Florida State University College of Law Florida State University College of Law
Scholarship Repository Scholarship Repository
Scholarly Publications
2-2016
The New Elections Clause The New Elections Clause
Michael T. Morley
Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/articles
Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Election Law Commons
79
ESSAYS
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
Michael T. Morley*
I
NTRODUCTION ............................................................................................ 79
I.
ARIZONA INDEPENDENT REDISTRICTING COMMISSION ............................ 83
A. Breadth of the Ruling ................................................................. 83
B. Competing Theories of Constitutional Interpretation ................ 87
C. A New Political Theory ............................................................. 90
II.
COLLATERAL IMPACT ON FEDERAL ELECTION LAW ........................... 92
A. Non-Delegation Doctrine ........................................................... 93
B. Independent State Legislature Doctrine ..................................... 94
C. Reallocating Presidential Electors .............................................. 96
III.
REMAINING QUESTIONS...................................................................... 98
A. Strict Statutory Construction and the Democracy Canon .......... 99
B. Federal Regulation of Presidential Elections ........................... 100
C. Commandeering and Federal Election Law ............................. 101
D. Limits on State Authority ......................................................... 103
C
ONCLUSION .............................................................................................. 104
I
NTRODUCTION
The Elections Clause
1
and Presidential Electors Clause
2
are the
constitutional sources of states’ authority to regulate federal elections.
3
© 2016 Michael T. Morley. Individuals and nonprofit institutions may reproduce and
distribute copies of this Essay in any format, at or below cost, for educational purposes, so
long as each copy identifies the author, provides a citation to the Notre Dame Law Review
Online, and includes this provision in the copyright notice.
* Assistant Professor, Barry University School of Law. Climenko Fellow and
Lecturer on Law, Harvard Law School, 201214; J.D., Yale Law School, 2003; A.B.,
Princeton University, 2000. I am grateful for feedback from John Koza and Franita Tolson.
This Essay was funded with a generous research grant from Dean Leticia Diaz of the Barry
University School of Law.
1 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1 (The Times, Places and Manner of holding Elections
for Senators and Representatives, shall be prescribed in each State by the Legislature
thereof; but the Congress may at any time by Law make or alter such Regulations . . . .”).
80
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
The “Swiss army kni[ves]” of federal election law, they also have been
interpreted as creating special doctrines in a surprisingly broad range of
fields such as statutory interpretation, preemption, and separation of powers
in state government, as they relate to federal elections.
4
The Supreme Court’s recent ruling in Arizona State Legislature v.
Arizona Independent Redistricting Commission (AIRC)
5
presents a bold
new interpretation of the Elections Clause that will reverberate far beyond
the issue immediately before the Court. Although the Elections Clause
confers power specifically on the “Legislature” of each state to regulate
congressional elections, the Supreme Court held that states may enact
election laws through any of their “lawmaking processes,” including public
initiatives and referenda.
6
Moreover, a state may completely prohibit its
institutional legislature from regulating certain aspects of congressional
elections by conferring that authority on some other entity instead.
7
Applying these holdings, the Court affirmed the validity of a state
constitutional amendment in Arizona, enacted through a public initiative,
which transferred authority to draw congressional districts from the state
legislature to an independent redistricting commission.
8
Most commentary concerning the Court’s ruling focuses on its
immediate impact of approving the use of independent redistricting
commissions,
9
as seven states have adopted.
10
This Essay contends that
AIRC is a dramatic expansion of precedent based on sweeping reasoning
that reshapes Elections Clause doctrine in largely unrecognized ways
2 Id. art. II, § 1, cl. 2 (Each State shall appoint, in such Manner as the Legislature
thereof may direct, a Number of Electors [to select the President] . . . .”).
3 Cook v. Gralike, 531 U.S. 510, 523 (2001); Bush v. Palm Beach Cty. Canvassing
Bd., 531 U.S. 70, 76 (2000) (per curiam).
4 Michael T. Morley, The Intratextual Independent Legislatureand the Elections
Clause, 109 N
W. U. L. REV. 847, 84849 (2015).
5 135 S. Ct. 2652 (2015).
6 Id. at 2677.
7 Id. at 2671 ([T]he people [of a state] may delegate their legislative authority over
redistricting to an independent commission just as the representative body may choose to
do.) (citing Transcript of Oral Argument at 1516, AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652 (2015) (No. 13-
1314)).
8 Id. (affirming Arizonas power to creat[e] a commission operating independently
of the state legislature to establish congressional districts).
9 See, e.g., Lyle Denniston, Opinion Analysis: A Cure for Partisan
Gerrymandering?, S
COTUSBLOG (June 29, 2015, 3:21 PM),
http://www.scotusblog.com/2015/06/opinion-analysis-a-cure-for-partisan-gerrymandering/;
Edward B. Foley, The Constitution Needed a Judicial Assist, O
HIO STATE UNIV.: ELECTION
L. AT MORITZ (June 29, 2015, 2:32 PM), http://moritzlaw.osu.edu/election-
law/article/?article=13151.
10 Redistricting Commissions: Congressional Plans, NATL CONFERENCE OF STATE
LEGISLATURES (Dec. 8, 2015), http://www.ncsl.org/research/redistricting/redistricting-
commissions-congressional-plans.aspx.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
81
across a range of other fields. This Essay offers a critical analysis of the
“new” Elections Clause and its Article II analogue, the Presidential
Electors Clause, as they remain in the wake of this tumultuous ruling.
