the joke is relevant to appreciating both the scope of the defendant’s
misconduct and the plaintiff’s injury.
304. See, e.g., Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 54–56 (1988) (celebrating the
importance of parodists and satirists in public debate over politics); Falwell v. Flynt, 805
F.2d 484, 487 (4th Cir. 1986) (Wilkinson, J., dissenting from denial of petition for en banc
rehearing) (“[s]atire is particularly relevant to political debate because it tears down facades,
deflates stuffed shirts, and unmasks hypocrisy”); Fitzgerald, supra note 198, at
14
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 157
from liability, the court does so with the understanding of possible personal
injury that might go unremedied.
By contrast, release humor is probably the least helpful of the three
humor categories. To be sure, plenty of sources suggest that release humor
serves important individual and social functions of processing discomfort
with taboo or negative subjects.
305
Yet these functions do not translate
neatly into any calculus about whether a court should regulate defamatory
humor. Specifically, one wonders whose discomfort a court should
consider and how: The jokester’s discomfort? The discomfort of the
plaintiff who was the joke’s subject? Or should the court simply consider
general social disapproval or collective discomfort over the subject matter?
This latter possibility leads to a particular problem with regulating release
humor: when a court decides to regulate a joke about one of the subjects
associated with release humor—sex, incest, death, disability, excretion, and
the like—one wonders whether the court is simply imposing its view of bad
taste.
306
Not only is the role of regulating taste inherently problematic for a
court, but the concept of “taste” is relatively unhelpful in evaluating First
Amendment values.
307
What is an especially useful aid in deciding cases of defamatory
humor is the concept of incongruity. Starting with the premise that humor
is often artistic and beneficial to individuals and communities, a court
should evaluate whether in fact a communication can be characterized as
humorous. Incongruity theory provides a testing rod.
As discussed above, most humor theorists maintain that incongruity is
a necessary, though not sufficient, condition for a communication to be
(explaining satire’s important social role that “combines laughter with information and
[sometimes lacerating] criticism.”).
305. See supra notes 35–40 and accompanying text for a discussion of the function of
release humor.
306. See New Times, Inc. v. Isaacks, 146 S.W.3d 144, 157, 166 (Tex. 2004)
(explaining that courts should not be cast in the role of monitoring “bad taste”); Little, supra
note 3, at 1285–88 (discussing the problems that arise when courts are cast in the role of
regulating taste).
307. It is perhaps for this reason that United States courts initially abandoned trying to
determine whether humor improperly undermined the dignity of a particular plaintiff. For an
example of the Supreme Court steering clear of defining First Amendment restrictions on
governmental judgments about taste, see, for example, Nat’l Endowment for the Arts v.
Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 585–86 (1998), observing that in the arts funding context, the
government is making decisions about “artistic worth” and cannot be guided by “absolute
neutrality.”
158 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
funny.
308
Thus, a court evaluating whether a communication merits
protection from liability might, as a starting point, evaluate the degree of
incongruity contained in the communication. Incongruity comes in many
permutations, some slapstick-ed-ly obvious and some nuanced. Common
heuristics of incongruity humor nonetheless exist, suggesting that a court
might look fruitfully for such rhetorical techniques as juxtaposition of
diverse phenomenon, illogical or irrational sequencing, joinder of
opposites, dueling scripts, and a set-up that primes for a later surprise.
309
Of course, a court’s identifying one of these techniques in a
communication does not definitively determine that the communication is
funny or should be insulated from liability. The presence of incongruity,
however, suggests that those who viewed or heard the communication were
more likely to have perceived it as a joke, as something not to be
interpreted literally and as something communicated for a reason other than
simply conveying information about its subject. If that is the case, then the
communication may be less likely to hurt the plaintiff.
310
In this way,
incongruity serves a useful proxy for the reasonable reader’s or listener’s
understanding: the greater the incongruity, the less likely that the reader or
listener interpreted the communication as conveying solidly unflattering
“truths” about the plaintiff. In addition, the incongruity’s presence cues the
court to the possibility that the communication is capable of amusing its
audience and, thus, might satisfy one of the myriad positive functions, for
individuals or groups, associated with humor.
Incongruity, therefore, provides tests for understanding how a
communication is interpreted, as well as for evaluating the individual and
social worth of the communication. Both of these are important, though not
determinative, factors for a court to consider while evaluating whether a
communication is the type that should flourish, unfettered by civil liability.
In other words, incongruity’s presence performs a screening function: a
first step signaling the court to continue with the complex process of
308. See supra notes 41–44, 55–65, and accompanying text for a discussion of
authority supporting the necessity of incongruity to humor.
