Psychological Review
1983, Vol.
90, No.
3,215-238
Copyright
1983
by the
American Psychological
Association,
Inc.
Toward
an
Ecological Theory
of
Social
Perception
Leslie
Zebrowitz
McArthur
Brandeis
University
Reuben
M.
Baron
University
of
Connecticut
The
ecological
approach
to
perception
(J.
Gibson,
1979; Shaw, Turvey,
&
Mace,
1982)
is
applied
to the
social
domain.
The
general
advantages
of
this
approach
are
enumerated,
its
applicability
to
social
perception
is
documented,
and its
spe-
cific
implications
for
research
on
emotion
perception,
impression
formation,
and
causal
attribution
are
discussed.
The
implications
of the
ecological
approach
for
our
understanding
of
errors
in
social
perception
are
also
considered. Finally,
the
major
tenets
of the
ecological
approach
are
contrasted
with
current
cognitive
approaches,
and a
plea
is
made
for
greater
attention
to the
role
of
perception
in
social knowing.
Current
research
on
social perception
op-
erates within
a
very narrow
schema—the
schema.
The
questions addressed concern
the
knowledge
structures (e.g., schemata, proto-
types,
scripts) that impose meaning
on the
blooming,
buzzing confusion around
us. The
questions ignored concern
the
structured
stimulation
that exists
in our
social environ-
ment.
As
such,
we
have learned much about
the
processing
of
information
and
little about
what that stimulus information
is. We
know,
for
example, that there
are
primacy
effects
in
impression formation:
The
person
who is
first
perceived
as
industrious
and
then
as
stubborn
will
often
be
judged more positively
than
one who is first
perceived
as
stubborn.
But,
what information (other than
a
verbal
label)
communicates industry
or
stubbor-
ness?
This
we do not
know. Similarly,
we
know
that there
are
discounting
effects
in
causal attribution: Success
on a
difficult
task
will
be
attributed
to
ability
if
little
effort
is
present,
but not if
there
is a
great deal
of
effort.
But, what information communicates
effort?
This
we do not
know.
To
fully
understand impression formation
or
causal attribution
or
other aspects
of
social
The
authors
would like
to
thank Teresa
Arnabile,
Su-
san
Fiske, David Hamilton, Bert Hodges,
Joann
Mon-
tepare,
Dick
Nisbett, David
Schneider,
and Jim
Todd
for
their very helpful
comments
on an
earlier draft
of
this
paper.
Requests
for
reprints
should
be
sent
to
Leslie
Z.
McArthur,
Department
of
Psychology, Brandeis Univer-
sity,
Waltham,
Massachusetts
02254
or to
Reuben
M.
Baron,
Department
of
Psychology, U20, University
of
Connecticut,
Storrs,
Connecticut
06268.
perception,
we
must ultimately
identify
the
nature
of the
stimulus information that
re-
veals
industry, hostility,
and the
other attri-
butes that
we
perceive
in
people. Whereas
current
cognitive approaches
fall
short
in
this
endeavor,
the
ecological approach
to
percep-
tion
provides
a
fruitful
model
for
theory
and
research.
The
purpose
of
this article
is to ad-
vocate this approach. More
specifically,
we
will
(a)
summarize
the
basic tenets
and ad-
vantages
of the
ecological position,
(b)
dem-
onstrate
the
applicability
of
this approach
to
the
realm
of
social perception,
and (c)
con-
sider
implications
of
this approach
for our
understanding
of
errors
in
social perception.
The
Ecological Position
and Its
Advantages
for
the
Study
of
Social Perception
What
we
call
the
"ecological position"
is
not a
unified
theory
of
perception; rather,
it
draws
on
several recent theories (e.g.,
J.
Gib-
son, 1966, 1979; Shaw, Turvey,
&
Mace,
1982).
This approach
has
four
distinguishing
features.
First,
it
assumes that perception
serves
an
adaptive
function
and
that
the ex-
ternal
world must therefore provide infor-
mation
to
guide biologically
and
socially
functional
behaviors. Second,
it
assumes that
this information
is
typically revealed
in ob-
jective physical
events—dynamic,
changing,
multimodal stimulus information
as
opposed
to
static
or
unimodal
displays.
Third,
it as-
sumes
that
the
information available
in
events
specifies,
among other things, environmental
affordances,
which
are the
opportunities
for
acting
or
being acted upon that
are
provided
215
216
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
by
environmental entities. Fourth,
it
assumes
that
the
perception
of
these
affordances
de-
pends
upon
the
perceivers'
attunement,
that
is,
the
particular stimulus invariants
to
which
the
perceiver attends.
The
Adaptive Nature
of
Perception
The
ecological approach
to
perception
be-
gins
by
assuming that perception serves
an
adaptive
function.
That
is, by
informing
ac-
tion,
perception
is
assumed
to
promote
in-
dividual
goal attainment
as
well
as
species
survival.
1
J.
Gibson
(1979),
for
example,
ar-
gues:
"The medium, substances, surfaces,
objects,
places,
and
other animals have
af-
fordances
for a
given animal. They
offer
ben-
efit
or
injury,
life
or
death. This
is why
they
need
to be
perceived"
(p.
143).
The
idea
that
perception
is a
matter
of
discovering
and ad-
justing
to
utilitarian properties
of the
envi-
ronment
has
important
ramifications
for
the-
ory
and
research
in
social
perception.
Most
generally,
it
focuses
attention
on
the
what
of
perceptual
processing
(i.e.,
the
useful,
struc-
tured
information
in the
environment),
whereas
traditional approaches emphasize
the how of
processing
(i.e.,
structuring mech-
anisms
in the
head;
see
Shaw
&
Bransford,
1977).
More
specifically,
the
proposition that
"perception
is for
doing"
(J.
Gibson, 1979)
focuses
our
attention
on a
particular subset
of
information within
the
perceiver's envi-
ronment,
namely
that
information which
(a)
is
revealed
in
events,
(b)
affords
adaptive
ac-
tion,
and (c) is
accessible
to the
perceptual
systems
of
the
perceiver.
Information
in
Events
The
ecological
position. Within
the
eco-
logical
approach
to
perception,
the
units
of
information
in
structured stimulation
are
events.
The
idea
of an
event
is
both simple
and
complex. Viewed descriptively,
all we
mean
by an
event
is a
dynamic
as
opposed
to a
static stimulus
display—a
motion picture
versus
a
posed photo
or a
person
walking
versus
a
person standing still.
The
dynamic
changes
over space
and
time that characterize
events
come
in
many
varieties.
For
example,
they
may be
fast
or
slow (e.g., smiling
vs.
aging),
they
may be
rigid
or
elastic (e.g.,
ro-
tating
vs.
stretching), they
may be
reversible
or
nonreversible (e.g., rolling
vs.
growing).
And,
as the
foregoing examples illustrate,
events
occur
in the
social
as
well
as the
phys-
ical
environment.
Events
provide perceivers with structured
information
that
supplements
the
informa-
tion that
is
available
in
static
stimuli.
For ex-
ample,
one can
perceive certain properties
in
a
stationary sphere, such
as its
size,
its
color,
and its
texture.
But
there
are
other attributes
that
can be
perceived only
in
events. These
include
the
heaviness
of the
sphere
that
can
be
perceived
by
observing
its
rate
of
accel-
eration down
an
incline,
by
observing some-
one
lift
it, or by
lifting
it
oneself.
This
last
example
highlights
an
important point,
namely,
that events
may be
created
by the
perceiver;
dynamic stimulus information
may
result
not
only
from
the
displacement
of en-
tities
in the
environment,
but
also
from
the
exploratory
behaviors
of an
active perceiver.
Certain properties
of an
entity will change
during
an
event, whereas others remain
the
same.
Those
elements
that
remain
the
same
are
referred
to as
structural invariants.
For
example,
the
shape
and
color
of an
object
remains
the
same
as it
rotates;
similarly, most
of
your features remain
the
same
as you
smile
or
even
as you
age.
The
styles
of
change that
events
may
manifest
are
referred
to as
trans-
formational
invariants.
For
example,
we
rec-
ognize
a
particular style
of
biomechanical
movement
as
"walking"
over
a
wide range
of
structures
(e.g., humans, cows,
and
dogs).
Similarly,
we
identify
particular morpholog-
ical
changes
as
"aging"
over
a
wide range
of
species
and
forms
(cf. Todd, Mark, Shaw,
&
Pittenger, 1980).
Advantages
for
social
perception
research.
Whereas
current research
in
social percep-
tion
has
concentrated
on the
cognitive pro-
cessing
of
social
information—how
sche-
mata, memory,
and
various cognitive heu-
ristics
influence
the
meaning
we
extract
from
the
social
environment—research
within
the
1
The
proposition
that
perception
is
adaptive repre-
sents
a
metatheoretical
or
primitive
assumption that
is
not
directly
falsifiable.
Making
this
assumption
does,
however,
lead
to
empirical
hypotheses
that
are
capable
of
disconfirmation.
See,
for
example,
the
sections
on
emotion,
error,
and
attributions
in
this article.
SOCIAL PERCEPTION
217
ecological approach will reveal
the
meaning
that
is
communicated
by
social events. More
specifically,
such research will reveal what
it
is
in a
person's movements, gestures, voice,
and
facial
appearance that communicates
to
us
that
person's
momentary intentions, emo-
tional
state,
or
more stable qualities,
and
what
it is in the
interactions between
two or
more people that communicates
to us the
nature
of
their relationship even when
we
cannot
hear
their
words (cf.
Archer
&
Akert,
1977).
We
clearly make great
use of
such
in-
formation
in our
daily
life,
for
example, when
deciding whom
to ask for
directions, whom
to ask for a
date,
or
whom
to
steer clear
of
in
the
subway. However, current research
does
not
provide
us
with
a
description
of the
stimulus information
to
which
we are re-
sponding.
A
notable exception
is
research
on
nonverbal
communication,
an
excellent
ex-
ample
of
focusing
on
information
in the
stim-
ulus. (See Schneider,
Hastorf,
&
Ellsworth,
1979,
for a
comprehensive review
of the
per-
tinent literature.) However, this research
has
tended
to
concentrate upon
the
communi-
cation
of
affect.
There
is
other psychological
information
in the
extensional properties
of
people,
and it
needs
to be
identified.
The
ecological approach
not
only focuses
on
the
neglected
and
important question
of
what
information
is
provided
by
social stim-
uli,
but it
also emphasizes
the
importance
of
addressing
this
question
by
examining
dy-
namic stimulus information, something
which
is
rarely done
in
social perception
re-
search. Perceivers more
often
make social
judgments
from
written summaries
of
social
events
than
from
direct exposure
to
those
events
as
they unfold. Thus
we
study social
cognition,
not
social perception.
The
ecolog-
ical approach makes explicit that
if we
want
to
study social perception,
we
must give
our
subjects
a
chance
to
perceive people
and
their
behavior.
Integral
to
the
emphasis
on
dynamic stim-
ulus
information within
the
ecological
ap-
proach
is an
emphasis
on the
active perceiver.
Not
only
is the
stimulus information pro-
vided
by
inert objects shown
to
become
dy-
namic when perceivers
are
permitted active
perceptual exploration (e.g.,
J.
Gibson,
1966,
p.
195),
but
also,
it is
assumed
that
the
prop-
erties
of the
external environment
will
be
more accurately detected when perceivers
are
allowed
such active exploration.
The
ecolog-
ical approach emphasizes
the
intrinsic con-
nection between
action
and
perception,
something
that
has
been given
insufficient
consideration
in
traditional theories
of
social
perception.
The
Perception
of
Affordances
The
ecological
position.
Perception
in the
ecological approach
is not
concerned with
just
any
information. Rather,
it
concerns
the
pick-up
of
useful
information.
The
useful-
ness
of
information depends upon
its
rele-
vance
to the
perceivers'
actions
and
goals,
and
for
this reason,
the
ecological approach
stresses
the
perception
of the
affordances
of
the
environment. These
are
defined
by J.
Gibson (1979)
as
"what
it
offers
the
animal,
what
it
provides
or
furnishes,
either
for
good
or
ill"
(p.
127).
A
more
poetic
and
vivid
in-
dication
of
what Gibson means
by
affordance
is
provided
by his
quotation
from
Koffka
(1935,
p. 7):
"Each
thing says what
it is
...
a
fruit
says
'eat
me';
water
says
'drink
me';
thunder says
'fear
me';
and
woman says
'love
me'
"
(J.
Gibson, 1979,
p.
138).
Gibson
maintains that
the
action possibilities pro-
vided
by an
object
in the
environment
as
well
as the
consequences
of
interacting
with
that
object
may be
revealed
in its
extensional,
physical characteristics.
For
example,
the
edibility
of
fruit
may be
specified
extension-
ally
by
color, smell, size,
and
texture.
Of
course,
any one of
these properties
may not
be
sufficient
to
reveal
a
fruit's edibility.
Rather,
the
detection
of
this
affordance
may
require
event information such
as
that pro-
vided
by
grasping
the
fruit
and
squeezing
it
or
even breaking
it
open. This
fact
highlights
the
mutuality
of the
affordances
of the en-
vironment
and the
behavior
of the
animal.
And,
although
Gibson
emphasizes
the
objec-
tive
reality
of
affordances,
he
also emphasizes
this
synergy: "Affordances
are
properties
of
things
taken with
reference
to an
observer
but
not
properties
of the
experiences
of the ob-
server.
They
are not
subjective values."
(J.
Gibson, 1979,
p.
137)
Thus,
a
fruit
affords
eating
by
some
observers
but not
others:
Monkeys
eat
bananas
and
coconuts, whereas
ants typically
do
not.
218
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
Advantages
for
social perception research.
Although
the
concept
of
affordance
is
closely
linked
to
Kurt Lewin's (1936) concept
of va-
lence,
it has not
been represented
in
social
perception research
any
more than
in
per-
ception research
in the
nonsocial
domain.
2
Rather,
research
in
social perception
has fo-
cused
on the
detection
of
structural invari-
ants—dispositional
properties such
as
abili-
ties
and
traits. Conceptualizing
our
social
perceptions
in
terms
of
affordances
may be
both
more valid
and
more useful than
the
trait approach.
There
is now
considerable evidence that
people
may not
have
traits
as
traditionally
conceived. Rather, behavior
may be
specific
to
situations
as
well
as to the
person with
whom
one is
interacting
(e.g., Mischel,
1968).
The
concept
of
affordance
deals nicely with
this possibility, because
an
affordance
is in-
herently specific
to a
particular
perceiver
what
John
affords
me may or may not be the
same
as
what John
affords
you.
In
addition
to
better capturing
the
realities
of
human
behavior,
the
concept
of
affordance
may
often
surpass
the
trait approach
in
capturing
the
perceivers' phenomenology. Although
we may
sometimes
use
trait terms
to
think about peo-
ple
(and although
our
research subjects have
almost invariably been forced
to do
so),
it is
likely
that
we
often
want
to
know what people
qan
do to or for us and
what
we can do to
them, rather than some abstract information
regarding
the
number
of
situations
in
which
they
will
behave thus
and so.