Part I begins by analyzing the AIRC ruling itself. Rather than
interpreting the Elections Clause’s language, the Court attempted to
implement what it perceived to be the provision’s purpose: facilitating fair
congressional elections. This Part argues that the majority opinion is best
seen as a legal process interpretation,
11
but may also be viewed as a failed
application of John Hart Ely’s representation-reinforcing approach.
12
While the majority opinion is consistent with academic and popular
opinion concerning redistricting commissions, it was inappropriate given
the concrete, specific nature of the term being interpreted (“Legislature”),
and is fundamentally at odds with the political theory underlying the
Constitution.
The majority sought to further what it believed to be the Elections
Clause’s purpose by allowing states to insulate and protect the electoral
process from politicians. The Framers, however, believed that the political
branches themselves are the most important and reliable defenders of
democracy; they deliberately and repeatedly chose to entrust most critical
aspects of the electoral process to elected officials. The majority’s
approach could have significant implications in future cases involving
clashes between the political branches and judiciary over the power to
resolve election disputes and enforce the right to vote.
Part II turns to AIRC’s impact on Elections Clause and Presidential
Electors Clause jurisprudence. Most basically, the ruling allows states to
completely and permanently exclude their institutional legislatures from
regulating congressionaland, by extension, presidentialelections,
subject to no apparent limiting principle. The ruling also largely settles the
issue of delegations under those provisions. It clarifies that, although the
Elections Clause confers power to craft rules governing congressional
elections specifically on the “Legislature” of each state, this power may be
delegated to executive or administrative entities. It leaves undisturbed the
Court’s previous holding that the Elections Clause authorizes federal
preemption of state laws concerning congressional elections, independent
of the Supremacy Clause, without triggering a presumption against
preemption.
13
11 See generally HENRY M. HART, JR. & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS:
BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW (William N. Eskridge, Jr. &
Philip P. Frickey eds., 1994) (providing the definitive account of the legal process school of
thought).
12 See generally JOHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST (1980) (explaining
theory).
13 Arizona v. Inter Tribal Council of Ariz., Inc., 133 S. Ct. 2247, 225354 (2013).
82
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
Another likely consequence of the Court’s ruling is that, since the
Presidential Electors Clause will probably be construed in pari materia
with the Elections Clause, members of the public will be able to use public
initiatives to reallocate their states’ electoral votes in presidential elections
on a proportional or district-by-district basis, rather than through the
prevailing winner-take-all system. Thus, while AIRC is a congressional
redistricting case, it could dramatically reshape the landscape of
presidential politics by putting substantial numbers of electoral votes from
traditionally partisan strongholds such as California and Michigan in play.
Finally, and perhaps most significantly, the ruling summarily and
unnecessarily rejects the “independent state legislature doctrine.” The
doctrine provides that, when a legislature enacts a law regulating federal
elections under the Elections Clause or Presidential Electors Clause, it is
acting under a higher source of power “independent” of the state
constitution, and therefore is not subject to substantive state constitutional
constraints. Repudiating this doctrine, the Court declared that state laws
relating to federal elections are subject to both state and federal
constitutional restrictions, thereby facilitating challenges to provisions such
as voter ID laws.
Part III surveys the remaining questions concerning the Elections
Clause and Presidential Electors Clause that AIRC leaves open. Perhaps
the most salient issue is the extent to which these provisions implicitly
create a special canon of statutory interpretation for state laws governing
federal elections. Several courts and commentators have suggested that,
since these clauses confer authority specifically on state legislatures, rather
than states as entities, courts must be particularly deferential to the plain
meaning of laws enacted under them. Courts may not exercise the same
interpretive discretion over state laws governing federal elections as they
may possess in other contexts.
14
Although this “super-strong” plain
meaning approach has been criticized,
15
it is a fair and fundamentally
important principle that limits courts’ ability to “interpret” the law, after the
results of an election are known and a concrete dispute has arisen, to
achieve their preferred electoral outcomes.
As the Court’s ruling focused primarily on separation of powers at the
state level, it also leaves unaddressed some federalism-related issues.
Because the Presidential Electors Clause does not expressly authorize
Congress to legislate concerning presidential elections, it remains possible
that federal authority in that area is more limited than with congressional
elections. It is also unclear whether Printz v. United States’s constraints on
14 See, e.g., Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 11213 (2000) (Rehnquist, C.J., concurring)
(concluding that, because the Constitution delegates plenary authority over presidential
elections to state legislatures, the text of [an] election law itself . . . takes on independent
significance”).
15 See Richard L. Hasen, The Democracy Canon, 62 STAN. L. REV. 69 (2009).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
83
commandeering limit Congress’s power to direct state and local officials in
their conduct of federal (or state) elections.
16
Finally, the Court has held
that the Elections Clause implicitly prohibits states from enacting laws
designed to benefit or hinder certain candidates.
17
The Court has yet to
fully flesh out the scope of this important limit on states’ authority over
federal elections.
The Elections Clause and Presidential Electors Clause are the sources
of a wide range of constitutional doctrines concerning federal elections.
While AIRC, on its face, addresses only the meaning of “Legislature” in the
Elections Clause and the validity of redistricting commissions, the Court’s
broad reasoning sweeps much further. This Essay offers a first analysis of
the “new” Elections Clause in the wake of this ruling.
I.