309. See supra notes 3945–54 and accompanying text for an inventory of various
earmarks of incongruity humor.
310. In addition to the possibility that a mere joke might not inflict harm, damages
from humor may be particularly difficult to establish. Under First Amendment principles
established in Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 349 (1974), liability for defamation
“extends no further than compensation for actual injury,” proven by competent evidence.
Even if jokes are actionable, they may be unlikely to cause provable reputational injury. See
Dorsen, supra note 9
(pointing out the difficulty of providing damages from satire).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 159
evaluating whether First Amendment or defamation principles protect the
communication.
A. A
RE COURTS CAPABLE AND WILLING TO IDENTIFY INCONGRUITY?
Is testing for incongruity an intellectual operation that courts have the
capacity and willingness to undertake? Yes. Courts interpret texts all the
time, testing for such qualities as argumentation technique, linguistic
patterns, logic, and internal consistency.
311
Moreover, one can infer courts’
capacity to discern incongruity from anecdotal evidence showing that they
are already implicitly scanning challenged communications for
incongruities. In an earlier study, I concluded that courts in three legal
contexts evince a consistent tendency not to impose civil liability for
incongruity humor.
312
The contexts I studied are diverse—contract,
trademark infringement, and employment discrimination—and arguably
represent three pillars of law (contract, property, and tort).
Defamation cases show the same preference for incongruity humor. In
the United States, this preference is clear from the fact/opinion dichotomy
itself. When evaluating whether a communication suggests any factual
matters about the plaintiff, courts are routinely asking whether the qualities
of the communication—such as its logic and its congruence with known or
external circumstances—could be reasonably understood as describing real
facts.
313
Several classic as well as contemporary cases illustrate how this
search for factual inferences is really no more than a search for
incongruities in the challenged communication. For example, in Polygram
Records, Inc. v. Superior Court,
314
the court evaluated a defamation claim
311. Michael L. Geis, On Meaning: The Meaning of Meaning in the Law, 73 WASH. U.
L. Q. 1125, 1132 (1995) (presenting a case study of linguistic reasoning in the Supreme
Court); Peter Meijes Tiersma, The Judge as Linguist, 27 L
OY. L. REV. 269, 269-70 (1993)
(exploring judicial analysis of language in a variety of contexts, including criminal law,
torts, contracts, and wills); Stephanie A. Vaughan, Persuasion Is An Art . . . but It Is Also an
Invaluable Tool in Advocacy, 61 B
AYLOR L. REV. 635 (2009) (discussing effective
persuasive techniques). See generally L
AWRENCE M. SOLAN, THE LANGUAGE OF JUDGES
(1993) (reviewing linguistics analyses in judicial opinions). See Janet E. Ainsworth, In a
Different Register: The Pragmatics of Powerlessness in Police Interrogation, 103 Y
ALE L.J.
259, 320–21 (1993) (analyzing linguistic differences between men and women and
proposing that legal doctrines accommodate these differences).
312. See Little, supra note 3, at 1239
(describing preference for incongruity humor in
contract, trademark infringement, and employment cases).
313. See, e.g., New Times, Inc. v. Isaacks, 146 S.W.3d 144, 158 (Tex. 2004)
(evaluating whether a newspaper spoof was subject to defamation liability by analyzing
whether the publication could reasonably be understood as describing real facts).
314. Polygram Records, Inc. v. Superior Court, 216 Cal. Rptr. 252 (Ct. App. 1985).
160 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
based on Comedian Robin Williams’s parody of advertising practices and
wine snobbery. According to the court, Williams developed his parody
around “the fantasy of a black wine ‘tough enough’ to be advertised by
‘Mean Joe Green.’”
315
In the crescendo of its decision insulating the parody
from liability, the court concluded that Williams’s “suggestions that the
hypothetical wine is a ‘motherfucker,’ black in color, tastes like urine, goes
with anything ‘it’ damn well pleases, or is ‘tough’ or endorsed by ruffians
are obvious figments of a comic imagination impossible for any sensible
person to take seriously.”
316
Along the same lines, another court scanned a fictional editorial for
signs of imaginative “exaggeration and distortion,” concluding that the
editorial contained too many incongruities to support defamation
liability.
317
Referring to specific parts of the editorial, the court queried:
“Would a six-year-old be able to comment intelligently on the works of
[J.D.] Salinger and [Mark] Twain, while using expressions like ‘[e]xcuse
my French’? Would a faith-based organization label itself ‘GOOF’? Would
a judge say that it is time to panic and overreact?”