Not
only
do
affordances
often
capture
the
properties
of
other
people
and our
percep-
tions
of
them better than traits
do, but the
affordance
concept
has the
further
advantage
of
permitting
us to
assess
the
accuracy
of
perceptions more readily than
the
trait con-
cept does. Although
it is
difficult
if not im-
possible
to find a
criterion
appropriate
for
validating
perceived traits, behavioral evi-
dence
can
serve
to
validate perceived
afford-
ances.
For
example,
if
someone
is
perceived
to
afford
protection,
one can
determine
the
accuracy
of
this perception
by
ascertaining
whether
that person
will
indeed provide pro-
tection
to the
perceiver. However,
if
someone
is
perceived
as
protective, then
any
instance
of
protecting
or
nonprotecting
can
neither
confirm
nor
disconfirm
this trait ascription.
Perceptual
Attunements
The
ecological
position.
The
fact
that
af-
fordances
are
perceiver referenced highlights
a
basic tenet
of the
ecological approach,
namely, that perception requires certain
compatibilities between
the
perceiver
and the
perceived.
At the
most fundamental level,
there must
be a
match between animals'
re-
ceptor capabilities
and the
stimulus
infor-
mation
to
which they
are
perceptually sen-
sitive. Indeed,
it can be
hypothesized
that
perceptual
systems have evolved
to be
sen-
sitive
to the
types
of
structured information
available
in a
given ecological niche. Thus,
animals
who
live
in
darkened areas, such
as
caves,
have poorly developed visual systems
but
very well-developed auditory systems
that
permit navigation
and
hunting.
The
concept
of
perceptual attunement
in the
ecological
approach
is not
limited
to
attunements
that
occur
through biological preprogramming
in
response
to
evolutionary pressures. Attune-
ments
may
also derive
from
what
J.
Gibson
(1966)
has
called
the
"education
of
atten-
tion." More
specifically,
the
stimulus
infor-
mation
to
which perceivers
are
attuned
may
vary
as a
function
of
their perceptual learn-
ing,
goals, expectations,
and
actions.
The
influence
of
perceptual learning
on
attunements
is
revealed when
one
compares
the
forest
that
is
seen through
the
eyes
of a
naturalist
to the
forest seen through
the
eyes
of
a
city dweller. Whereas
the
naturalist will
differentiate—that
is,
see—many
levels
of
structure,
the
city person
may
never
see
any-
thing more than
a
uniform
and
boring mass
of
green.
On a
less anecdotal level,
the
master
chess player sees more moves
on an
appro-
priately arranged
chessboard
than
the
novice
sees.
Evidence that
the
expert actually sees
the
board
differently
is
provided
by
Neisser's
(1976)
report
that
experts show more
board-
dependent
eye fixations
than novices
do.
Cross-cultural
differences
in
susceptibility
to
perceptual illusions
also
provide evidence
for
2
According
to J.
Gibson (1979,
p.
138),
Kurt Lewin's
concept
of
valence
is an
English translation
of the
term
Aufforderungscharakter,
which
has
also been translated
as
invitation character,
a
translation that probably makes
the
concept
clearer
as
well
as
more
readily identifiable
as
analogous
to the
concept
of
affordance.
SOCIAL PERCEPTION
219
the
role
of
perceptual learning (e.g., Segall,
Campbell,
&
Herskovitz, 1966).
The
influence
of
goals upon perceptual
attunements
is not a
domain
of
exclusive
in-
terest
to the
ecological approach. Indeed, this
topic
has
been extensively explored
in a
body
of
research known
as the
"new
look",
which
sought
to
demonstrate that
the
perception
of
stimuli
may be
inhibited
or
enhanced
as a
function
of the
needs
or
goals
of the
perceiver
(e.g.,
Postman, Bruner,
&
McGinnies,
1948).
Although
this research
was
earlier subject
to
considerable criticism (e.g., Goldiamond,
1958),
it has
recently been revitalized
in Er-
delyi's
(1974)
reformulation,
and its
primary
emphasis
is
quite compatible with
the
eco-
logical
view
that perceivers
are
attuned
to the
stimulus information
that
is
most relevant
to
adaptive
actions.
Like
motivational
influences
upon percep-
tion,
the
postulated
influence
of
expectations
is
not
limited
to the
ecological approach.
However,
one can
differentiate
between
two
expectancy
effects,
only
one of
which reflects
perceptual
attunement.
In the
effect
that
op-
erates
at a
perceptual level, perceivers with
one
expectation
may
partition
a
complex
stimulus
differently
from
those with another
expectation.
In
Asch's
(1952)
terms, these
expectancy
effects
reflect
variations
in the
object
of
judgment—the
effective
stimulus
information
is
different
for
different
sets.
Another
kind
of
expectancy
effect
operates
at a
more inferential level: Perceivers with
one
expectation interpret
the
same stimulus
information
differently
from
those with
an-
other
expectation.
In
Asch's (1952) terms,
such
expectancy
effects
reflect
variations
in
the
judgment
of the
object.
The
role
of
action
in
perceptual attune-
ments
is
obvious
but
often
overlooked
in
tra-
ditional
approaches that treat
the
perceiver
as a
passive receptacle
for
sensory stimula-
tion.
Actions constrain what
is
perceived.
Where
one is
walking, what
one is
touching,
where
one
looks, listens,
and
sniff's
will
all
influence
the
particular subset
of
information
that
is
available
to
guide subsequent actions.
Advantages
for
social perception research.
The
assumption that perception
is
selective
and
that what
is
perceived
will
vary
from
perceiver
to
perceiver
is not
unique
to the
ecological
approach. What
is
unique
is the
basis upon which selectivity
and
individual
differences
are
postulated
and, therefore,
the
factors
presumed
to
influence them.
According
to the
ecological position,
we
are
sensitive
to
adaptively relevant informa-
tion,
as
opposed
to all
possible information.
Although
this
may
seem
a
self-evident truth,
it
is
something that
has not
been central
to
research
and
theory
in
social perception,
and
in
underscoring this point,
the
ecological
ap-
proach highlights
new
areas
for
research.
In
particular,
the
assumption
that
what
we
per-
ceive
in the
social environment
is
likely
to
be
first and
foremost that which
is
most
es-
sential
to
adaptive action suggests
a
hierarchy
in
the
ease with which various social prop-
erties
are
perceived.
For
example, emotions
such
as
anger
and
fear
should
be
most
readily
perceived because they
are
most essential
to
adaptive action
on the
part
of the
perceiver.
3
Similarly,
the
stable
attributes
of
domineer-
ingness,
aggressiveness,
and
strength should
be
perceived more readily than kindness,
in-
telligence,
or
reliability
because
the
former
are
more essential
to
adaptive action.
The
ecological approach
not
only draws
our
attention
to the
fact
that
some
social
properties should
be
more readily detected
than others
by all
perceivers
but
also
it
sheds
new
light
on the
issue
of
individual
differ-
ences.
Different
information
is
essential
to
the
behavioral goals
of
different
people. What
low-status
people need
to
perceive
in
order
to
interact
effectively
with their environment
may
often
be
different
from
what high-status
people need
to
perceive; what people
in one
culture
need
to
perceive
may be
different
from
what those
in
another culture need
to
perceive; what people
in one
occupation need
to
perceive
may
differ
from what people
in
another occupation need
to
perceive;
and so
forth.
4
Thus,
the
ecological approach suggests
3
Some evidence consistent with this argument
is
pro-
vided
by
Averill's (1983)
finding
that
there
are
many
more
words
in the
English
language
referring
to
negative
emotions than
to
positive
ones.
4
The
truth
of
this
assertion
has
been
vividly illustrated
to the first
author recently
as a
consequence
of a new
hobby—oil
painting.
The
necessity
to
create
on
canvas
what
is
seen
in the
external world
has fine
tuned
her
perceptual capacities
in
ways never imagined
possible
shadows,
for
example,
that
formerly went
unnoticed,
have
now
become
palpable
entities
with color,
texture,
and
form.
220
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
that
we may
discover much
of
interest
in the
domain
of
individual differences
in
social
perception
if we
begin
our
investigations with
a
careful
analysis
of
what
it is
that various
individuals
most need
to
perceive
in
order
to
interact
effectively
with their social envi-
ronment.
The
concept
of
perceptual attunement
is
pertinent
to
research
on the
development
of
social perceptions
as
well
as
individual dif-
ferences.
According
to J.
Gibson
(1966),
per-
ceptual development involves
the
"education
of
attention."
More specifically, Eleanor Gib-
son's
(1969)
perceptual
differentiation
theory
holds that
as
perception
develops,
the
organ-
ism
extracts
from
the
total stimulus
flux
cer-
tain
distinctive features
and
invariant rela-
tionships
not
previously detected. Because
developing
an
attunement
to
these
new
prop-
erties
of
stimulation will result
from
an
active
search
directed
by the
task
at
hand,
one
would expect
perceptual
attunements
to de-
velop
in
synchrony with
the
development
of
behavioral
capabilities.
As
such,
we may
learn
much about
the
development
of
social
perceptions
(i.e.,
the
social
invariants
to
which
perceivers
at a
given developmental
level
are
attuned)
if we
begin
with
an
analysis
of
the
behavioral goals that
the
social per-
ceptions
can
serve.
The
concept
of
perceptual
attunement
has a
further
implication
for
studying
the
development
of
social percep-
tions. Intrinsic
to the
concept
of
perceptual
attunement
is the
assumption that perceivers
can
extract
certain
information
from
the
stimulus
environment
before
the
develop-
ment
of
conceptual
structures
and
language.
Because
testing this assumption requires
re-
search
investigating
the
perceptions
of
young
children,
developmental research becomes
an
essential component
of
research
on
social
perception within
the
ecological approach
rather than
a
separate enterprise.
Applicability
of the
Ecological Approach
to
Social Perception
We
have shown
that
an
ecological
theory
of
perception
offers
several advantages over
current approaches
to
social
perception.
The
question
to be
considered
in
this section
is
"Can such
a
theory
be
applied
to the
realm
of
social perception?"
Adaptive
Function
of
Social
Perception
One of the
basic tenets
of the
ecological
approach
is
that perception serves
an
adap-
tive
function
for the
organism inasmuch
as
it
informs
(and
is
informed
by)
action.
The
fact
that
it is
biologically important
to
detect
properties
of
the
physical environment such
as
chasms
or
obstacles
or fires
bolsters
the
argument
that
we are
attuned
to the
stimulus
information
that reveals these properties
and
need
not
rely
upon
the
slower
and
less sure
processes
of
inference (cf. Nisbett
&
Ross,
1980).
Can we
provide
the
same kind
of un-
derpinnings
for an
ecological theory
of
social
perception?
The
adaptive value
of
attune-
ment
to
stimulus information
specifying
so-
cial events
has
been acknowledged
by J.
Gib-
son
(1979),
who
argued, "For
any
animal
needs
to
distinguish
not
only
the
substances
and
objects.
...
It
cannot
afford
to
confuse
prey with predator, own-species with another
species,
or
male with female"
(p. 7).
Certainly
it is as
adaptive
to
differentiate
male
from
female
and
prey
from
predator
in the
social
environment
as it is to
detect properties
of
the
physical environment. Similarly,
the
help-
lessness
of
babies,
the
looks
of
fear
or
anger,
and the
ravages
of
disease
require
fast
and
sure
recognition
if our
species
is to
survive.
It
should
be
noted,
however,
that
the
adaptive
value
of
accurate social perception
is not
lim-
ited
to its
utility
for
species survival. Accurate
social perception also serves
an
adaptive
function
at the
level
of
individual goal
at-
tainment—for
example, getting
from
others
that
which
we
desire
and
escaping that which
we
dislike.
Stimulus
Information
in
Social Events
Although
one can
make
a
convincing
ar-
gument
that attunement
to
stimulus
infor-
mation
specifying
social events
has
adaptive
value,
applying
the
ecological approach
to
social perception requires more than dem-
onstrating
a
Darwinian
aesthetic
appeal.
One
must also argue
that
social perception rests
upon
the
same
types
of
information
as
per-
ceptions
of the
physical environment.
The
first
question
is
"Are social
properties
re-
vealed
in
events?"
J.
Gibson's arguments
on
behalf
of
event perception
are
actually more
telling
in the
realm
of
social perception
than
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
221
in
the
realm
of
object perception. Perceiving
the
properties
of
people, even more than
those
of
inanimate objects,
will
often
require
a
dynamic stimulus display both because
hu-
mans
are
animate
and
because many
of
their
properties
can be
detected only
in
their
ac-
tions.
One can
thus argue simply
on
logical
grounds
that social properties must
often
be
revealed
in
dynamic stimulus displays.
A
sec-
ond
question that must
be
considered
in ap-
plying
the
ecological
approach
to the
social
realm
is "Do the
stimulus properties detected
in
the
realm
of
social perception include
structural
invariants, transformational
in-
variants
and
affordances,
just
as in the
phys-
ical
realm?"
Structural
invariants. Just
as the
physical
appearance
of a
windmill reveals
to
perceiv-
ers
structural invariants (e.g.,
a
vertical
shaft
and
sails),
so
does
the
physical appearance
of
people
reveal certain
structural
invariants
(e.g.,
a
backbone
and
limbs). However, people
are
also perceived
to
have invariant proper-
ties whose physical extension
is not so
readily
apparent. Consider,
for
example, Heider's
(1958)
concept
of
dispositional
properties,
which
he
defines
as
"the invariances that
make
possible
a
more
or
less stable, predict-
able,
and
controllable world." According
to
Heider,
these relatively unchanging struc-
tures
include
"such
object properties
as
color
and
size,
and
such person properties
as
char-
acter
and
ability"
(p.
80).
Can we
directly
perceive
human structural invariants such
as
character
and
ability? Although Heider sug-
gests that
we can
when
he
says, "Certainly
a
person's apparent self-confidence
often
influ-
ences
our
judgments
of his
abilities"
(p.
94),
his
writings stressed
the
role
of
inference
in
social
perception:
Thus,
it is
very
unlikely
that
we
will
be
able
to
coordinate
univocally
certain characteristics
of the
stimulus mani-
folds
to
impressions
of
personality traits, social
acts,
or
sentiments
in a
simple
way.
In
order
to
understand
the
connection between
the
stimulus
pattern
and the
impres-
sion,
we
have
to
resort
to
thought models which
are
more
complicated,
(p. 24)
Following
Heider's lead, most research
in
social perception
has
assumed that social
in-
variants must
be
inferred,
as
opposed
to
being
specified
in the
stimulus. However,
ev-
idence
that structural invariants such
as
abil-
ity
or
personality
are
indeed specified
in the
stimulus
has
been provided
in
research
ex-
amining
stimulus information presumed
to
be
important
on the
basis
of
ethological
the-
ories.