ARIZONA INDEPENDENT REDISTRICTING COMMISSION
In AIRC, the Court adopted a sweeping interpretation of the Elections
Clause, despite other available lines of reasoning that would have permitted
it to reach comparable conclusions on narrower grounds. Section A
discusses the breadth of the ruling, demonstrating that the Court adopted a
particularly far-reaching interpretation of the Elections Clause. Section B
explains that the Court’s approach is best understood as a legal process
interpretation of the clause, which was a particularly questionable approach
given the nature of that provision. Finally, Section C shows that the
political theory underlying the Court’s ruling is fundamentally at odds with
that which permeates the Constitution.
A. Breadth of the Ruling
The Elections Clause provides, “The Times, Places and Manner of
holding Elections for Senators and Representatives, shall be prescribed in
each State by the Legislature thereof; but the Congress may at any time by
Law make or alter such Regulations.”
18
The people of Arizona enacted an
initiative amending their state constitution to transfer authority to determine
congressional district boundaries from the institutional legislature to a
16 521 U.S. 898, 935 (1997).
17 U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U.S. 779, 83334 (1995) ([T]he Framers
understood the Elections Clause as a grant of authority to issue procedural regulations, and
not as a source of power to dictate electoral outcomes, to favor or disfavor a class of
candidates, or to evade important constitutional restraints.”); see, e.g., Cook v. Gralike, 531
U.S. 510, 524 (2001) (holding that the Elections Clause did not authorize a state to enact a
law plainly designed to favor candidates who are willing to support the particular form of a
term limits amendment set forth in its text and to disfavor those who either oppose term
limits entirely or would prefer a different proposal”).
18 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1 (emphasis added).
84
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
bipartisan commission.
19
The amendment raised two serious questions
under the Elections Clause. First, from a purely procedural perspective, the
Elections Clause permits only the “Legislature” to enact laws regulating
federal elections. The redistricting commission, however, was created by a
constitutional amendment that was directly enacted by the people of the
state through a public initiative, rather than the legislature. Second,
substantively, putting aside the manner in which the amendment was
enacted, it strips the legislature of its authority to craft congressional
districts and vests that power instead in an independent commission. The
appellant,
20
the Arizona state legislature, challenged the amendment solely
on substantive grounds, foregoing any procedural arguments.
21
The
Court’s ruling, however, swept aside objections of either type.
Even if the Court did not wish to adopt the appellant’s
22
and
dissent’s
23
position that independent redistricting commissions are
categorically unconstitutional, it could have reached any number of
moderate or compromise rulings. For example, it could have held that,
although the Elections Clause confers authority to regulate federal elections
specifically on institutional state legislatures, the legislature may delegate
that power to other entities, such as independent commissions. This
approach would have validated the procedural objection to Arizona’s
commission, since Arizona’s institutional legislature was not involved in
the creation of the state’s redistricting commission, while rejecting the
substantive one.
From a policy perspective, it might be objected that legislatures would
refuse to voluntarily relinquish their power over redistricting. Four of the
seven current congressional redistricting commissions, however, were
established by state legislatures and subsequently ratified by voters.
24
A
fifth stemmed directly from a constitutional convention.
25
Only two
congressional redistricting commissions were created through public
19 ARIZ. CONST. art. IV, pt. 2, § 1.
20 The case was an appeal from a three-judge panel of the U.S. District Court for the
District of Arizona directly to the U.S. Supreme Court. AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652, 2662
(2015); see 28 U.S.C. § 2284(a) (2012).
21 Brief for Appellant at 24, 36, AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652 (2015) (No. 13-1314).
22 Id.; see also Morley, supra note 4 (presenting intratextual argument against validity
of the Arizona commission).
23 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2678 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting).
24 See Act of Nov. 7, 1995, 206th Leg., Second Ann. Sess., 1995 N.J. Laws 2510
(codified at N.J.
CONST. art. IV, § 3); S.J. Res. 105, 52nd Leg., First Reg. Sess., 1993 Idaho
Sess. Laws 1530 (codified at I
DAHO CONST. art. III, § 2); H.B. 2322, 16th Leg., Reg. Sess.,
1992 Hawaii Sess. Laws 1029 (codified at H
AW. CONST. art. IV, § 2); S.J. Res. 103, 48th
Leg., Reg. Sess., 1983 Wash. Sess. Laws 2202 (codified at W
ASH. CONST. art. II, § 43).
25 See MONT. CONST., art. V, § 14(2).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
85
initiatives.
26
Interpreting the Elections Clause as referring exclusively to
institutional legislatures therefore would have preserved the majority of
commissions that presently exist and realistically left the door open to the
creation of others.
Alternatively, the Court could have modified its holding by declaring
that, while the term “Legislature” refers to any entity or process to which a
state constitution commits “legislative authority,
27
a state is not free to
exclude its “actual” institutional legislature from that definition. In other
words, the Court could have interpreted “Legislature” to refer to the
institutional legislature, as well as any other processes or entities through
which the state constitution allows election laws or redistricting plans to be
adopted (including either public initiative or approval by a redistricting
commission). This view would have been consistent with the Court’s
Elections Clause precedents, which upheld the use of public referenda
28
and gubernatorial vetoes
29
without categorically excluding institutional
legislatures from regulating any aspect of federal elections.