318
Often United States courts look for reference to an act or state of
being that is physically impossible. Thus, the court in Pring v. Penthouse
International, Ltd.
319
concluded a spoof’s description of a beauty contestant
315. Id. at 260.
316. Id. at 260–61.
317. Isaacks, 146 S.W.3d at 158.
318. The specific portions of the editorial supporting these rhetorical questions
provided as follows:
*Reference to a freedom-opposing religious group that goes by the acronym,
“GOOF,” standing for “God Fearing Opponents of Freedom.”
*Reference to a judge stating that “any implication of violence in a school
setting . . . is reason enough for panic and overreaction.”
*Reference to a six-year old’s statement in reaction to her book report: “Like, I’m
sure. It’s bad enough people think like Salinger and Twain are dangerous, but
[Maurice] Sendak? Give me a break, for Christ’s sake. Excuse my French.
Id. at 149, 158.
An even more recent example is Hamilton v. Prewett, 860 N.E.2d 1234, 1247 (Ind. Ct. App.
2007). In Hamilton, the court decided that a website was not capable of defamation liability
because it was a parody. In support of this decision, the court noted that the website asserted
that a group of “Amish Aliens” from another solar system invaded the Earth and were
taking over the world by placing minerals in our water. Id. at 1246. The parody continued
that the only way to cope was to “submit to Amish Aliens” or to purchase the plaintiff’s
water conditioning products. Id.
319. Pring v. Penthouse Int’l, Ltd., 695 F.2d 438, 441 (10th Cir. 1982) (evaluating a
beauty contest spoof by reference to rhetorical hyperbole case law and deciding that the
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 161
having sex with her coach during a competition involved physically
impossible acts. Another court reasoned that liability should not attach to a
song parody containing illogical or impossible statements, such as directing
the plaintiff to “‘move on in’ with his ‘live-in lover.’”
320
Australian defamation cases also track incongruity reasoning. For
example, Australian courts take the position that “vulgar abuse” escapes
liability, reasoning that a communication can be “so excessive, irrational
and disproportionate that the imputations conveyed would not be taken
seriously, and so cannot reasonably be said to arise.”
321
Similarly,
defamation liability does not attach if the challenged communication is
“self-evidently absurd”
322
or the plaintiff could not reasonably be believed
to possess certain unfavorable qualities.
323
United States and Australian courts thus already seem to have made
their way to a similar insight as humor theorists: a communication
containing incongruities is more likely to be funny and less likely to be
interpreted as a serious statement. This practice suggests that courts would
take well to more explicit consideration of incongruity as part of textual
analysis of allegedly defamatory humor.
spoof could not be interpreted as providing actual facts since the spoof presented
“impossibility and fantasy within a fanciful story”).
320. Freedlander v. Edens Broad., Inc., 734 F. Supp. 221, 228 (E.D. Va. 1990).
321. Magnusson, supra note 198.
322. Coleman v John Fairfax Publ’ns Pty Ltd., (2003) NSWSC 564 (25 June 2003)
[22]–[23] (Austl.).
323. Brander v Ryan [2000] SASC 446 ¶¶ 77–89 (Austl.). Prior to the Uniform
Defamation Act, Australian courts also made use of the concept of congruency in evaluating
the fair comment defense. As a judge stated in one case: “I am of the opinion that . . . the
comment established by the defendant should be congruent with the imputation to which it
is pleaded. If a comment is established which falls short of such congruency the defence is
not made out.” David Syme & Co. v Lloyd [1984] 3 NSWLR 346, 358 (Austl.) (Glass, JA),
discussed in Andrew Kenyon, Defamation, Artistic Criticism, and Fair Comment, 18
S
YDNEY L. REV. 193, 209–10 (1996). Australian Broadcasting Corp. v Hanson provides an
important counterexample of the tendency of Australian courts to insulate incongruous
humor from liability. [1998] QCA 306 (28 September 1998) (Austl.). The court in Hanson
found the song parody defamatory even though it was chock full of incongruities. For
example, the song included statements that no person would ever say about themselves.
Handsley & Davis, supra note 290, at 6 (concluding that no person could be expected to say
things like “You know I’m not human” and “I have very horrendous plans”). In addition, the
song was filled with nonsensical juxtapositions and non-sequiturs. Magnusson, supra note
198, at 286 (explaining that the songs satire derives in part from “the insertion in Hanson’s
own voice, of seemingly random and incoherent non sequiturs”).