For
example,
Guthrie
(1970)
has
pro-
posed several morphological characteristics
that
may
signal dominance
by
virtue
of
their
roots
in our
phylogenetic past. And, consis-
tent with
his
postulates, recent research
by
Keating,
Mazur,
and
Segall
(1981)
has re-
vealed
that persons with
the
broader
of two
faces
or the
more
receding
of two
hairlines
are
perceived
as the
more dominant
by
peo-
ple
from
a
variety
of
cultures. Similarly,
drawing
on
Lorenz's (1970) postulates
re-
garding
infantile stimulus features,
Mc-
Arthur
and her
colleagues
(McArthur
&
Apatow,
Note
1;
Berry
&
McArthur, Note
2)
have
found
that adult males with relatively
"babyish"
facial
features, such
as
large eyes,
short noses
and
ears,
or low
vertical place-
ment
of all
features,
are
perceived
as
less
strong
and
domineering than those with more
"mature"
features—smaller
eyes, longer noses
and
ears,
or
higher placement
of all
features.
To
discover
the
stimuli that reveal human
structural invariants
may
require
not
only
examining
stimulus information that
is
well
grounded
ethologically
but
also scaling
up to
a
higher level
of
stimulus complexity.
For
example,
it may be
possible
to
detect person-
ality
dispositions such
as
shyness
or
nurtur-
ance when individuals
are
observed
in
dyads
or
in
groups
but not
when they
are
observed
in
isolation. Similarly,
it may be
possible
to
detect certain traits when people
are
observed
in
action
but not
when they
are
observed
in
more static displays. Consider,
for
example,
KofTka's
(1935) presumption
of a
mapping
of
inner qualities into overt actions: "The
slow
dragging movements
of the
depressed,
the
jerky, discontinuous movements
of the
irritable, correspond, indeed,
to the
leaden
state
of
depression
or the
disrupted state
of
irritability"
(p.
658). More substantial evi-
dence
that
a
person's
gait
can
reveal
struc-
tural invariants
is
provided
by the
work
of
Cutting
and his
colleagues.
By filming
people
in
darkness with point lights
on
their major
joints, Kozlowski
and
Cutting
(1977)
dem-
onstrated
that
a
walker's
sex can be
recog-
nized
from
the
moving point lights without
familiarity
cues. Subsequent research
re-
vealed
that
the
perception
of a
biomechanical
222
LESLIE
Z.
MCARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
invariant
in a
person's
gait—the
center
of
moment—is
sufficient
for the
identification
of
a
walker's
sex
(Cutting, 1978; Cutting,
Profitt,
&
Kozlowsky,
1978).
The
foregoing
examples
suggest that
as we
begin
to
consider
the
stimulus information
in
events,
we may
find
that there
is
indeed stimulus information
sufficient
for the
perception
of
many human
structural
invariants.
The
question remains
as to
what structural
invariants
are
specified
by the
stimulus
in-
formation
in
social events. Although
the an-
swer
to
this
question
must
be
established
em-
pirically,
some boundary conditions
can be
derived
from
the
theory
of
ecological percep-
tion,
which suggests
that
there will
be
stim-
ulus
information
sufficient
for the
perception
of
structural invariants whose perception
has
important adaptive value
either
to the
per-
ceiver
or the
perceived. Drawing
on J.
Gib-
son's
(1979)
proposition that animals cannot
afford
to
confuse prey
with
predator,
own
species with another,
or
male with
female,
one
would expect social stimulus informa-
tion
to
specify benevolence versus malevo-
lence,
in-group
versus out-group,
and
gender
and
sexual receptivity. Similarly,
the
adaptive
value
of
detecting structural invariants such
as
physical strength
and
illness, mental
as-
tuteness
and
insanity,
and
social dominance
and
dependency argues
for
their specification
in
the
stimulus information that people pro-
ject.
In
contrast, there
are
other physical,
mental,
and
social qualities whose detection
has
less general adaptive importance (e.g.,
fine
motor coordination, mathematical rea-
soning ability, sense
of
humor),
and
these
structural invariants should
be
less clearly
specified
in
social stimulus information,
re-
quiring
more inferential processes
for
their
identification.
Of
course,
it
should
be
reit-
erated that, according
to the
ecological
ap-
proach,
the
detection
of any
structural
in-
variant
is
more likely when event informa-
tion
is
provided
and
when
its
detection
is
relevant
for the
perceivers' actions.
Transformational
invariants.
In
addition
to
manifesting various
structural
invariants,
a
windmill reveals
in its
motions
the
trans-
formational
invariant rotating. Similarly,
transformational
invariants
such
as
walking
or
running
are
given
in the
physical move-
ment
of
people.
For
example, Johansson
(1973)
has filmed
motion patterns
by
means
of
a
moving-dot technique
in
which
10
small
luminous points were attached
to the
main
limb joints
of an
actor
who was
then
filmed
in
near darkness while walking
or
running.
Although
the film
depicted nothing
but a
group
of 10
bright dots, each moving
in its
own
path, perceivers were able
to
detect
a
walking
or a
running
man
when viewing
the
film
for
as
little
as 200
msec. What
these
data
tell
us is
that perceivers
are
attuned
to
very
abstract information concerning
the
invari-
ances
in
their
environment.
The
abstract
character
of
this information coupled with
the
speed with which
it is
translated into
a
percept
indicates
that
kinematic
stimulus
in-
formation
is
sufficient
for the
perception
of
human
locomotion.
5
Recent research
by
Runeson
and
Frykholm
(1981)
indicates
that
such information
is
also
sufficient
for the
perception
of
human
effort,
inasmuch
as the
relative heaviness
of
lifted weights
was
per-
ceivable
from
moving point-light displays.
It
thus appears that trying
is
revealed
in the
speed,
direction,
and/or
smoothness
of mo-
tions.
The
transformational invariants
that
char-
acterize walking, running,
and
trying
in the
foregoing
research involved changes
in the
layout
(i.e.,
the
position)
of an
individual.
Changes
in the
layout
of two or
more people
may
also
be
directly specified
by the
moving
stimulus
display that they project. Thus,
again
using
the
moving-dot technique,
Jo-
hansson
(1973)
found that perceivers
are
able
to
detect dancing when
viewing
a film
that
depicts nothing
but a
group
of 20
bright
dots
that
are
affixed
to the
joints
of two
dancing
people. Similarly,
the
classic, animated
film
produced
by
Heider
and
Simmel
(1944)
re-
veals
that perceivers detect chasing
and fight-
ing
in
kinematic stimulus information.
It is
conceivable that there
are
transformational
invariants
specific
to
other social events such
as
lovemaking,
dominating,
submitting,
5
It is
recognized
that
the
point-light
research
involves
an
impoverished stimulus display
on all
dimensions
of
a
stimulus array except parameters
of
movement.
This
is
by
intention, because this research
is
designed
to
dem-
onstrate
that
kinematic stimulus information
is, in and
of
itself,
sufficient
for the
perception
of
various mean-
ingful
human behaviors.
SOCIAL PERCEPTION
223
mothering,
and so
forth.
If so,
then
sufficient
information
for the
detection
of
these events
may
be
provided
by the
motion vectors that
people project. Some evidence that complex
social
relationships
are
specified
in the mo-
tions
of two
interacting people
is
provided
by
Archer
and
Akert
(1977),
who
exposed some
perceivers
to
short
videotaped
clips
of a
nat-
ural
social interaction
and
other perceivers
merely
to a
written
transcript
of the
inter-
action.
The
results
of
this research were very
striking: Only those
who
were
able
to see the
interaction were able
to
accurately detect
a
variety
of
social
relationships,
including kin-
ship, friendship,
and
status
differentials.
Archer
and
Akert's
data
suggest that there
are
transformational invariants
specific
to
social events such
as
parenting, winning,
def-
erence,
and
friendship.
The
task remains
to
locate
and to
systematically describe
the na-
ture
of the
stimulus information that reveals
these invariants.
In
some cases,
sufficient
stimulus
information
may be
provided
by
changes
in
people's gross motor activity,
as
is
true
for
walking, running,
and
dancing.
In
other cases,
sufficient
stimulus information
may
be
provided
by finer
motor
activities.
Emotional expressions,
for
example, involve
characteristic
changes
in the
facial stimulus
array
as
well
as in
other nonverbal behaviors,
and the
sufficiency
of
such information
for
the
detection
of
emotions
has
been demon-
strated
in a
large number
of
studies (e.g.,
Rosenthal, Hall, DiMatteo, Rogers,
&
Archer,
1979).
Not
only
do
characteristic
facial
expressions, gestures,
and
vocal qualities pro-
vide information
sufficient
for the
detection
of
emotion, but, moreover, some recent
re-
search
by
Bassili
(1978)
using
a
modified
point-light
technique suggests that
the
emo-
tion
may be
revealed
in the
nonverbal changes
per se.
Because separate features,
facial
lines,
and so
forth
are not
visible with this proce-
dure,
it
allows
one to
determine whether
fa-
cial movement, apart
from
the
appearance
of
particular
features,
communicates
emotion.
The
results reveal that emotions
can
indeed
be
specified
by
facial
motor
activity occurring
over
time.
Changes
slower
than
those
transformations
that reveal emotional state
are
associated
with changes
in
age. Wrinkling,
drooping
skin,
and
changes
in
craniofacial shape
are
invariant transformations
of the
human
face
and
head with increasing age. Considerable
research supports
the
hypothesis that percep-
tions
of a
person's
age are
strongly tied
to
these
transformational invariants.
For ex-
ample, Shaw
and his
associates (Shaw
&
Pit-
tenger,
1977; Todd
et
al.,
1980) have inves-
tigated
perceivers'
sensitivity
to
differences
in
the
shape
of
facial
profiles
that
are
associated
with growth. Subjects' judgments
of the age
of
various
facial
profiles
supported
the hy-
pothesis
that
increasing levels
of a
cardiodal
strain
transformation (which simulates
ac-
tual growth) performed
on a
standard
profile
would
produce increases
in the
perceived
age
of
the
profile.
Furthermore, subjects' sensi-
tivity
to the
profile
differences
was
very acute:
(a)
They could
detect
and
associate with
age
shape
differences
produced
by the
strain
transformation
that were only
a few
times
greater
than
the
absolute limit determined
for
visual
acuity
in
resolving spatially adjacent
lines,
and (b)
these discriminations were
made
very
quickly. These
findings all
suggest
that changes
in
craniofacial morphology
are
sufficient
for the
identification
of
changes
in
a
person's
age.
Affordances.
It has
been argued that
the
structural
and
transformational invariants
that characterize social events
may be
spec-
ified
in the
physical
extensions
of
those
events
just
as
they
are for
nonsocial events. What
about
human
affordances?
It is
reasonable
to
argue
that people have physical properties
that
modulate
light
and
sound waves
in a
manner
that reveals their
affordances
just
as
the
structure
of a
windmill
may
reveal
its
climbability?
Although acknowledging that
human
affordances
are in
certain respects
unique,
J.
Gibson (1979) would answer
in the
affirmative.
The
perceiving
of
these mutual affordances
...
is
just
as
much
based
on
stimulus
information
as is the
simpler
perception
of the
support that
is
offered
by the
ground
under
one's
feel
. . .
other persons
can
only
give
off
information
about themselves
insofar
as
they
are
tan-
gible,
audible, odorous,
testable,
or
visible,
(p.
135)
Although
there
has
been little research
concerning
the
perception
of
affordances,
some
evidence
that
they
are in
fact revealed
in
social stimuli
is
provided
by
recent studies
examining
perceptions
of
people
who
vary
in
the
babyishness
of
their appearances.
Alley
224
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
(1981)
found
that
perceivers report
a
greater
desire
to
protect
from
attack
and to
cuddle
stimulus persons whose head shape
or
bodily
proportions
are
babyish than those
who
have
a
more mature appearance.
Alley
also found
a
greater desire
to
protect,
but not to
cuddle,
persons with
an
elderly craniofacial appear-
ance than
persons
who
were young
adults.
Related
findings
have been obtained
by
McArthur
and
Apatow (Note
1),
who
found
that
faces
varying
in the
babyishness
of
their
features
are
perceived
as
affording
different
social
interactions.
For
example, persons
with
more
babyish faces were
perceived
as
less
likely
to
turn
a
cold shoulder
to the
sub-
jects'
attempts
at
friendly
conversation,
less
able
to
move several boxes
of the
subjects'
heaviest books,
and
more likely
to be the
kind
of
roommate
who
would comply with
all of
the
subjects' wishes about furniture arrange-
ment, quiet hours,
and so
forth.
Attunements
in
Social
Perception
Although
we
have discussed
the
perception
of
social
affordances
in a
manner that does
not
distinguish among perceivers,
it is im-
portant
to
recall that
in the
ecological
ap-
proach
to
perception
"affordances
are
prop-
erties
of
things taken with
reference
to an ob-
server"
(J.
Gibson,
1979,
p'.
137). Thus,
the
affordances
detected
by
some perceivers
may
not be
detected
by
others.
For
example, per-
ceivers
of any
strength
may
perceive
the
structural invariant high physical power
in a
stimulus
person with
mature
facial
features.
But,
whether
that
stimulus person
is
per-
ceived
as
affording
defeat
in a
wrestling
match will depend upon
the
perceivers'
own
physical
powers. Similarly, perceivers
of any
status
may
perceive
the
structural invariant
low
social power
in a
stimulus person with
babyish
facial
features. However, whether
the
babyfaced
person
is
perceived
as
affording
compliance with
the
perceiver's
own
wishes
will
undoubtedly depend upon
the
perceiver's
own
social
powers.
6
It may
also depend upon
the
perceiver's social goals:
The
person
who
has
no
desire
to
elicit compliance
may not
perceive that
particular
affordance.
Although
the
correspondence between perceived
af-
fordances
and
one's
own
capabilities
and
goals
has not
been extensively studied,
one
intriguing
finding is the
report
that
prison
inmates convicted
of
assaultive crimes
are
highly
attuned
to
stimulus information
in a
person's gait that reveals
the
person's
"mug-
gability"—that
is, the
affordance
of
assault
(Grayson
&
Stein,
1981).
Although
we
have been illustrating
the in-
fluence
of a
perceiver's
own
action
potential
upon
the
detection
of
affordances,
it
should
be
noted
that
the
detection
of
structural
or
transformational
invariants
can
also
vary
across perceivers. Most notably, perceivers
may
be
blind
to
those structural
or
transfor-
mational
invariants
that
have
no
behavioral
utility
(i.e., that
do not
have
any
related
af-
fordance).
We are all
familiar with
the ex-
ample
of
Eskimos
who
differentiate
several
varieties
of
snow.
In the
traditional Eskimo
life-style,
each snow structure undoubtedly
affords
different
activities.
For the
urban
dweller,
snow
of any
sort
affords
shoveling
and
slipping,
and the
different
structures
are
therefore
not
perceived. Blindness
to
percep-
tual information
specifying
structural
in-
variants
that have
low
behavioral utility
may
also
be
found
in the
social realm.