Such reasoning would have led the Court to reject the procedural
objection to the Arizona commission, because state laws concerning federal
elections may be enacted through public initiative. It would have upheld
the substantive challenge, however, because the state constitutional
amendment completely excluded the institutional legislature from
participating in redistricting. The Court might have felt that this
interpretation still would have allowed the institutional legislature to
maintain too much control over the redistricting process and other aspects
of federal elections. Such concerns could have been alleviated, however,
by state constitutional provisions limiting a legislature’s ability to override
or nullify the outcome of a public initiative
30
or determination of a
redistricting commission.
26 See Proposition 20, CAL. SECY OF STATE (Nov. 2010) (codified at CAL. CONST. art.
XXI), http://vig.cdn.sos.ca.gov/2010/general/pdf/english/text-proposed-laws.pdf#prop20;
Proposition 106, A
RIZ. SECY OF STATE (Sept. 2000) (codified at ARIZ. CONST. art. IV, pt. 2,
§ 1), http://apps.azsos.gov/election/2000/Info/pubpamphlet/english/prop106.pdf.
27 See AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2668 n.17, 2671.
28 Ohio ex rel. Davis v. Hildebrant, 241 U.S. 565, 569 (1916).
29 Smiley v. Holm, 285 U.S. 355, 36566 (1932).
30 Indeed, state constitutional provisions authorizing initiatives already contain such
restrictions. See, e.g., A
RIZ. CONST. art. IV, pt. 1, § 1(6)(B)(C) (prohibiting the legislature
from repeal[ing] an initiative measure approved by a majority of the votes cast thereon,
and requiring a three-fourths vote of the legislature to amend a measure adopted by
initiative); C
AL. CONST. art. II, § 10(c) ([The Legislature] may amend or repeal an initiative
statute by another statute that becomes effective only when approved by the electors unless
the initiative statute permits amendment or repeal without their approval.”); cf. A
RK. CONST.
art. V, § 1 (requiring a two-thirds vote to amend or repeal any measure adopted by
initiative).
86
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
Finally, the Court also could have adopted a broad reading of
“Legislature,” as referring to any entity or process through which a state’s
lawmaking authority is exercised, while holding that the Elections Clause
implicitly prohibits delegation of that power. Thus, while the Elections
Clause allows the people of a state to adopt a redistricting plan via public
initiativewhich is one of the state’s lawmaking processesthey could
not permit an independent commission to do so. By way of comparison,
the Constitution, as originally enacted, empowered state legislatures to
appoint U.S. Senators;
31
it likely would have been unconstitutional for a
legislature to transfer that authority to an executive agency or independent
commission.
32
This interpretation would have been bolstered by the fact that, unlike
other constitutional provisions which refer to states as overall entities, the
Elections Clause specifically confers responsibility for regulating federal
elections on state legislatures in particular. Such a direct delegation to a
particular branch of state government reasonably could be construed as
implicitly prohibiting that branch from delegating that power to some other
entity. The AIRC Court summarily rejected this possibility, based solely on
a concession from appellant’s counsel.
33
Rather than any of these narrower, compromise possibilities, the Court
instead adopted a sweepingly broad interpretation of the Elections Clause
that went far beyond precedent. At most,
34
Ohio ex rel. Davis v.
Hildebrant authorized a state’s voters to enact measures concerning federal
elections through legislative channels in addition to the state legislature,
such as public initiatives or referenda.
35
And Smiley v. Holm clarified that,
when such laws are enacted by the institutional legislature, they remain
subject to gubernatorial veto.
36
Neither of those cases compels the
31 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 3, cl. 1.
32 See, e.g., State ex rel. Van Alstine v. Frear, 125 N.W. 961, 971 (Wis. 1910)
(rejecting preSeventeenth Amendment challenge to non-binding public referendum on U.S.
Senate candidates, because legislators retained their power and obligation to exercise their
conscientious judgmentson the issue); State ex rel. McCue v. Blaisdell, 118 N.W. 141, 147
(N.D. 1908) (same, because [t]he Legislature still elects the senator, and the act merely
gives the voters of each party an opportunity to express their choice of candidates). See
generally Derek T. Muller, Legislative Delegations and the Elections Clause, F
LA. ST. U. L.
REV. (forthcoming) (manuscript at 5–8), http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract_id=2650432.
33 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2671 ([T]he people may delegate their legislative authority
over redistricting to an independent commission just as the representative body may choose
to do.) (citing Transcript of Oral Argument at 1516, AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652 (2015) (No.
13-1314)).
34 I have argued elsewhere that the Hildebrant Court actually did not reach the merits
of the petitioners Elections Clause claim, construing it instead as a non-justiciable
Guarantee Clause argument. Morley, supra note 4, at 861.
35 241 U.S. 565, 569 (1916).
36 285 U.S. 355, 36566 (1932).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
87
conclusion that the Elections Clause permits a state’s voters to completely
exclude an institutional legislature from regulating any aspects of federal
elections.
37
Importantly, the Court’s ruling contains no limiting principle.
Nothing in the opinion turned on the fact that the commission was
empowered to determine congressional district boundaries, as opposed to
regulating other aspects of federal elections. Since the Court repeatedly
denied that the Elections Clause’s reference to “Legislature” refers to the
institutional legislature,
38
it does not appear there is any core nucleus of
authority over federal elections that a state’s actual legislature must retain.