162 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93
B. IS INCONGRUITY A MEASURE OF WORTH?
Having concluded that courts can capably and meaningfully identify
incongruous content, incongruity may seem a measure of whether a
putatively funny communication is either worthy of First Amendment
protection or should be otherwise disqualified from defamation liability.
Since incongruity is suggestive of humor, incongruity establishes some of a
communication’s positive social worth. Considering incongruity as a
definitive measure of social worth, however, would overstate incongruity’s
promise.
Implicit in the idea that a communication has positive social worth is
the conclusion that the communication’s contribution to social welfare is
greater than its damage to an individual plaintiff or group. Unfortunately,
one cannot accurately make such a broad claim for humor, given its
double-edged quality on matters of hurt.
On the positive side, humor allows dialogue in uncomfortable matters
to take place more easily. Through humor-studded communications, people
can converse about matters they may not otherwise broach. Truths can
sometimes be conveyed without the barbed quality accompanying
straightforward, unadorned insults.
324
Yet the opposite effect also frequently results. Incongruous humor is
perfectly capable of conveying a negative message. Given the mental
stimulation that incongruous humor inspires,
325
one can imagine that such
humor can be a potent vehicle for inflicting injury.
326
Likewise, empirical
studies suggest humor tinged with hostility can enhance aggressive
324. See, e.g., PALMER, supra note 113, at 61 (1994) (observing that humor can
“release the pressure of inhibition” while leaving in place inhibition’s function outside of
the humor context); Podlas, supra note 83, at 512 (arguing that humor lowers “emotional
(and intellectual) defenses, thereby avoiding resistance” of listeners).
325. See Carey, supra note 62 (reporting on studies supporting connection between
mental stimulation and such things as a “pink unicorn,” a “three dollar bill,” and a “nun with
a beard.”). But cf. Laura R. Bradford, Parody and Perception: Using Cognitive Research to
Expand Fair Use in Copyright, 46 B.C. L. REV. 705, 766–67 (2005) (arguing that legal
protection should vary according to “hierarchy” of cognitive “processing,” and observing
that the unconscious impact is greater for input for which there is less processing).
326. As Dr. Samuel Johnson observed, “[a]buse is not so dangerous when there is no
vehicle of wit . . . .” J
AMES BOSWELL, THE LIFE OF SAMUEL JOHNSON 1146 (Everyman’s
Library 1992) (1791). See also Fitzgerald, supra note198, at 14
(quoting Johnson and
explaining that “ridicule provokes amusement which emphasizes the underlying message”).
2011] Defamatory Humor and Incongruity’s Promise 163
tendencies,
327
damage potential social networks,
328
and camouflage
feelings, such as Schadenfreude.
329
These competing forces counsel against extravagant claims about
incongruity’s merit. Nonetheless, incongruity plays an important role in
signaling courts that they have strong reason to believe they are considering
humor and, thus, something worthy of protecting.
V. CONCLUSION
As part of the machinery of constitutional democracy, United States
courts constantly handle clashes of important values. The constitutional
doctrine they have developed for evaluating these clashes is far from
perfect, but it is usually viable and well meaning. United States defamation
law negotiates the clash between reputation and free expression with much
the same success as other legal rules that confront a delicate balance, such
as state criminal procedure rules, economic rules, and health care
regulations. In the process of negotiating competing values, courts should
avoid ritualistic incantations of constitutional doctrine without considering
what they are trying to achieve. Courts must explicitly consider the values
sacrificed and served by choosing a particular disposition.
United States courts risk ignoring important concerns when they
become seduced by the apparent determinacy of the fact/opinion
distinction. While the distinction does a proficient job of incorporating
relevant concerns, it can obscure important values related to reputation and
humorous expression. Given the particular importance of free expression in
general and humor in particular, reputational concerns will often yield to
other values in defamatory humor cases. But why cling so dogmatically to
our sense of First Amendment exceptionalism? Americans should feel
proud of our heritage in the free speech arena, but that should not stop us
from learning from others—such as Australians—who strike a different
balance for competing values.
327. Robert A. Baron, Aggression-Inhibiting Influence of Sexual Humor, 36 J.
PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 189, 190 (1978) (discussing possible connection between
aggression and humor).
328. Martin, supra note 89, at 16 (suggesting that negative humor can damage
“potential social support”).
329. Dolf Zillman & Jennings Bryant, Misattribution Theory of Tendentious Humor,
16 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 146, 150 (1980) (suggesting that disparagement humor
can cover up hostility or Schadenfreude).
164 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 21:93