For ex-
ample, Gilson, Brown,
and
Daves (1982)
re-
cently
demonstrated that perceptions
are
sig-
nificantly
related
to
sexual preference. Using
a
binocular rivalry paradigm, these authors
found
that
gay men
tended
to
report
images
of
men
whereas straight
men
reported images
of
women.
The
perceiver's expectations,
as
well
as
behavioral
potential,
may
influence percep-
tual
attunements.
For
example, binocular
ri-
valry
research
has
demonstrated
that
people
more readily perceive photographic slides
whose
content
is
expected
by
virtue
of
being
drawn
from
their
own
culture than slides
drawn
from
an
unfamiliar culture (Bagby,
1957).
Similarly, people more readily per-
ceive
violent photographic slides
when
such
scenes
have become expected
by
virtue
of
police
training than when
no
such training
has
occurred (Toch
&
Schulte,
1961),
and
they
more readily perceive
a
familiar
upright
face
than
an
inverted face
(Engel,
1956;
Has-
6
This contrast
is
akin
to
Heider's
(1958)
distinction
between
power,
which
is a
dispositional property
of the
person,
and
can, which
is a
relationship
between
the
per-
son
and the
environment.
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
225
torf
&
Myro,
1959).
It is
important
to
note
that
the
impact
of a
perceiver's expectations
or
behavioral potential upon perceptions
does
not
negate
the
impact
of
information
in
the
stimulus. Indeed,
it has
been argued
that such factors exert their
influence
by at-
tuning
the
perceiver
to
particular aspects
of
the
available stimulus information.
Representative Applications
of An
Ecological
Theory
of
Social Perception
Having
argued
for the
advantages
and ap-
plicability
of an
ecological approach
to
social
perception,
it
seems important
to
consider
what
kind
of
research that approach would
entail
and how it
would
differ
from
current
approaches. Three research areas
will
be
con-
sidered
for
this
purpose:
emotion
perception,
impression
formation,
and
causal attribu-
tion.
Emotion
Perception
The
domain
of
person perception that
is
probably most amenable
to an
ecological
analysis
is the
perception
of
emotions
in
oth-
ers.
The
strong cross-cultural consensus
in
emotional expression along with
the
pancul-
tural
accuracy
in
emotional recognition (Ek-
man,
1971)
supports
an
ecological interpre-
tation
at two
levels:
(a) It
suggests
a
promi-
nent
role
for
stimulus-based information
in
the
perception
of
emotions;
and (b) it
sup-
ports
the
suppositions
of
Darwin
(1872)
and
others (cf. Andrews,
1965;Sackett,
1966)
that
emotions have
a
species-wide adaptive sig-
nificance.
Stimulus
information.
Unlike
other
areas
of
person perception,
the
existing research
on
emotion perception
has
given strong empha-
sis
to the
identification
of the
stimulus
in-
formation
that
is
utilized
in the
detection
of
other's emotional states.
A
wide range
of
motor information
has
been identified,
in-
cluding facial
expressions,
gait,
and
posture,
as
well
as
multiple paralinguistic cues (see
Schneider
et
al.,
1979). What
the
ecological
approach adds
to
this research
are
some
novel
postulates regarding
the
nature
of the
stimulus information that
is
likely
to be im-
portant
in the
communication
of
emotion.
Much
of the
existing research
on the
rec-
ognition
of
emotion
in
facial
expressions
has
employed
posed,
static
modes
of
stimulus
presentation,
and the
results
of
such research
may
not
provide
us
with
an
accurate picture
of
the
stimulus information that
is
employed
in the
detection
of
emotion
in
more natu-
ralistic
situations.
For one
thing, static pho-
tographs tend
to
provide supranormal dis-
plays
of
emotions, which
are not
available
in
more spontaneous expressions. Thus,
to the
extent
that perceivers
are
accurate
in
iden-
tifying
the
emotions modeled
in
posed, static
facial
expressions, their accuracy
may
derive
from
stimulus information
very
different
from
that utilized
in
more naturalistic
en-
counters. Moreover,
any
inaccuracies
may
derive
from
deficiencies
in the
stimulus
in-
formation:
Although
a
static display
may be
adequate
for
accurate
recognition
of
some
emotions, other emotions
may
require tem-
porally
extended stimulus information
for
accurate recognition.
The
importance
of
temporal organization
to
emotion recogni-
tion
has
recently been demonstrated
by
Bas-
sili
(1979),
who
found
that
the
mouth, eyes,
and
eyebrows move together
in
characteris-
tically
different
ways
for
different
emotions.
These data support
J.
Gibson's
(1979)
general
proposition
that
perception
rests
on the
abil-
ity
to
pick
up
formless invariants over time.
From this perspective,
differences
between
emotions
can be
modeled
in
terms
of
differ-
ences
in how the
elastic
surface
of the
face
is
topologically deformed over time.
The
hypothesis that emotions
are
revealed
in
dynamic facial
expressions
poses
the
fol-
lowing
question
for
future
research:
"What
is the
nature
of
facial
change
in
moving
from
neutrality
to joy as
opposed
to
anger
or
some
other emotion?"
The
ecological approach
not
only
raises this question,
but it
also suggests
a
particular sort
of
answer, namely, that
the
information
for
emotion perception
is not
only
dynamic
but
also holistic.
To the
extent
that
we
respond
to
higher order relationships
that hold over
particular
parts,
such
as the
position
of the
eyes, mouth, eyebrows,
and
so
forth,
the
detection
of
emotion will
not
follow
a
feature-by-feature analysis. Rather,
perceivers respond
to
changes
in the
whole
facial
configuration. This suggests that emo-
tional expressions
may be
described
by
trans-
formations
that
preserve only higher order,
226
LESLIE
Z.
MCARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
nonmetric relationships between
the
facial
features,
just
as
physical maturation
of the
craniofacial
profile
has
been described
by the
topological strain transformation (Shaw
&
Pittenger, 1977). What
remains
for
future
re-
search
is to
specify
the
nature
of the
trans-
formations
that reveal each
of the
emotions.
Basilli's
use of the
point-light technique pro-
vides
a
possible entry into this problem,
as
does Buck, Baron,
and
Barrette's
(1982)
use
of
unitization breakpoint data
as a
clue
to
where significant stimulus changes
occur
in
expressive
behavior.
Species-wide
attunements.
Cross-cultural
accuracy
in
emotion recognition suggests
that emotional expressions
may
have evolved
to
provide information
that
is of
adaptive
significance
to the
entire species. Such
infor-
mation would include
the
signaling
of
envi-
ronmental danger
as
well
as the
regulation
of
social interactions. Consistent with this evo-
lutionary perspective, there
is
evidence
of a
close coordination between
the
social inter-
action opportunities available
in a
given eco-
logical
niche
and the
expressive potential
of
inhabitants
of
that niche.
For
example,
An-
drews
(1965) observed that animals whose
niche
required
a
high level
of
social coordi-
nation, such
as the
plain-dwelling
baboon
as
opposed
to the
forest-dwelling mandrill
ba-
boon, have
a
more mobile
facial
musculature
for
expressing emotion.
A
stress
on the
adaptive
significance
of
emotional
expressions
shifts
the
emphasis
in
the
study
of
emotion perception
from
emo-
tion
as
phenomenal experience
to
emotion
as
a
guide
to
action.
Specifically,
emotions
may
be
viewed
as
social
affordances
in the
sense
that
they call forth various interper-
sonal behaviors.
For
example, anger
is
likely
to
provoke avoidance, whereas
joy is
likely
to
encourage approach. Relevant research
in-
cludes
the
work
of Orr and
Lanzetta
(1980)
and
Lanzetta
and Orr
(1981),
who
have dem-
onstrated that
a
fearful
face
facilitates learn-
ing
the
association
between
a
neutral
cue and
electric shock, whereas
a
happy
face
inhibits
this
association. Similarly, Ohman
and
Dim-
berg
(1978) found
that
a
correlation between
an
angry
face
and
electric shock
was
learned
more readily
than
a
correlation
between
a
happy
face
and
shock.
It
thus appears that
a
fearful
or
angry
face
signals that
the
envi-
ronment
affords
danger,
and
such
faces
fa-
cilitate appropriate adaptive actions,
a find-
ing
that supports
the
basic ecological prop-
osition that "perception
is for
doing"
(J.
Gibson,
1979). Further research designed
to
ascertain what other environmental
afford-
ances
may be
detected
in
various emotional
expressions,
thereby informing adaptive
ac-
tion, should prove informative.
Individual
attunements.
In
addition
to
stressing
the
role
of
emotional expressions
to
reveal affordances whose detection
has
adap-
tive
significance
for all
humans,
the
ecolog-
ical
approach
to
emotion perception empha-
sizes
the
influence
of
individual perceivers'
action capabilities
and
their social experi-
ences
on
their attunement
to the
information
in
emotional expressions. Consistent
with
this
emphasis,
the finding
that
females
are
more attuned than males
are to
expressive
information
(see Rosenthal
et
al.,
1979)
has
been interpreted
as
reflecting
the
greater
im-
portance
of
such information
for
adaptive
actions
by
those
who are
relatively powerless
(Henley,
1977).
Some evidence that black
perceivers
are
more attuned
to
expressive
in-
formation
than white perceivers also sup-
ports this interpretation (Gitter, Black,
&
Mostofsky,
1972).
The
impact
of
experience
on
attunement
to
expressive information
is
suggested
by (a)
Feldman
and
Donohue's
(1978)
finding
that black observers
are
better
than white observers
at
detecting
the
expres-
sive
meaning
of the
facial
and
bodily cues
of
black
actors,
and (b)
Rosenthal
et
al.'s
(1979)
finding
that people whose professions require
effective
interpersonal interactions
are
more
accurate
in
reading emotional expressions
than
those
whose professions
are
less
social.
The
role
of
individual attunements
in
emotion perception clearly warrants further
research.
One
important question concerns
the
determinants
of
such attunements,
two
of
which have already been discussed:
(a) the
relevance
of the
expressive information
for
a
particular
perceiver's behavior,
and (b) the
perceiver's past experience with
the
expres-
sive
information.
A
third possible determi-
nant—the
perceiver's
motoric
preparation
for
expressive
information—is
suggested
by
Zajonc
and
Markus's
(Note
3)
recent
finding
that
the
most accurate perceivers
are
those
whose
own
motor behavior shows
the
greatest
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
227
coordination
with
the
expressive
behavior
of
the
person being observed. Similarly, Laird,
Wagener,
Halal,
and
Szegda
(1982)
have
dem-
onstrated that recall
of
affect
was
best when
people's manipulated
facial
expressions were
consistent with
the
emotional content
of the
material recalled. These data suggest that
a
happy
observer
may
more readily detect
(or
recall)
happiness than other emotions,
an
angry
observer
may
more readily detect
an-
ger,
and so
forth.
They also suggest that per-
ceivers
who are
most sensitive
to
feedback
from
their
own
expressive behavior
may
more accurately detect
others'
emotions than
perceivers
who are
less self-aware. (See
McArthur,
Solomon,
&
Jaffee,
1980,
for re-
search
pertinent
to
such individual
differ-
ences.)
Impression
Formation
A
large proportion
of the
research
on
impression
formation
has
focused
on
peo-
ple's utilization
and
integration
of
trait
ad-
jectives
provided
in
written format
by the in-
vestigator.
Although this approach
to
impres-
sion
formation
may
provide
us
with
valuable
information
regarding cognitive processes
and
although
it
does have some ecological
validity—sometimes
we do
form
impressions
of
others
on the
basis
of
written adjectives,
such
as in
letters
of
recommendation—it
fails
to
capture many
of the
essential elements
of
the
typical impression-formation situation.
Stimulus
information.
In an
ecological
approach
to
perception,
one
examines
impression formation when perceivers
are
given
the
opportunity
to
see, hear,
and/or
in-
teract with
a
stimulus person. Perceivers,
thus,
are
able
to
extract information available
in
the
extensional properties
of
that person
as
opposed
to
information that
has
been dis-
tilled
or
fabricated
by an
experimenter.
In
such
situations,
the
perceiver
has
access
to
information
provided
by
demeanor,
vocal
qualities,
and
physiognomic characteristics.
Thus,
the
ecological approach
to
impression
formation
places more emphasis than tra-
ditional approaches
on
ascertaining what
in-
formation
is
extracted
from
these directly
perceptible attributes.
It
has
already been argued
that
vocal qual-
ities
and
physiognomy provide reliable
in-
formation
for the
perception
of
emotions,
and the
existing research literature
has
pro-
vided
data
to
support this assertion.
Is it
pos-
sible
that such characteristics also provide
information
concerning more stable attri-
butes
of
individuals, such
as
their traits
and/
or
their continuing
affordances?
Although
the
data pertinent
to
this question have
not
been
well
integrated into
the
mainstream
of re-
search
on
impression formation, there
is in
fact
considerable evidence that vocal char-
acteristics
as
well
as
facial
physiognomy exert
a
strong
influence
upon impressions
of a
per-
son's abilities
and
personality traits. (See
Knapp,
1980,
and
McArthur, 1982,
for re-
views
of
this literature.)
One
problem
with
the
foregoing research
is
that
it has
largely
been
a
shotgun approach
to
ascertaining what stimulus characteristics
yield
what impressions.
The
ecological
ap-
proach provides
a
sorely needed theoretical
framework
with guidelines concerning
the
type
of
stimulus information that
is apt to
reveal
traits
or
affordances
as
well
as the
types
of
traits
and
affordances
that
are
likely
to be
perceived. More
specifically,
the
ecological
approach calls
for an
examination
of the in-
formation
in
dynamic human behavior
as
apprehended
by an
active perceiver.
It
also
suggests
that
configural
stimulus information
may
be
more important than individual ele-
ments,
a
point that
is
consistent with evi-
dence
that
the
impact
of
particular
facial
fea-
tures
upon personality ratings
may
depend
upon
the
other features with which they
ap-
pear (Secord, Dukes,
&
Bevan, 1954; Secord
&
Muthard,
1955).
In
addition
to
suggesting
a
search
for
dynamic
and
configural
stimulus
information,
the
ecological approach sug-
gests
that
the
psychological attributes that
will
be
most clearly specified
in
this
infor-
mation
are
those that
are
most important
for
adaptive behavior.
The
assumption that per-
ception serves
an
adaptive function also
im-
plies
that
the
perceived
psychological
attri-
butes
will
be
accurate, provided that they
are
grounded
in
sufficient
stimulus information
as
apprehended
by an
appropriately attuned
perceiver. Although some studies have pro-
vided
evidence
for
accuracy (e.g., Kramer,
1963;
Scherer, 1978), most
of the
existing
re-
search either
has not
been concerned with
this question
or has
manipulated vocal
or
228
LESLIE
Z.
MoARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
physiognomic
attributes
in a
manner that
precludes
accurate impressions.