To the contrary, under the Court’s reasoning, the people of a state may
completely exclude their institutional legislature from regulating all aspects
of federal elections, delegating that authority instead to the Secretary of
State, an executive agency, or an independent commission, among other
possibilities. This is an extremely odd and unsatisfying interpretation of a
constitutional provision expressly specifying that “[t]he Times, Places and
Manner of holding Elections for Senators and Representatives, shall be
prescribed in each State by the Legislature thereof.”
39
In the Court’s view,
this clause effectively means “The Constitution of a State may prohibit the
Legislature from prescribing the Times, Places and Manner of holding
Elections for Senators and Representatives.”
B. Competing Theories of Constitutional Interpretation
The majority opinion and principal dissent in AIRC dramatically
illustrate diametrically opposed theories of constitutional interpretation.
The dissent relies on textualism, by focusing on the meaning of the word
“Legislature” as used in the Elections Clause;
40
intratextualism, by
considering how other clauses in the Constitution use that term;
41
and
original understanding.
42
While the majority makes a desultory attempt at
37 Cf. AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2671 ([T]he Elections Clause permits the people of
Arizona to provide for redistricting by . . . a commission operating independently of the
state legislature . . . .”).
38 See id. at 267175.
39 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1.
40 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2679 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting) (explaining that Founding Era
dictionaries demonstrate that “‘the Legislature referred to an institutional body of
representatives, not the people at large”).
41 Id. at 268083 (The unambiguous meaning of the Legislaturein the Elections
Clause as a representative body is confirmed by other provisions of the Constitution that use
the same term in the same way.”); see also Morley, supra note 4 (setting forth a detailed
intratextual analysis of the Elections Clause). See generally Akhil Reed Amar,
Intratextualism, 112 H
ARV. L. REV. 747 (1999) (explaining intratextualism).
42 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2684 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting) (The history of the Elections
Clause further supports the conclusion that the Legislatureis a representative body.”).
88
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
demonstrating that the term “Legislature” actually refers to something other
than a state’s institutional legislature,
43
most of the opinion provides a non-
interpretivist, legal process interpretation of the Elections Clause.
The leading theorists of the legal process school, Henry M. Hart, Jr.
and Albert M. Sacks, presented their theory solely as one of statutory
interpretation, but prominent commentators have gone on to apply it to
constitutional law, as well.
44
Hart and Sacks contend that, when construing
a legal text, “[t]he first task . . . is to determine what purpose ought to be
attributed to it.”
45
They explain that legal enactments “ought always to be
presumed to be the work of reasonable men pursuing reasonable purposes
reasonably.”
46
When a law’s actual purpose is unclear, a court may attempt
to reconstruct what the purpose of a reasonable legislator would have
been.
47
Thus, to apply a statutory or constitutional provision under the
legal process approach, a court must seek to implement its underlying
purpose, whether actual or constructive.
The AIRC majority believed that “[t]he dominant purpose of the
Elections Clause . . . was to empower Congress to override state election
rules, not to restrict the way States enact legislation.”
48
It was intended to
ensure that state officials did not attempt to manipulate the outcomes of
federal elections.
49
Particularly since “the initiative and the referendum . . .
were not yet in our democracy’s arsenal” when the Elections Clause was
drafted, its reference to “Legislatures” could not have been intended to
prevent states’ electorates from regulating federal elections through such
means.
50
The legal process school also stresses institutional competence. Each
organ of government has its own structure and processes, and therefore is
uniquely competent to handle certain kinds of issues.
51
Consistent with this
insight, the AIRC majority extolled the importance of independent
43 Id. at 2671 (discussing the definition of Legislature in Founding Era
dictionaries).
44 William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey, The Making of The Legal Process,
107 H
ARV. L. REV. 2031, 2052 (1994).
45 HART & SACKS, supra note 11, at 1125 (emphasis removed); see also id. at 1374
(advocating that courts should [i]nterpret the words of the statute immediately in question
so as to carry out the purpose as best it can”).
46 Id. at 1125.
47 See id. at 1374, 1378.
48 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2672.
49 Id.
50 Id.
51 HART & SACKS, supra note 11, at 4 (“[D]ifferent procedures and personnel of
different qualifications invariably prove to be appropriate for deciding different kinds of
questions.”); see also id. at 160.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
89
commissions in combatting political gerrymandering by legislatures.
52
The
Court strained to construe the Elections Clause so as to allow states to
assign responsibility for redistricting to what the Court perceived to be the
most appropriate institution for the task. Had the majority shared the Chief
Justice’s doubts about redistricting commissions,
53
it might have adopted a
less aggressive interpretation of the Elections Clause.
The Court’s reasoning is vulnerable to the standard objections to legal
process interpretations. Legal process theory treats the legislative
process—and, by extension, the constitutional drafting processas
fundamentally rational. Public choice theory convincingly demonstrates,
however, that deliberations of lawmaking bodies are chaotic, path-
dependent, and fraught with tradeoffs, negotiations, and compromises.
54
By attempting to further the purpose underlying a legal provision, rather
than enforcing its plain meaning, a court is implementing a rule that has not
actually survived the bicameral legislative process or constitutional
ratification process. As Professor John F. Manning notes,
[i]f the Court feels free to adjust the semantic meaning of [a legal
provision] when the rules embedded in the text seem awkward in
relation to the [provision’s] apparent goals, then legislators cannot
reliably use words to articulate the boundaries of the frequently
awkward compromises that are necessary to secure a [measure’s]
enactment.