The
ecolog-
ical
approach
not
only highlights
the
accu-
racy
question
but
also,
in
examining per-
ceived
aftbrdances,
provides
one
solution
to
the
problem
of finding an
acceptable crite-
rion
for
judging
the
accuracy
of
impressions.
Species-wide
attunements.
One
constel-
lation
of
physical
attributes that should reveal
affordances
that
are
adaptive
for
perceivers
to
detect
are
those
associated
with infancy.
As
noted earlier, stimulus persons
who
pos-
sess
babyish physical features (decreased
strain
in the
craniofacial
profile,
proportion-
ately
larger eyes, shorter ears
and
nose)
are
perceived
as
affording
different
actions
and
reactions than persons
who do not
possess
these
features.
There
are
many other directly
perceptible
attributes that have adaptive sig-
nificance,
and
research designed
to
determine
what
impact these have
on
impressions
may
prove
fruitful.
For
example, there
are
hor-
monally
induced qualities
of
voice, appear-
ance,
and
gait that
may be
correlated with
physical
strength,
social
dominance,
or
sex-
ual
availability.
The
choice
of
perceptible
characteristics
to
study
may
also
be
informed
by
considering Secord's
(1958)
suggestion
that strong associations between particular
physical
characteristics
and
particular
behav-
iors
derive
from
the
function
of the
physical
attribute (e.g., women
with
large breasts
may
be
perceived
to
afford
nurturance),
from
metaphor
(e.g.,
people with poor posture
may
be
perceived
as
spineless),
or
from
temporal
extension (e.g.,
people
with
high-pitched
voices
may be
perceived
as
timid because
a
temporarily
high-pitched voice
reflects
fear).
Individual
attunements.
In
addition
to
focusing
attention upon stimulus informa-
tion
that reveals properties whose detection
has
adaptive significance
for all
humans,
the
ecological
approach
to
social perception
em-
phasizes
the
impact
of
individual
perceivers'
experience,
goals,
and
action capabilities
on
their
attunement
to
this
and
other informa-
tion.
Thus, although
one
might expect that
most perceivers
are
attuned
to the
physical
signs
of
chronic illness, these signs
may be
more readily perceived
by the
physician than
by
the lay
person,
not
only because this
in-
formation
is
more relevant
to the
physician's
behavioral
goals
but
also because extensive
experience
has
more
finely
tuned
the
physi-
cian's perceptual apparatus
to the
detection
of
these invariants.
A
physician
who
meets
on the
street
a man
with
red
discoloration
of the
cornea
and
notched
teeth
is
meeting
someone
who
openly displays
two of
Hutchinson's
signs
and
is
likely
to be
syphilitic.
Others
present, however,
medically
blind,
will
sec no
evil.
(Goffman,
1963,
p.
51)
Another
example
of
individual
differences
in
attunement
to
social invariants
is
provided
by
the
experiences
of the first
author
while
she
was
traveling through Europe. Several
people
whose acquaintance
she
made accu-
rately perceived
her
Jewish identity
from
her
appearance and/or demeanor.
As it
turned
out, these people were themselves Jewish,
and
they were
old
enough
to
have lived through
the
Holocaust.
One can
speculate that their
own
survival
required
a
keener attunement
to the
stimulus information that reveals
"Jewishness"
(see Savitz
&
Tomasson,
1959)
than
is
possessed
by the
average person whom
Jews
encounter
in the
United States. Given
the
likely
impact
of
perceptual experience
and
perceiver goals upon
the
detection
of in-
variants
in the
realm
of
social perception,
more research devoted
to
examining these
variables
should
be
enlightening.
Causal
Attribution
Most
of the
theory
and
research
on
peo-
ple's
causal
explanations
for
social
events
has
focused
upon
the
cognitive operations that
might
be
engaged
in by an
individual
in
order
to
infer
the
causes
of
reported
behaviors.
This
approach
to
causal attributions
is
certainly
a
useful
and
ecologically appropriate one.
Although
it has
been
argued
that
our
impres-
sions
of
others
are
more
often
than
not
based
upon
first-hand
perceptual information, this
is
probably
not the
case
for our
causal attri-
butions.
As
often
as we
ponder
the
causes
of
observed
behavior,
we
also ponder
the
causes
of
those behaviors that
we
learn
of
second
hand.
Although
the
focus
on
inferential pro-
cesses involved
in
causal attributions
is
well
placed,
we can
still lament
the
neglect
of
per-
ceptual processes.
Stimulus
information.
Michotte's
(1963)
work
has
demonstrated that there
is
stimulus
information
sufficient
for the
perception
of
physical
causality.
Yet
theories
and
research
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
229
dealing with
the
attribution
of
causality
in
the
social domain have focused almost
ex-
clusively
upon inference. Research
that
in-
vestigates
the
stimulus information
specify-
ing
social causality
is
needed
to
redress this
imbalance.
The
ecological approach suggests
that
such
research
must allow perceivers
to
watch, listen
to,
and/or
interact
with
the
peo-
ple
for
whom they
will
be
making causal
at-
tributions.
In
this manner,
one can
ascertain
what information
in the
extensional prop-
erties
of a
person
or
persons
is
sufficient
for
making
a
given attribution. And,
one can
thus begin
to
describe
the
stimulus invariants
that
give rise
to the
perception
of
social cau-
sality just
as
Michotte
described
the
stimulus
invariants
that give
rise to the
perception
of
physical
causality.
Some
of
the
research
on
causal
attributions
is
consistent with
the
foregoing goals.
For
example,
Dix (in
press)
has
recently dem-
onstrated
that
the
concrete depiction
of
low-
consensus information
may
allow young chil-
dren
to
perceive personal causality before
they
have developed
the
cognitive sophisti-
cation
to
infer
such causality
via the
appli-
cation
of
logical schemata. Other research
(Bassili,
1976)
has
described
the
stimulus
in-
variants that give rise
to the
perception
of
chasing,
an
example
of
social causality. Sim-
ilarly,
Kassin, Lowe,
and
Gibbons
(1980)
have
identified perceptual information
that
yields
the
perception
of two
other
causes
pushing
and
carrying.
Whereas
the
foregoing studies have
em-
ployed
either pen-and-ink sketches
or
ani-
mated geometric forms, other studies
em-
ploying
videotapes
of
real, interacting people
have
also taught
us
something
of
interest
re-
garding
the
stimulus information that
is
suf-
ficient
for
making
a
given attribution. When
we
watch
or
listen
to two
people
having
a
conversation,
the
person
who is for
some rea-
son
perceptually salient
is
seen
as
exerting
more causal influence than
the
person
who
is
less salient. This
effect
has
been demon-
strated
for a
wide range
of
salient attributes,
including
movement, bright lighting, louder
talking, boldly
patterned
clothing, novelty,
and
unit formation. (See
McArthur,
1981,
for
a
review
of
this
literature.)
Although
the im-
pact
of
salient stimulus
properties
upon per-
ceptions
of
causality
has
been amply dem-
onstrated,
the
question remains
as to why
this
occurs.
In
keeping with
the
inferential
ap-
proach
to
person perception,
a
number
of
cognitive
mediators have been proposed
and
tested (e.g.,
see
Fiske, Kenny,
&
Taylor,
1982).
On the
other hand, McArthur
(1980)
has
argued
that
the
ecological
approach
to
perception
may
suggest
a
more satisfactory
explanation
for the
tendency
to
perceive
sa-
lient
people
as
causal.
In the
context
of a
dynamic
social interaction, each person's
be-
havior
is
typically both cause
and
effect:
Per-
son A
reacts
to
Person
B and
that reaction
causes
a
reaction
in
Person
B. The
power
of
certain stimuli
to
draw attention
may
cause
the
perceiver
to
pick
up the
salient
person's
influence
on the
nonsalient person, rather
than
vice versa. Thus,
a
conversation between
a
soft
spoken person
and a
louder person
or
between
a
dimly
lit
person
and a
more
brightly
lit
person
may be
registered
in
units
reflecting
the
causal
influence
of the
louder
or
brighter actor
on the
quieter
or
dimmer
actor rather than
in
units reflecting
the re-
verse
causal
influence.
Although
no
research
has
successfully
assessed
the
perceptual
or-
ganization
of a
social interaction
involving
salient
and
nonsalient stimulus persons, there
is
evidence
to
indicate that such organization
is
responsive
to
salience manipulations
(Newtson,
Rindner, Miller,
&
LaCross,
1978)
and
that
it is
related
to
perceived causality
(Massad,
Hubbard,
&
Newtson, 1979). Such
evidence clearly warrants more research
de-
voted
to
investigating
the
impact
of
percep-
tual,
as
opposed
to
cognitive,
influences
upon
the
attribution
of
social causality.
An
Ecological Perspective
on the
Nature
of
Error
in
Social Perception
Most
current
thinking
in the
domains
of
social perception
and
cognition either takes
as
axiomatic
the
proposition
that
our
knowl-
edge
of the
social environment
is
highly
error
prone (e.g., Nisbett
&
Ross, 1980; Ross,
1977)
or
simply
ignores
the
accuracy prob-
lem
altogether
in
favor
of a
process analysis
that focuses
on the
cognitive operations
in-
tervening
between stimulus
and
response
(e.g., Anderson, 1974; Newtson, 1976).
Moreover, when
the
problem
is
discussed,
in-
ferential
processes
are
typically assigned
the
230
LESLIE
Z.
MCARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
role
of
straightening
out the
noisy data
of
perception
as in
Taylor
and
Fiske's (1978)
adaptation
of the
Brunswikian model
of
per-
ception. Indeed, within mainstream social
cognition, putting
the
term perceived before
a
construct,
as in
perceived control
or
per-
ceived
crowding,
automatically
confers
a
sub-
jectivity
and
lack
of
trustworthiness
to
that
source
of
data.
In
sharp contrast
to
such views,
the
eco-
logical
perspective
emphasizes
the
essential
accuracy
of
perception-based
knowledge (e.g.,
Ittelson,
1973). And, because
J.
Gibson (1979)
strongly
argues that perception
of the
social
environment
is
likely
to
follow
the
same basic
principles
as
perception
of the
nonsocial
en-
vironment,
an
ecological model challenges
the
current view that social perceptions
are
more
often
flawed
than not. Before
attempt-
ing
to
reconcile these contrasting perspec-
tives,
some comment
is
needed regarding
Gibson's equation
of
social
and
nonsocial
perception, since
one
must certainly
ac-
knowledge
differences
between
the
two. Most
notably,
people, unlike
oak
trees,
do try to
deceive
perceivers. However, there
is
substan-
tial
evidence that perceivers
can
detect
de-
ception
in the
stimulus information that
the
deceiver projects (e.g., Runeson
&
Frykholm,
1982;
Zuckerman, DePaulo,
&
Rosenthal,
1981).
Moreover, when perceivers
fail
to de-
tect deception, their error
may
reflect
lack
of
sufficient
motivation
or
even collusion with
the
deceiver
rather
than
inadequacies
in
per-
ceptual
ability (cf.
Goffman,
1959). These
considerations bolster
the
ecological view
that
social perception,
like
nonsocial percep-
tion,
is
essentially accurate.
The
question
re-
mains
as to how we can
reconcile this per-
spective
with
the
more current
view.
The
Meaning
of
Error
and
Bias
At
the
outset,
it
should
be
made clear that
there appears
to be a
qualitative
difference
in
the
meaning
of
error
when
one
approaches
social
perception
from
an
ecological perspec-
tive
as
opposed
to an
inferential-constructive
one. Within
the
ecological perspective,
the
criterion
for
accuracy
is the
efficacy
of
one's
behavioral adjustments
to a
distal
object:
Error
occurs when one's knowledge
of the
world
does
not
permit adaptive action
(i.e.,
does
not
allow
one to
accomplish behavioral
goals). Within
an
inferential framework,
the
criterion
for
accuracy
is the
logicality
of
one's
reasoning processes,
and
error occurs when
one
manifests problems
in
reasoning. Within
the
latter framework, error
and
bias
are
syn-
onymous. However, within
an
ecological
framework,
bias
is
different
from
error: Bias
is
simply
a
matter
of
selective attention
and
action,
and
whether
a
given bias leads
to
error
in
adaptive behavior
is an
empirical,
not a
logical, problem.
Sins
of
Omission
Although
consistently arguing
for the
gen-
eral veridicality
of
perception,
J.
Gibson
(1966)
leaves room
for
certain kinds
of
error
based
both
on
deficiencies
in the
information
available
at a
given
time
as
well
as on
the
inherent
selectivity
in any
perceiver's pickup
of
information. Thus, Gibson states:
In
an
eventful
environment with sights
and
sounds
and
smells
and
touches
all
around,
the
individual
cannot
reg-
ister
everything
at
once,
and his
perception must there-
fore
be
selective
. . .
What
the
object really
affords
may
be
missed
and
what
the
observer perceives
it as
affording
may
be
mistaken,
(p.
309)
Missing what
an
object really
affords
may be
called
an
error
of
omission. However,
from
an
ecological viewpoint such
as
that espoused
by
Shaw, Turvey,
and
Mace (1982),
to
label
all
such omissions
as
error
is
wrong because
such labeling ignores
the
adaptive specificity
of
the
perceptual system. More
specifically,
they argue
that
the
essential accuracy
of
per-
ception rests upon
the
ability
of
animals
to
be
sensitive
to
adaptively relevant informa-
tion
as
opposed
to all
possible information.
Thus, these theorists would
not
want
to
call
a
bat's
perception
in
error when
it
misses
purely
visual information,
nor
would they
say
that humans' perceptions
are in
error
when
they miss ultraviolet information
or
high-frequency
auditory information.
When omissions
occur
at the
species
level,
most would probably agree that
it is
dubious
to
even
refer
to
them
as
errors. However,
the
issue
within species
is
more controversial.
For
example,
if an
expert
in a
given domain sees
more than
a
novice,
do we
want
to
call
the
novice's perceptions
in
error?
If
the
Eskimos
see
more
varieties
of
snow than
we do, are
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
231
our
perceptions
in
error?
If we use as our
criterion
for
accurate perception
the
detec-
tion
of
affordances
that
are
essential
to
adap-
tive
action, then
we
probably would
not
want
to
call even these omissions
"errors."
Of
course, there
are
omissions
in
which perceiv-
ers
fail
to
detect affordances essential
to
their
own
actions. Some
of
these would have
to be
labeled
'error'
within
an
ecological perspec-
tive,
for
example,
failing
to
perceive
an
attack
dog
as
vicious. However, even some
mal-
adaptive
omissions would
not be
labeled
er-
ror
within
the
ecological approach
if
they
re-
sulted
from
impoverished stimulus infor-
mation.
The
failure
to
detect
an
affordance
may
often
result
from
an
artificial
reduction
in the
information
available
to the
perceiver. Some-
times
the
reduction
in
information derives
from
static, temporally truncated,
or
other-
wise
nonrepresentative stimulus displays that
have
been constructed
in the
interests
of ex-
perimental purity
as
opposed
to
ecological
validity.