55
The work of John Hart Elywho was by no means a strict
textualistsuggests another, more targeted objection. He argued that
courts cannot interpret certain provisions of the Constitution, such as
“privileges and immunities” and “equal protection,” based solely on their
plain text, because the language is too vague.
56
His representation
reinforcement theory counsels courts to construe such broad phrases in a
manner that will keep open the “channels of political change” and protect
“discrete and insular minorities” from oppression.
57
The AIRC majority
52 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2677 (explaining that Arizonas voters sought to restore the
core principle of republican government’” by turn[ing] to the initiative to curb the practice
of gerrymandering(quoting Mitchell N. Berman, Managing Gerrymandering, 83 T
EX. L.
REV. 781 (2005))); see also id. at 2676 (emphasizing that independent commissions have
succeeded to a great degreein combatting political conflicts of interest (quoting Bruce E.
Cain, Redistricting Commissions: A Better Political Buffer?, 121 YALE L.J. 1808, 1808
(2012))).
53 Id. at 2691 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting) (discussing the partisanship that has
infected Arizonas commission).
54 Frank H. Easterbrook, StatutesDomains, 50 U. CHI. L. REV. 533, 547 (1983); see
also William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism, 37 UCLA L. R
EV. 621, 64044 (1990).
55 John F. Manning, What Divides Textualists from Purposivists?, 106 COLUM. L.
REV. 70, 111 (2006).
56 ELY, supra note 12, at 1114.
57 Id. at 103 & n.97.
90
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
likely would enthusiastically agree that its opinion adopts a representation-
reinforcing approach, because its whole purpose is to allow states to take
steps to prevent politicians from drawing congressional district lines on a
partisan basis, for the benefit of entrenched incumbents.
58
Even apart from the Chief Justice’s empirical concerns about the
impartiality and fairness of purportedly independent commissions,
59
the
majority opinion fails as an attempt at representation reinforcement for one
fundamental reason: the term “Legislature” is not the type of broad
provision embodying general principles that calls for some outside moral or
political theory to meaningfully implement.
60
It is a concrete term, used
repeatedly throughout the Constitution itself, most state constitutions
during the Founding Era, and the constitutional convention. The nature and
context of these references demonstrate that it refers to a specific entity
within each state: a body comprised of elected representatives with general,
statewide lawmaking authority that periodically convenes.
61
C. A New Political Theory
The most significant impact of the majority’s approach is that it
wholeheartedly embraces a political theory concerning the electoral process
that is fundamentally at odds with the one underlying the Constitution
itself. Whether viewed from a legal process or representation-reinforcing
perspective,
62
the majority opinion rests on the view that legislatures
cannot be trusted with redistricting authority, because they have structural
incentives to succumb to the temptation of political gerrymandering.
63
Indeed, the majority goes so far as to completely ignore the U.S. House of
Representatives’s interpretation of the Elections Clause in resolving an
election contest, dismissing it as a largely party-lines vote.
64
The Framers, however, were of a very different view. They believed
that Congress was the only entity that could be “trusted” with control over
58 See supra notes 48–49 and accompanying text.
59 See supra note 53.
60 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652, 268990 (2015) (Roberts, C.J., dissenting).
61 Morley, supra note 4.
62 See supra Section I.B.
63 See supra note 52.
64 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. at 2674 (declaring that the Houses interpretation of the Elections
Clause in Baldwin v. Trowbridge, 2 Bartlett Contested Election Cases, H.R. Misc. Doc. No.
152, 41st Cong., 2d Sess., 4647 (1866), is not a disposition that should attract this Courts
reliance). The majority did not acknowledge the numerous other authorities that agreed
with the Houses conclusion that the Elections Clause confers powers specifically on
institutional state legislatures. See Michael T. Morley, Rethinking the Right to Vote Under
State Constitutions, 67 V
AND. L. REV. EN BANC 189, 198202 (2014) (citing cases).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
91
the electoral process.
65
Justice Story explains that lodging authority over
congressional elections in any entity other than Congress itself would
undermine “its independence, its purity, and even its existence.”
66
By
granting Congress power over congressional elections, the “major evil of
interference by other branches of government is entirely avoided, while a
substantial degree of responsibility is still provided by regular elections, the
interim demands of public opinion, and the desire of each House to
preserve its standing in relation to the other institutions of government.”
67
Even aside from Congress’s authority to make rules concerning
congressional elections under the Elections Clause,
68
each House of
Congress has sole authority to determine the elections and returns of its
members
69
and to effectively nullify the outcomes of elections by expelling
members.
70
Congress is likewise responsible for determining the outcome
of presidential elections. The House and Senate have power to count
electoral votes,
71
including the authority to reject votes they deem invalid.
72
In the event that a candidate for President or Vice President fails to receive
a majority of electoral votes, as determined by Congress, then the House or
Senate, respectively, determine the winner of that office.
73
The House also
has the power to impeach federal officers,
74
and the Senate is responsible
for trying all impeachments.
75
Allowing Congress to control and even determine the outcomes of
federal elections creates a substantial risk of direct partisan manipulation.
Yet the Constitution’s structure embodies the Framers’ repeated, deliberate
decisions to entrust Congress with such responsibility. Although the
Court’s skepticism of allowing the political branches to control the
65 1 JAMES KENT, COMMENTARIES ON AMERICAN LAW 220 (Legal Classics Library
1986) (1826); cf. W
ILLIAM RAWLE, A VIEW OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 47
(photo. reprint 2003) (2d ed. 1829) (discussing the need of legislative bodies to be able to
defend themselves from encroachments and interference).