At
other
times,
it
derives from
re-
stricting
the
perceiver's ability
to
actively
ex-
plore
the
available stimulus information.
Certainly
the
veridicality
of
oner's
percep-
tions
is
typically enhanced
as
more complete
stimulus
information
is
provided.
In the so-
cial
domain,
for
example, accurate identifi-
cation
of
personal identity, gender,
and
type
of
affect
from
Johannson-type
point-light
displays
is
possible
only when
dynamic,
as
opposed
to
static, displays
are
used.
7
Other
research indicates that
the
perception
of
higher
order social properties,
such
as ma-
levolent
and
benevolent intent, requires
not
only
dynamic information,
but
also rela-
tional
information such
as
that provided
by
the
joint spatial
and
temporal trajectories
of
the
entities involved (Bassili,
1976).
Thus,
information
from
an
interpersonal behavior
sequence
is
likely
to
yield more complete
and
accurate perceptions than information about
the
behavior
of a
single actor
at a
single point
in
time.
Just
as
impoverished information
can re-
sult
from
nondynamic stimuli,
it can
also
result
from
an
inactive perceiver. Consider
for
example
the
fact
that touch comes
to the
aid
of
vision when
a
stick
in the
water that
looks
bent
feels
straight. Similarly,
a
closer
look
corrects
a
more distant one,
and a mi-
rage
disappears. Within
the
social domain,
being
able
to
interact with another person
as
well
as to
passively watch
and
listen
to him
or her may
also dispel
a
number
of
errors.
Because
an
intermodal
and
temporally
ex-
tended
sampling
of
environmental stimulus
information
is the
natural
condition
for ef-
fective
functioning
of the
perceptual systems,
omissions that occur when such sampling
is
precluded
are not
viewed
as
error
in the
eco-
logical
approach
to
perception.
Sins
ofComission
J.
Gibson,
as
quoted before, suggests that
what
an
object
is
perceived
as
affording
may
sometimes
be
mistaken,
an
event that
can be
called
an
error
of
comission. However,
from
a
radical ecological viewpoint,
it is
inappro-
priate
to
label
all
such mistakes
as
error
in
the
sense that many
of
them
may
have
no
bearing
on
adaptive
actions.
Consider
the fol-
lowing
example: Based
on the
fact
that
the
prey
of
sharks normally produce
a
charac-
teristic
electric
field, it is
possible
to
lure,
a
shark
to
strike
at an
artificial electric
field as
if
it
were prey.
If
edibility
and
certain
electric
field
properties
are
correlated
in the
shark's
natural niche,
is the
shark really
in
error?
Shouldn't
the
criterion
for
error
be the
nat-
ural,
as
opposed
to the
experimental, struc-
ture
of
reality, because
the
perceptual systems
are
attuned
to
natural contingencies?
Of
course,
there
are
comissions
in
naturalistic
settings
and one
would probably want
to
call
these
"errors."
However, there
is an
impor-
tant
difference
between
an
ecological per-
spective
on
such errors
and
more traditional
views.
From
the
ecological perspective,
the
nature
of
these errors should
not be
random.
Rather, such errors should
be
rooted
in
strat-
egies
of
information
pickup
and/or
attune-
ment
to
particular invariants that usually
serve
an
adaptive function
for the
perceiver.
Thus, what
we
label
"errors
of
comission"
are
likely
to be
overgeneralizations
of
highly
adaptive perceptual attunements.
The
phe-
7
Needless
to
say,
the
point-light
research
does
not
provide
complete
stimulus
information.
It is
cited
here
only
to
demonstrate
that
with
increasing
stimulus
in-
formation (e.g., dynamic
as
opposed
to
static
displays),
there will
be
increased
veridicality
of
perceptions.
232
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
nomena
of
illusory causation
and
illusory
correlation that have received considerable
attention within
the field of
social perception
may
be
instances
of
such overgeneralization.
Illusory
causation.
The
tendency
to at-
tribute causal
influence
to
perceptually
sa-
lient persons
has
been called
the
illusory
cau-
sation
effect
(McArthur,
1980).
It
seems plau-
sible
to
suggest
that
such
"errors"
may
result
from
the
overgeneralization
of a
highly
adap-
tive
perceptual attunement. More
specifi-
cally,
it may be
that perceptually salient stim-
uli
are
actually more likely than nonsalient
stimuli
to
exert causal
influence
in the en-
vironment,
and our
perceptual apparatus
may
have evolved
to
process information
in
a
manner that
is
maximally sensitive
to
this
reality.
This proposal gains credence when
one
considers
the
causal
efficacy
of
percep-
tually
salient stimuli
in the
natural environ-
ment:
Bright lights, such
as
lightening
or fires,
and
loud sounds, such
as
thunder,
a
roaring
animal,
or a
screaming baby,
are
more
apt
to
exert causal influence than their less
in-
tense
counterparts. Similarly, moving stim-
uli,
such
as a
charging bull,
and
unit-forming
stimuli,
such
as a
herd
of
buffalo,
are
more
apt to
exert causal influence than
a
stationary
or
unrelated collection
of
animals.
If our
per-
ceptual
systems were
not
more attuned
to the
causal
influences
of
salient stimuli
on
non-
salient
stimuli then vice versa, then
we
might
not
live
long enough
to
detect causal invari-
ants through more "objective" registration
of
the
information available.
Illusory
correlation.
Another error
of so-
cial
perception that
may be
rooted
in
adap-
tive
perceptual functioning
is
illusory
corre-
lation:
People's perceptions
of the
correlation
between
events tend
to be
unduly
influenced
by
certain event pairs. These
effects
have been
demonstrated both
in the
realm
of
nonsocial
perception (e.g., Chapman, 1967)
and in the
realm
of
person perception, where
the
illu-
sory
correlation concerns
an
actor-behavior
link.
More
specifically,
certain types
of be-
havior
are
perceived
to be
more representa-
tive
of
certain categories
of
people than they
really
are
(e.g., Chapman
&
Chapman,
1967;
Hamilton
&
Gifford,
1976; McArthur
&
Friedman, 1980). Within
the
framework
of
an
ecological approach
to
perception,
the in-
teresting question posed
by the
phenomenon
of
illusory correlation
is
"What
strategies
of
information
pickup and/or what kinds
of co-
occurrences will lead
the
perceiver
to
detect
an
invariant relationship (i.e.,
a
correlation)
that
is not
present?"
Since
perceivers cannot possibly process
all
available information,
it
seems adaptive
for
the
perceptual systems
to be
geared
to
pick
up
information that
is the
most ecolog-
ically
significant.
This might include
infor-
mation
from
stimuli that
are
intense,
un-
usual,
rare,
or
aversive, because events
in-
volving
stimuli with these characteristics
are
more
apt to
require adaptive responding than
events
involving more mundane stimuli.
In
view
of
this argument
it is
significant
that
research reveals greater visual
fixation of so-
cial
stimuli that
are
extreme (i.e., intense
and
atypical),
infrequent,
or
negative
(Fiske,
1980;
McArthur
&
Ginsburg,
1981).
Moreover,
these
are the
very stimuli that tend
to be in-
volved
in
illusory correlation
effects
(Ham-
ilton
&
Gifford,
1976;
Rothbart,
Fulero, Jen-
son,
Howard,
&
Birrell,
1978).
It
thus appears
that illusory correlation
effects
may
derive
from
the
selective registration
of
information
that
it is
particularly important
for
perceivers
to
detect, such
as
unfamiliar
people perform-
ing
unusual, negative,
or
intense acts.
Illusory
correlation
may
also derive
from
the
selective registration
of
information that
is
typical
or
representative
of the
natural
en-
vironment.
A
perceptual system attuned
to
typical
correlations would
be
more
efficient
than
one
that discovered each correlation
anew.
Thus,
for
example, large objects (in-
cluding
people)
may be
perceived
as
affording
more
physical resistance, more danger,
or
even
more noise than small ones, because this
is
typically
the
case.
8
This example illustrates
8
A
similar explanation
may be
offered
for the
per-
ceived correlation between physical
attractiveness
and
social
and
intellectual competencies
(e.g.,
Berscheid
&
Walster,
1974).
Specifically,
this
illusory
correlation
may
derive
from
a
veridical
correlation
between
the
unat-
tractiveness
that results
from
various
physical
abnor-
malities
and the
corresponding
disorders
of
social
and
intellectual functioning.
The
perceived
correlation
be-
tween
physical attractiveness
and
honesty (e.g., Berry
&
McArthur,
Note
2) may
also
have
its
roots
in a
verid-
ical
correlation.
It has
been found
that
when
people
are
telling
the
truth,
they look
more
attractive
than
when
they
are
lying
(Krauss,
1981).
SOCIAL PERCEPTION
233
the
possibility that illusory correlations
in the
realm
of
person perception
may
derive
from
attunement
to
co-occurrences whose adap-
tive significance
is
grounded
in the
physical
realm.
It
also illustrates
the
perception
of
cross-modal correlations,
a
phenomenon that
has
been
well
documented
by
Marks
(1978).
Indeed, even newborn infants
associate
par-
ticular
auditory stimuli with particular visual
ones (Born, Spelke,
&
Prather,
Note
4),
which
indicates that perceiving certain kinds
of in-
formation
as
correlated
is not
dependent
upon extensive learning about natural cor-
respondences,
but
rather
is a
fundamental
perceptual
preparedness.
Self-fulfilling
prophecies.
A
third
error
of
commission
that warrants discussion
in
con-
sidering
an
ecological approach
to
social per-
ception
is
that
of
self-fulfilling
prophecies.
Such
effects
fall
into
two
general categories:
(a)
eliciting
from
others
the
behaviors
we ex-
pect
to
perceive,
and (b)
perceiving
in
others
the
behaviors
and
traits
we
expect
to
perceive.
Although
these
findings
seem problematic
for
a
theory that emphasizes
the
essential accu-
racy
of
social perceptions,
a
closer analysis
reveals
that they
may be
reconciled
with
the
ecological approach.
First,
the
research documenting
a
tendency
for
perceivers
to
elicit
the
very
behavior they
expect
to
perceive provides
no
real problem
for
an
ecological theory
of
perception.
In
these
cases,
the
perceiver detects properties
in
the
target person that
are
actually mani-
fested
in
behavior. Indeed,
the
accuracy
of
these perceptions
is
often
affirmed
by
ratings
of
the
target person's behavior
by
blind judges
who
have
no
"prophecy"
(e.g., Snyder,
Tanke,
&
Berscheid, 1977). Thus,
the
"error"
in
these
self-fulfilling
prophecy
effects
is not
misperception
but
rather misguided
action
that
is,
action that
has not
been
sufficiently
informed
by
perception.
A
second type
of
self-fulfilling
prophecy,
perhaps better labeled
a
self-confirming
prophecy,
is
more problematic
for the
eco-
logical position.
This
is the
tendency
for
per-
ceivers
to
detect
in
other people those prop-
erties that they expect
to find,
such that very
different
properties
may be
detected
in the
same behavioral information
by
perceivers
with
different
expectations (e.g.,
Kelley,
1950;
Langer
&
Abelson,
1974;MassadetaL,
1979;
Snyder
&
Frankel,
1976).
Like illusory cor-
relation
and
illusory
causation, such
effects
may
reflect
in
part
the
overgeneralization
of
an
adaptive
perceptual attunement:
To the
extent
that
our
expectations
are
more
often
right
than wrong,
it may be
functional
to be
particularly
sensitive
to
confirmatory stim-
ulus
information.
These
effects
may
also
be
a
reflection
of
ambiguities
in the
stimulus
information.
More
specifically,
they
may oc-
cur in
situations
in
which
the
behavioral
in-
formation
has no
underlying
structural
in-
variant—that
is,
there
are no
properties that
remain
the
same under changes
in the
sam-
pling
of
behavior across space
or
time.
If so,
then
two
observers, taking
different
samples
of
behavior, would
not
necessarily detect
the
same
underlying property.
It
follows
from
this
argument
that
self-confirming
prophecies
should
not
occur
in the
case
of
attributes
that
are
indeed invariant. Although researchers
have
begun
to
question whether people have
dispositional
invariants (e.g.,
Mischel,
1968),
some people
do
seem
to
have some
traits
(e.g.,
Bern
&
Allen,
1974).
In
these cases,
one
would
expect that
different
samples
of the
same person's behavior would tend
to
reveal
the
same invariant
disposition.
One
would
also expect that
the
detection
of
this invariant
disposition could
not be
overpowered
by er-
roneous
initial prophecies
of a
self-confirm-
ing
nature.
In
addition
to the
possibility that some
people
will
provide information
for
struc-
tural
invariants that
is
immune
to
self-ful-
filling
prophecy
effects,
it is
also likely that
there exist transformational invariants
and
affordances
that
are
immune
to
such
effects.
More
specifically,
invariant properties whose
detection serves important adaptive
actions,
such
as the
transformational invariant
fight-
ing
or the
affordance
danger,
may be so
strongly
manifested
in the
stimulus
infor-
mation that people project that they could
not be
overpowered
by
erroneous prophecies.
Some evidence
for
this assertion
is
provided
in a
recent study
by
Woll
and
Martinez
(1982),
who
found that biasing labels
for a
pictured facial expression influenced recog-
nition memory when
the
expression depicted
a
pleasant
or
neutral emotion,
but not
when
it
depicted
an
unpleasant emotion. Insofar
as the
accurate detection
of
unpleasant
emo-
234
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
tions
has
greater adaptive
significance
than
the
accurate
detection
of
neutral
or
pleasant
ones,
this
finding is
consistent with
the
eco-
logical
view.
So is the finding
that
the
influ-
ence
of
biasing
labels upon recognition
of any
of
the
emotions
was
limited
to the
condition
in
which there
was a
15-minute
delay
be-
tween
the
original presentation
of the
emo-
tional expressions
and the
recognition
task.
In
a
1-minute
delay condition, where per-
ceptual
information would
be
more salient,
the
labels
had no
impact
on
recognition.
Although
the
ecological approach must
acknowledge
errors
in
social perception such
as
illusory
causation, illusory correlation,
and
self-fulfilling
prophecy,
it
incorporates
such
errors into
a
theoretical framework that
argues
for the
general veridicality
of
percep-
tion.
In
particular,
it
suggests that
errors
of
comission
may
reflect
the
overgeneralization
of
highly
adaptive perceptual attunements.
Conclusions
The
ecological approach
to
social percep-
tion
provides
an
innovative conception
of
what
is
perceived,
how it is
perceived,
and
who
perceives
it.
What
is
perceived
is first
and
foremost what perceivers need
to
per-
ceive
for
adaptive interaction with their
en-
vironment.
Thus,
the
ecological approach
assumes
that perception
is by and
large
ve-
ridical.
It
also assumes that
we
often
perceive
affordances
as
opposed
to the
isolated struc-
tural
properties that have traditionally been
studied.