66 2 JOSEPH STORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES
§ 831, at 295 (Bos., Hilliard, Gray & Co. 1833).
67 Morgan v. United States, 801 F.2d 445, 450 (D.C. Cir. 1986).
68 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1.
69 Id. art. I, § 5, cl. 1; see, e.g., Morgan, 801 F.2d at 450; McIntyre v. Fallahay, 766
F.2d 1078 (7th Cir. 1985).
70 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 5, cl. 2.
71 Id. amend. XII.
72 3 U.S.C. § 15 (2012) (allowing Members of Congress to object to the counting of
particular electoral votes).
73 U.S. CONST. amend. XII.
74 Id. art. I, § 2, cl. 5.
75 Id. art. I, § 3, cl. 6.
92
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
electoral process has a valid basis and is widely shared,
76
it runs contrary to
the political theory embedded in the Constitution itself.
The Court’s willingness to reinterpret even a clear and concrete
provision such as the Elections Clause in light of its skepticism about the
political branches’ ability to fairly handle election-related issues raises
questions over the extent to which the Court will defer to Congress’s
resolution of disputes that more directly impact the right to vote. The same
fairness concerns that led the Court to permit entities other than a state’s
institutional legislature to redraw congressional districts might similarly
motivate it to permit entities other than the respective Houses of Congress
to determine which congressional candidates should be seated or which
electoral votes should be counted. Thus, the theory underlying AIRC sets
the stage for greater judicial enforcement of the constitutional right to vote
and a potential clash with Congress over the scope of its constitutional
prerogatives.
II.
COLLATERAL IMPACT ON FEDERAL ELECTION LAW
Although AIRC’s most immediate consequence is to establish the
constitutionality of redistricting commissions, the Court’s ruling also
impacts Elections Clause jurisprudence in a variety of other, potentially
further-reaching ways. Section A explains that a state legislature—defined
broadly as including any process or entity that a state constitution
authorizes to exercise legislative authoritymay delegate power over
federal elections to other organs of government. Section B discusses the
Court’s summary rejection of the independent state legislature doctrine.
And Section C examines AIRC’s implications for states’ rules for allocating
presidential electors among candidates. As mentioned earlier, AIRC left
undisturbed the Court’s earlier holding that federal laws enacted pursuant
to the Elections Clause which preempt state statutes governing
congressional elections are not subject to a presumption against
preemption.
77
76 See, e.g., ELY, supra note 12; Nicholas Stephanopoulos, Reforming Redistricting:
Why Popular Initiatives to Establish Redistricting Commissions Succeed or Fail, 23 J.L.
&
POL. 331, 333 (2007) (embracing independent commissions as the only realistic way to
curb political gerrymandering); Jeffrey C. Kubin, Note, The Case for Redistricting
Commissions, 75 TEX. L. REV. 837, 838 (1997) ([W]hile commissions are no panacea, they
offer a viable means of restoring a degree of efficiency, fairness, and finality to a states
decennial gerrymander.”); cf. Cain, supra note 52, at 184243 (offering recommendations to
improve commissions).
77 Arizona v. Inter Tribal Council of Ariz., Inc., 133 S. Ct. 2247, 225354 (2013).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
93
A. Non-Delegation Doctrine
The AIRC Court not only adopted an expansive interpretation of
“Legislature,” but held that any process or entity that qualifies as a
legislature may delegate its power under the Elections Clause to other
organs of state government.
78
Interestingly, the Court did not cite any
authority or offer any analysis in support of its holding, but rather rested
this conclusion exclusively on a concession by appellant’s counsel.
79
Prior to this ruling, courts had periodically wrestled with delegation
issues under the Elections Clause. Recognizing that the Elections Clause is
one of the Constitution’s only provisions that “confers a power on a
particular branch of a State’s government,”
80
some courts had suggested
that the provision might implicitly bar legislatures from transferring that
power to other entities, or substantially restrict legislatures’ ability to make
such delegations.
81
The AIRC Court held that the power to regulate federal elections is
fully delegable. Because the Elections Clause confers power on both
legislatures and Congress, it is reasonable to assume that the same
limitations on delegation apply to both entities. In general, Congress may
delegate its powers so long as it cabins the agency’s discretion based on an
“intelligible principle.
82
The Supreme Court has upheld every
congressional delegation of authority it has encountered over the past
78 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652, 2671 (2015) ([T]he people may delegate their legislative
authority over redistricting to an independent commission just as the representative body
may choose to do.) (citing Transcript of Oral Argument at 1516, AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652
(2015) (No. 13-1314)).
79 Id.
80 Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 112 (2000) (Rehnquist, C.J., concurring).
81 See, e.g., Green Party of Tenn. v. Hargett, 882 F. Supp. 2d 959, 101718 (M.D.
Tenn. 2012) ([G]iven the absence of statutory standards for the exercise of the State
Elections Coordinators discretion,a state law authorizing the coordinator to develop
criteria for determining whether a group qualifies as a minor political party is not a
permissible delegation of legislative authority.”), rev’d 700 F.3d 816 (6th Cir. 2012). Of
course, it still would violate the Elections Clause for an organ of state government to
attempt to regulate federal elections in the absence of a delegation from an entity or process
that qualifies as a Legislature. See Libertarian Party of Ohio v. Brunner, 567 F. Supp. 2d
1006, 1012 (S.D. Ohio 2008) (Even if the Ohio General Assembly could delegate its
authority to a member of the executive branch . . . , there is no evidence that the state
legislature has specifically delegated its authority to Defendant to direct the manner in
which [federal elections are conducted].); Grills v. Branigin, 284 F. Supp. 176, 180 (S.D.