How
these affordances
are
perceived
is
through
the
dynamic, multimodal
infor-
mation
in
events. This
is
necessitated
by the
fact
that
affordances
are
typically complex
properties that have
no
one-to-one
connec-
tion
to the
static, stimulus elements that
are
provided
to
perceivers
in
traditional research
paradigms.
Who
perceives various
afford-
ances
are
those
for
whom these properties
are
behaviorally
relevant. Perceptual altune-
ments
thus
vary
not
only
as a
function
of the
cognitive
factors that
are
studied
in
tradi-
tional
approaches,
but
also with perceptual
experience, behavioral
capabilities,
and on-
going
behavior.
The
advantages
of
social perception
re-
search
within
the
ecological framework
are
numerous.
The
emphasis
on
information
in
the
stimulus provides
a
needed balance
to the
current emphasis
on
constructive
processes
in
the
perceiver.
The
emphasis
on
dynamic
stimulus
displays provides
a
needed balance
to
research that examines perceptions
of
peo-
ple
who are
neither seen
nor
heard.
The em-
phasis
on the
dynamic relationship between
perception
and
action directs attention
to the
rather neglected question
of
social
percep-
tions
within ongoing relationships, where
perceptions
are
informed
by
actions
and
where people really
do
have
the
opportunity
to
perceive
one
another's invariant attributes.
The
emphasis
on
perceived
affordances
pro-
vides
a
vital alternative
to the
trait analysis
of
social perception. And, more generally,
the
emphasis upon
the
adaptive function
of
per-
ception places formerly disconnected
re-
search issues
into
an
integrated
conceptual
framework
that generates
new
questions
and
promises
to
greatly enrich
our
understanding
of
social perception.
As
the
foregoing conclusions reveal,
the
ecological
approach
to
social perception dif-
fers
in a
number
of
respects
from
traditional
information-processing
models.
An
addi-
tional, metatheoretical
difference
between
the
two
approaches warrants some explicit
discussion. Whereas
the
ecological
approach
views
perception
as the act of
picking
up in-
variant
information
from
the
environment,
the
information-processing approach views
perception
as a
process
of
inference
that must
be
elucidated
by
specifying
the
cognitive pro-
cesses intervening between sensory inputs
and the
perceptual outcome.
This
difference
between
the
information-processing
and
eco-
logical
approaches
is
perhaps best exempli-
fied
by
their divergent
perspectives
regarding
the
meaning
and
utility
of the
schema con-
struct.
From
the
ecological perspective,
the
assumption
of an
internal,
reified
state
that
causally
mediates meaning
is
neither neces-
sary
nor
desirable. Instead
of
postulating
such
a
representational structure,
the
ecolog-
ical
approach simply assumes
that
the
past
history
of
one's interaction with
the
environ-
ment
consistently retunes
the
perceptual
ap-
paratus
on an
online basis.
Thus,
the
"ghost
in
the
machine" becomes superfluous. (See
Baron,
1980,
for a
more extended discussion
of
logical problems with using
the
schema
construct.)
Furthermore,
a
close look
at the
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
235
properties
of
events suggests
that
they serve
many
of the
same epistemic
functions
as
schemata.
Both
schemata
and
events
are
abstract,
global,
and
generalized structures involving
higher
order relationships that hold over par-
ticulars. Indeed,
at the
conceptual level
the
major
difference
between these constructs
is
whether
one
assumes that such abstract
knowledge
or
information structures exist
solely
in
one's head
or
have counterparts
in
the
world
as
events.
For
example,
is the
causal
efficacy
of
personal
effort
an
event
to be de-
tected
or the
creation
of a
schema? Similarly,
are
higher social relationships, such
as de-
pendency, events
to be
perceived given
a
properly
attuned observer
or are
they
the
products
of a
higher level constructive pro-
cess?
The
ecological view
is
that most,
if not
all,
adaptively relevant properties
are
exten-
sionally
projected. However,
it is
acknowl-
edged
that
the
detection
of
some
of
these
properties requires extensive perceptual
learning and,
in the
absence
of
such learning,
may
require inference. Thus,
it is
possible
even
likely—that
there
are
both internal
and
external sources
of
organization
and
struc-
ture. Still,
we
would argue that
the
internal
structures must
be
based upon
the
external
ones.
As
such,
to
fully
understand schemata
requires
an
understanding
of the
stimulus
in-
formation
that
is out
there serving
as
grist
for
the
schema mill.
There
are
several types
of
evidence relevant
to
differentiating
the
direct detection
of
stim-
ulus
information
from
constructive, infer-
ential processes.
Before
enumerating these,
it
is
important
to
state
that direct perception
basically
refers
to the
sufficiency
of the
per-
ceptual apparatus
to
extract certain environ-
mental meanings (e.g.,
affordances)
without
the
intervention
of
higher order cognitive
operations. Directness
in
this view does
not
mean directness
in the
phenomenological
sense
of the
immediacy
of the
perceptual
ex-
perience, although this
is
often
a
concomitant
of
direct
perception.
The
most basic evidence
for the
direct
de-
tection
of
functional information indepen-
dent
of
constructive cognitive operations
is
provided
by
research
that
demonstrates
the
ability
of
organisms with very limited cog-
nitive abilities (e.g., young infants
and
infra-
humans)
to
detect
relatively
abstract,
cross-
modal invariances
in
stimulus information.
(See
Born, Spelke,
&
Prather, Note
4, and
also
E.
Gibson
&
Spelke,
in
press,
for a
com-
prehensive
review
of the
infant
literature
on
this
topic.)
A
second source
of
relevant evi-
dence
is
naturalistic
and
experimental situ-
ations that demonstrate people's
ability
to
preserve
the
essential characteristics
of
rap-
idly
changing stimulus displays
in
their
online
responses.
For
example,
the
tennis player
at
the
net is
able
to
adroitly adjust
his or her
racket
to the
trajectory
of a
speeding
ball.
9
Similarly,
in the
social realm, people adroitly
adjust
their
own
nonverbal responses
to
rapid
changes
in
such responses
by
those with
whom
they interact (e.g.,
the
"eyebrow
flash",
Eibl-Eibesfeldt,
1975).
In
these examples,
perceiving
and
responding
are
instanta-
neously
coordinated,
and to
posit intervening
cognitive
processes seems gratuitous.
A
third
type
of
evidence
for the
sufficiency
of the
perceptual apparatus
to
extract environmen-
tal
meanings
is
demonstrations that changes
in
those meanings
are
closely,
if not
perfectly,
tied
to
changes
in the
available stimulus
in-
formation.
For
example,
in
research
on the
perception
of
aging, Shaw
and
Pittenger
(1977)
have argued
for a
psychophysical
re-
lationship between
the
objective, physical
changes that characterize
the
aging
face
and
the
perception
of
aging:
As
certain systematic
changes
occur
in the
cranium
and the
jawline
of
a
face
(the cardiodal strain transforma-
tion),
so
will
there
be
systematic changes
in
the
perceived
age of
that
face.
In
sum,
the
direct detection
of
meaning
in
objective stim-
ulus
information,
as
opposed
to the
subjec-
tive
construction
of
meaning,
is
evidenced
by
(a)
adaptive responses
to
stimulus informa-
tion
by
cognitively limited organisms,
(b)
adaptive, online responses
to
stimulus
infor-
mation that
is
rapidly changing,
and (c) re-
9
The
online coordination
of
seeing
and
doing speaks
to the
directness
of
perception
in at
least
two
ways:
(a)
The
joint
locomotor
movements
of the
perceiver
and the
target modulate
the
visual
flow
field
in
ways that help
specify
the
location
of the
target
(J.
Gibson,
1966;
Turvey,
1977),
and (b) the
requirement
for
both
speed
and ac-
curacy
of
responding suggests that
the fine-grained
con-
trol
of
action occurs
at
lower levels
of
brain functioning
that
do not
involve
the
higher order cognitive mechanism
of the
executive (Turvey, 1977).
236
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
sponses
that vary directly with
specifiable
changes
in the
objective stimulus
informa-
tion.
Whether
or not
readers accept
all of the
specific
suppositions
of the
ecological frame-
work,
we
hope that they
now do
accept
the
distinct
and
important role
of
perception
in
social
knowing—a
role that goes
far
beyond
a
primitive,
first-state,
registration
of
inputs.
And
we
hope
that
at
least some readers
will
be
challenged
to
pursue research
that
can
explicate
the
nature
of
social stimulus
infor-
mation
and
social perception. Perceptual
in-
formation
is
sometimes
sufficient
for
social
knowledge,
sometimes
it is
only
the
necessary
datum
for
social
inference
processes.
In
either
case,
we
cannot hope
to
fully
understand
so-
cial
cognition without understanding
the
per-
ceptual
information
on
which
it is
based:
"The idea exists only
by
virtue
of the
form."
Reference
Notes
1.
McArthur,
L.
Z,,
&
Apatow,
K.
Impressions
ofbaby-
Jaced
males.
Unpublished
manuscript,
Brandeis
Uni-
versity,
1983.
2.
Berry,
D., &
McArthur,
L. Z.
Impressions
of
college
males
rated
as
baby-faced versus mature-faced.
Manuscript
in
preparation, Brandeis University, 1983.
3.
Zajonc,
R. B., &
Markus,
H.
Affect
and
cognition:
The
hard
interface.
Unpublished manuscript, Uni-
versity
of
Michigan, 1981.
4.
Born,
W.
S.,
Spelkc,
E. S., &
Prather,
P.
Detection
of
auditory-visual relationships
by
newborn
infants.
Pa-
per
presented
at the
International
Conference
on In-
fant
Studies,
Austin, Texas, March 1982.
References
Alley,
T. R.
Caregiving
and the
perception
of
matura-
tional
status.
Unpublished
doctoral
dissertation, Uni-
versity
of
Connecticut,
1981.
Anderson,
N. H.
Cognitive algebra: Integration theory
applied
to
social attribution.
In L.
Berkowitz
(Ed.),
Advances
in
experimental social
psychology
(Vol.
7).
New
York: Academic Press, 1974.
Andrews,
R. J. The
origins
of
facial
expressions.
Sci-
entific
American, 1965,
213,
88-94.
Archer,
D.,
&
Akert,
R.
Words
and
everything
else:
Ver-
bal
and
nonverbal cues
in
social interpretation. Jour-
nal of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1977,
35,
443-449.
Asch,
S. E.
Social psychology.
Englewood
Cliffs,
N.J.:
Prentice Hall, 1952.
Averill,
J.
Anger
and
aggression:
An
essay
on
emotion.
New
York:
Springer-Verlag,
1983.
Bagby,
J. W. A
cross-cultural study
of
perceptual pre-
dominance
in
binocular
rivalry.
Journal
of
Abnormal
and
Social
Psychology,
1957,
54,
331-334.
Baron,
R. M.
Social knowing
from
an
ecological
event
perspective:
A
consideration
of the
relative
domains
of
power
for
cognitive
and
perceptual modes
of
know-
ing.
In J.
Harvey
(Ed.),
Cognition,
social behavior,
and
the
environment.
Hillsdale,
N.J.:
Erlbaum,
1980.
Bassili,
J. N.
Temporal
and
spatial
contingencies
in the
perception
of
social
events.
Journal
uf
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1976,
33,
680-685.
Bassili,
J. N.
Facial motion
in the
perception
of
faces
and of
emotional expression. Journal
of
Experimental
Psychology:
Human
Perception
and
Performance,
1978,
4,
373-379.
Bassili,
J. N.
Emotion recognition.
The
role
of
facial
movement
and the
relative importance
of
upper
and
lower
areas
of the
face.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1979,
37,
2049-2058.
Bern,
D.
J.,
&
Allen,
A. On
predicting
some
of
the
people
some
of the
time:
The
search
for
cross-situational
con-
sistencies
in
behavior. Psychological Review, 1974,
81,
506-520.
Berscheid,
E.,
&
Walster,
E.
Physical attractiveness.
In
L.
Berkowitz
(Ed.),
Advances
in
experimental social
psychology
(Vol.
7).
New
York:
Academic
Press,
1974.
Buck,
R.,
Baron,
R.,
&
Barrette,
D.
Temporal organi-
zation
of
spontaneous emotional expression:
A
seg-
mentation analysis. Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1982,
42,
506-517.
Chapman,
L. J.
Illusory correlation
in
observational
re-
port. Journal
of
Verbal
Learning
and
Verbal
Behavior,
1967,
6,
151-J55.
Chapman,
L.
J.,
&
Chapman,
J. P.
Genesis
of
popular
but
erroneous psychodiagnostic observations. Journal
of
Abnormal
Psychology,
1967,
72,
193-204.
Cutting,
J. E.
Generation
of
synthetic
male
and
female
walkers
through manipulation
of a
biomechanical
in-
variant. Perception, 1978,
7,
393-405.
Cutting,
J.
E.,
Proffitt,
D.
R.,
&
Kozlowski,
L. T. A
bio-
mechanical invariant
for
gait perception.
Journal
of
Experimental
Psychology:
Human
Perception
and
Per-
formance, 1978,
4,
357-372.
Darwin,
C.
Expression
of
the
emotions
in man and an-
imals. London: Murray, 1872.
Dix,
T. H.
Inference complexity
and
informational
sa-
lience
in the
development
of a
consensus-based causal
attribution.
Child Development,
in
press.
Eibl-Eibesfeldt,
I.
Ethology:
The
biology
of
behavior.
New
York:
Holt,
Rinchart,
&
Winston, 1975.
Ekman,
P.
Universals
and
cultural
differences
in
facial
expressions
of
emotion. Nebraska Symposium
on
Motivation,
1971,
18,
207-283.
Engel,
E. The
role
of
content
in
binocular
resolution.
American Journal
of
Psychology,
1956,
69,
87-91.
Erdelyi,
M. H. A new
look
at the new
look: Perceptual
defense
and
vigilance. Psychological Review,
1974,
81,
1-25.
Fcldman,
R.
S.,
&
Donohue,
L.
F.
Nonverbal commu-
nication
of
affect
in
interracial dyads. Journal
of
Ed-
ucational
Psychology,
1978,
70,
979-987.
Fiske,
S. T.
Attention
and
weight
in
person
perception:
The
impact
of
negative
and
extreme behavior. Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1980,
38,
889-
908.
Fiske,
S.
T.,
Kenny,
D.
A.,
&
Taylor,
S. E.
Structural
models
for the
mediation
of
salience
effects
on
attri-
bution. Journal
of
Experimental Social
Psychology,
1982,
18.
105-127.
SOCIAL
PERCEPTION
237
Gibson,
E. J.
Principles
of
perceptual
learning
and de-
velopment.
New
York:
Appleton-Century-Crofts,
1969.
Gibson,
E. J. The
concept
of
aftbrdances
in
development:
The
renascence
of
functionalism.
In W. A.
Collins
(Ed.).
Minnesota Symposia
on
Child
Psychology
(Vol.
15).
Hillsdale, N.J.:
Erlbaum,
1982.
Gibson,
E.
J.,
&
Spelke,
E. The
development
of
percep-
tion.
In J. H.
Flavell
& E.
Markman
(Eds.),
Cognitive
development.
In P. H.
Mussen
(Ed.),
Handbook
of
child
psychology
(Vol.
3). New
York: Wiley,
in
press.
Gibson,
J. J. The
senses considered
as
perceptual sys-
tems. Boston: Houghton
Mifflin,
1966.
Gibson,
J. J. The
ecological approach
to
visual
percep-
tion. Boston: Houghton
Mifflin,
1979.
Gilson,
M.,
Brown,
E.
C,
&
Daves,
W. F.
Sexual ori-
entation
as
measured
by
perceptual dominance
in
binocular rivalry. Personality
and
Social Psychology
Bulletin, 1982,
8,
494-500.
Gitter,
A. G.,
Black,
H.,
&
Mostofsky,
D.
Race
and sex
in
the
communication
of
emotion. Journal
of
Social
Psychology.
1972,
88,
273-276.
Goffman,
E. The
presentation
of
self
in
everyday
life.
Garden
City,
New
York:
Doublcday,
1959.
Goffman,
E.
Stigma: Notes
on the
management
of
spoiled
identity.
Englewood
Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963.
Goldiamond,
I.
Indicators
of
perception:
I.
Subliminal
perception, subception, unconscious perception:
An
analysis
in
terms
of
psychophysical
indicator meth-
odology.
Psychological
Bulletin,
1958,
55,
373-412.
Grayson,
B., &
Stein,
M. I.
Attracting assualt: Victims'
nonverbal
cues. Journal
of
Communication,
1981,
31,
68-75.
Guthrie,
R. E.
Evolution
of
human threat display organs.
In
T.
Dobzhansky,
M. K.
Hecht,
& W. C.
Steere
(Eds.),
Evolutionary
Biology (Vol.
4). New
York:
Appleton-
Century
Crofts, 1970.
Hamilton,
D. L., &
Gifford,
R. K.
Illusory correlation
in
interpersonal perception:
A
cognitive basis
of
ste-
reotypic
judgments. Journal
of
Experimental
Social
Psychology,
1976,
12,
392-407.
Hastorf,
A.
H.,
&
Myro,
G. The
effect
of
meaning
on
binocular
rivalry.
American Journal
of
Psychology,
1959,
72,
393-400.
Heider,
F. The
psychology
of
interpersonal
relations.
New
York:
Wiley,
1958.
Heider,
F.,
&
Simmel,
M. An
experimental study
of ap-
parent behavior. American
Journal
of
Psychology,
1944,
57,
243-259.
Henley,
N. M.
Body politics. Englewood
Cliffs,
N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, 1977.
Ittelson,
W. H.
Environment perception
and
contem-
porary
perceptual
theory.
In W. H.
Ittelson
(Ed.),
En-
vironment
and
cognition.
New
York: Seminar Press,
1973.
Johansson,
G.
Visual perception
of
biological motion
and a
model
for its
analysis. Perception
and
Psycho-
physics, 1973,
14,
201-211.
Kassin,
S.
M.,
Lowe,
C.
A.,
&
Gibbons,
F. X.
Children's
use
of the
discounting principle:
A
perceptual
ap-
proach. Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1980,39,
719-728.
Keating,
C.
F,
Mazur,
A.,
&
Segall,
M. H. A
cross-cul-
tural
exploration
of
physiognomic traits
of
dominance
and
happiness. Ethology
and
Sociobiologv,
1981,
2,
41-48.
Kelley,
H. H. The
warm-cold variable
in first
impres-
sions
of
persons.
Journal
of
Personality,
1950,
75,431-
439.
Knapp,
M. L.
Essentials
of
non-verbal communication.
New
York: Holt,
Rinehart,
&
Winston, 1980.
Koffka,
K.
Principles
of
gestalt
psychology.
New
York:
Harcourt
Brace, 1935.
Kozlowski,
L. T, &
Cutting,
J. E.
Recognizing
the sex
of a
walker
from
a
dynamic point-light display. Per-
ception
&
Psychophysics,
1917,21,
575-580.
Kramer,
E.
Judgment
of
personal
characteristics
and
emotions
from
non-verbal properties
of
speech.
Psy-
chological
Bulletin, 1963,
60,
408-420.
Krauss,
R. M.
Impression formation, impression man-
agement,
and
non-verbal
behaviors.
In E. T.
Higgins,
C. P.
Herman,
& M. P.
Zanna
(Eds.),
Social
cognition:
The
Ontario symposium (Vol.
1).
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erl-
baum,
1981.
Laird,
J.
D.,
Wagener,
J.
J.,
Halal,
M.,
&
Szegda,
M.
Remembering
what
you
feel.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1982,
42,
646-657.
Langer,
E.
J.,
&
Abelson,
R. P. A
patient
by any
other
name
. . .
clinician group difference
in
labeling bias.
Journal
of
Consulting
and
Clinical
Psychology,
1974,
42,
4-9.
Lanzetta,
J. X, &
Orr,
S. P.
Stimulus
properties
of
facial
expressions
and
their
influence
on the
classical con-
ditioning
of
fear.
Motivation
and
Emotion,
1981,
5,
225-234.
Lewin,
K.
Principles
of
topological
psychology.
McGraw-
Hill,
1936.
Lorenz,
K. Z. Die
angeborenen
Formen
Moglicher
Er-
fahrung.
Z
Tiernsychol.,
1943,
5,
235-409.
Cited
in
P.
H.
Mussen
(Ed.),
Carmichael's
manual
of
child
psychology
(Vol.
1).
New
York: John Wiley
and
Sons,
1970.
Marks,
L. E. The
unity
of
senses: Interrelations among
the
modalities. Academic Press:
New
York, 1978.
Massad,
C.
M.,
Hubbard,
M.,
&
Newtson,
D.
Selective
perception
of
events.
Journal
of
Experimental Social
Psychology,
1979,
15,
513-532.
McArthur,
L. Z.
Illusory causation
and
illusory corre-
lation:
Two
epistcmological accounts. Personality
and
Social
Psychology
Bulletin,
1980,6,
507-519.
McArthur,
L. Z.
What grabs you?
The
role
of
attention
in
impression formation
and
causal attribution.
In
E.
T.
Higgins,
C. P.
Herman,
& M. P.
Zanna
(Eds.),
Social cognition:
The
Ontario symposium (Vol.
1).
Hillsdale,
N.J.: Erlbaum, 1981.
McArthur,
L. Z.
Judging
a
book
by its
cover:
A
cognitive
analysis
of the
relationship between physical
appear-
ance
and
stereotyping.
In A.
Hastorf
& A.
Isen
(Eds.),
Cognitive social
psychology.
New
York: Elsevier, 1982.
McArthur,
L.
Z.,
&
Friedman,
S.
Illusory correlation
in
impression formation: Variations
in the
shared dis-
tinctiveness
effect
as a
function
of the
distinctive per-
son's
age, race,
and
sex. Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1980,
39,
615-624.
McArthur,
L.
Z.,
&
Ginsberg,
E.
Causal attribution
to
salient stimuli:
An
investigation
of
visual
fixation
mediators. Personality
and
Social
Psychology
Bulletin,
1981,
7,
547-553.
McArthur,
L.
Z.,
Solomon,
M.
R.,
&
Jaffe,
R. H.
Weight
differences
in
emotional responsiveness
to
proprio-
238
LESLIE
Z.
McARTHUR
AND
REUBEN
M.
BARON
ceptive
and
pictorial
stimuli. Journal
of
1'ersonalitv
and
Social
Psychology,
1980,
39,
308-319.
Michotte,
A. The
perception
of
causality.
New
York:
Ba-
sic
Books,
1963.
Mischel,
W.
Personality
and
assessment.
New
York:
Wiley,
1968.
Neisser,
U.
Cognition
and
reality.
San
Francisco: Freed-
man,
1976.
Newtson,
D.
Foundations
of
attribution:
The
perception
of
ongoing behavior.
In
J.
Harvey,
W. J.
Ickes,
&
R. F.
Kidd
(Eds.),
New
directions
in
attribution
re-
search
(Vol.
1).
Hillsdale,
N.J.: Erlbaum, 1976.
Newtson,
D.,
Rindner,
R.,
Miller,
R.,
&
LaCross,
K.
Effects
of
availability
of
feature changes
on
behavior
segmentation.
Journal
of
Experimental Social Psy-
chology,
1978,
14,
379-388.
Nisbett,
R.,
&
Ross,
L.
Human
inference:
Strategies
and
shortcomings
of
social
judgment.
Englewood
Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1980.
Ohman,
A.,
&
Dimberg,
U.
Facial expressions
as
con-
ditioned stimuli
for
electrodermal
responses:
A
case
of
preparedness?
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology.
1978,36,
1251-1258.
Orr,
S., &
Lanzetta,
J.
Facial expressions
of
emotion
as
conditioned stimuli
for
human autonomic
responses.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1980,
2,
278-282.
Postman,
L.,
Bruncr,
J.
S.,
&
McGinnics,
E.
Personal
values
as
selective
factors
in
perception.
Journal
of
Abnormal
and
Social
Psychology,
1948,
43,
142-154.
Rosenthal,
R.,
Hall,
J.
A.,
DiMatteo,
M.
R.,
Rogers,
P.
L.,
&
Archer,
D.
Sensitivity
to
nonverbal commu-
nication. Baltimore, Md.:
Johns
Hopkins University
Press, 1979.
Ross,
L. The
intuitive
psychologist
and his
shortcomings:
Distortions
in the
attribution
process.
In L.
Berkowitz
(Ed.),
Advances
in
experimental social
psychology
(\o\.
10).
New
York: Academic Press, 1977.
Rothbart,
M.,
Fulero,
S.,
Jensen,
C,
Howard,
J.,
&
Bir-
rell,
P.
From individual
to
group impressions:
Avail-
ability
heuristics
in
stereotype formation. Journal
of
Experimental Social
Psychology,
1978,
14,
237-255^
Runeson,
S.,
&
Frykholm,
G.
Visual
perception
of
lifted
weight.
Journal
of
Experimental
Psychology:
Human
Perception
and
Performance,
1981,
7,
733-740.
Runeson,
S.,
&
Frykholm,
G.
Kinematic specification
of
dynamics
as an
informational basis
for
person
and
action perception: Expectation, gender recognition,
and
deceptive intention.
Uppsala
Psychological
Re-
ports (No. 324).
Uppsala,
Sweden:
Department
of
Psychology,
University
of
Uppsala, 1982.
Sackett,
G. P.
Monkeys reared
in
isolation with pictures
as
visual input: Evidence
for an
innate releasing mech-
anism. Science, 1966, 154, 1468-1473.
Savitz,
L.,
&
Tomasson,
R. The
identifiability
of
Jewish
identity through appearance, gesture, voice. American
Journal
of
Sociology,
1959,
64,
468-475.
Scherer,
K. R.
Personality inference
from
voice quality:
The
loud voice
of
extroversion. European Journal
of
Social
Psychology,
1978,
8,
467-487.
Schneider,
D.
J.,
Hastorf,
A. H., &
Ellsworth,
P. C.
Person
perception.
Reading,
Mass.:
Addison-Wesley, 1979.
Secord,
P.
Facial features
and
inference processes
in in-
terpersonal perception.
In R.
Tagiuri
& L.
Petrullo
(Eds.),
Person perception
and
interpersonal behavior.
Stanford,
Calif: Stanford University Press,
1958.
Secord,
P. F,
Dukes,
W.
F.,
&
Bevan,
W.
Personalities
in
faces:
I. An
experiment
in
social perceiving. Genetic
Psychology
Monographs, 1954,
49,
231-279.
Secord,
P.
F.,
&
Muthard,
J. E.
Personalities
in
faces:
IV.
A
descriptive analysis
of the
perception
of
women's
faces
and the
identification
of
physiognomic
deter-
minants.
Journal
of
Psychology,
1955,
39,
269-278.
Segall,
M.
H.,
Campbell,
D.
T,
&
Herskovitz,
M. J. The
influence
of
culture
on
visual
perception.
Indianapolis,
Ind.:
Bobbs-Merrill,
1966.
Shaw,
R.,
&
Bransford,
J.
Introduction: Psychological
approaches
to the
problem
of
knowledge.
In R.
Shaw
& J.
Bransford
(Eds.),
Perceiving, acting,
and
knowing:
Toward
an
ecological
psychology.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erl-
baum, 1977.
Shaw,
R.,
&
Pittenger,
J.
Perceiving
the
face
of
change
in
changing faces:
Implications
for a
theory
of
object
perception.
In R.
Shaw
& J.
Bransford,
(Eds.),
Per-
ceiving,
acting,
and
knowing:
Toward
an
ecological
psychology.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1977.
Shaw,
R.,
Turvey,
M.,
&
Mace,
W.
Ecological psychology:
The
consequences
of a
commitment
to
realism.
In W.
Weimer
and D.
Palermo
(Eds.),
Cognition
and
sym-
bolic
processes (Vol.
2).
Hillsdale,
N.J.: Erlbaum,
1982.
Snyder,
M.,
&
Frankel,
A.
Observer bias:
A
stringent test
of
behavior
engulfing
the field.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology,
1976,
34,
857-864.
Snyder,
M.,
Tanke,
E.
D.,
&
Berscheid,
E.
Social per-
ception
and
interpersonal behavior:
On the
self-ful-
filling
nature
of
social
stereotypes.
Journal
of
Person-
ality
and
Social
Psychology,
1977,
35,
656-666.
Taylor,
S.
E.,
&
Fiske,
S. T.
Salience, attention,
and at-
tribution:
Top of the
head phenomena.
In L.
Berko-
witz
(Ed.),
Advances
in
experimental
social
psychology
(Vol.
11).
New
York: Academic
Press,
1978.
Toch,
H.
H.,
&
Schulte,
R.
Readiness
to
perceive vio-
lence
as a
result
of
police training. British Journal
of
Psychology,
1961,
52,
389-393.
Todd,
J. T,
Mark,
L.,
Shaw,
R.,
&
Pittenger,
J. The
per-
ception
of
growth. Scientific American, 1980, 242,
132-144.
Turvey,
M. T.
Preliminaries
to a
theory
of
action with
reference
to
vision.
In R.
Shaw
& 3.
Bransford
(Eds.),
Perceiving,
acting,
and
knowing. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erl-
baum, 1977.
Woll,
S. B., &
Martinez,
J. M. The
effects
of
biasing
labels
on
recognition
of
facial
expressions
of
emotion.
Social cognition, 1982,
/,
70-82.
Zuckerman,
M.,
DePaulo,
B.
M.,
&
Rosenthal,
R.
Verbal
and
nonverbal communication
of
deception.
In L.
Berkowitz
(Ed.),
Advances
in
experimental
social psy-
chology
(Vol. 14).
New
York: Academic Press,
1981.
Received
September
1,
1982
Revision
received
February
19,
1983