Ind. 1968) ([The Elections Clause] clearly does not authorize the defendants, as members
of the Election Board of Indiana, to create congressional districts. This power is granted to
the Indiana General Assembly . . . .”), aff’d Branigin v. Duddleston, 391 U.S. 364 (1968).
82 Whitman v. Am. Trucking Assns, 531 U.S. 457, 472 (2001) (quoting J.W.
Hampton, Jr., & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 409 (1928)).
94
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
eighty years.
83
It has approved delegations based on exceedingly vague
criteria, allowing agencies to set standards that are “fair and equitable”
84
or
that serve “the public interest, convenience, or necessity.”
85
Based on these
precedents, most commentators contend that the non-delegation doctrine is
effectively dead,
86
and surprisingly few mourn its loss.
87
The Court has never directly addressed whether the Elections Clause
imposes any constraints on the power of state legislatures or Congress to
delegate their authority to regulate federal elections. Even assuming that
some limit exists, it is likely nothing more than the “intelligible principle
standard to which other delegations of federal legislative authority are
subject.
88
Thus, it will be virtually impossible for a litigant to successfully
challenge even sweeping and effectively standardless delegations by
legislatures over election-related regulations to independent commissions,
executive officials, administrative agencies, or local entities.
B. Independent State Legislature Doctrine
Aside from its approval of redistricting commissions, perhaps the
most important and far-reaching aspect of AIRC was the Court’s summary
rejection of the independent state legislature doctrine. The doctrine
recognizes that, when a legislature enacts a law that applies to federal
elections, it is acting “by virtue of a direct grant of authority” from the
Elections Clause and Presidential Electors Clause.
89
Thus,
83 Cass R. Sunstein, Nondelegation Canons, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 315, 315 (2000); cf.
A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495, 54142 (1935); Panama
Refining Co. v. Ryan, 293 U.S. 388, 42021 (1935).
84 Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 423 (1944).
85 NBC v. United States, 319 U.S. 190, 216 (1943).
86 Richard D. Cudahy, The Nondelegation Doctrine: Rumors of Its Resurrection
Prove Unfounded, 16 S
T. JOHNS J. LEGAL COMMENT. 1, 39 (2002) (It will certainly be a
long time before a court of appeals is once again moved to bring the doctrine out from the
shadows into the sunlight.).
87 See, e.g., Thomas W. Merrill, Rethinking Article I, Section 1: From Nondelegation
to Exclusive Delegation, 104 C
OLUM. L. REV. 2097, 2165 (2004) ([T]he nondelegation
doctrine, as a general requirement that Congress must circumscribe the discretion of
administrative agencies, should be rejected.); Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Interring
the Nondelegation Doctrine, 69 U.
CHI. L. REV. 1721, 1722 (2002) (The nondelegation
position lacks any foundation in constitutional text and structure, in standard originalist
sources, or in sound economic and political theory.); cf. Sunstein, supra note 83, at 31516
(arguing that nondelegation canons of statutory interpretation, rather than a substantive
nondelegation doctrine, exist).
88 Whitman v. Am. Trucking Assns, 531 U.S. 457, 472 (2001) (quoting J.W.
Hampton, Jr., & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 409 (1928)).
89 Bush v. Palm Beach Cty. Canvassing Bd., 531 U.S. 70, 76 (2000) (per curiam); see
also supra note 3 and accompanying text.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
95
Although laws governing federal elections must be enacted through
the “legislative process” set forth in the state constitution, . . . a state
constitution cannot restrict the [substantive] scope of the power and
discretion that the U.S. Constitution bestows on the state legislature to
regulate the manner in which federal elections are conducted.
90
As the Supreme Court stated in McPherson v. Blacker, the
Constitution’s delegations specifically to state legislatures of power to
regulate federal elections “operat[e] as a limitation upon the State in respect
of any attempt to circumscribe th[at] legislative power,” including through
“any provision in the state constitution in that regard.”
91
Under the independent state legislature doctrine, if a state law
concerning federal elections conflicts with a state constitution, the law
prevails. For example, in In re Plurality Elections, a Rhode Island statute
required a candidate for federal office to receive only a plurality of votes in
order to win.
92
The state constitution, in contrast, required candidates for
public office to receive a majority of votes to prevail.
93
The Rhode Island
Supreme Court held that, because state legislatures act pursuant to their
authority under the U.S. Constitution when enacting laws regulating federal
elections, the law was enforceable regardless of any contrary provision in
the state constitution.
94
Numerous other courts
95
and commentators
96
have
recognized and applied the doctrine.
Without so much as acknowledging any of these authorities
including the Court’s own statement in McPherson—the AIRC majority
summarily repudiated the doctrine. It held, “Nothing in th[e] [Elections]
Clause instructs, nor has this Court ever held, that a state legislature may
prescribe regulations on the time, place, and manner of holding federal
elections in defiance of provisions of the State’s constitution.”
97
As
90 Morley, supra note 64, at 199200 (quoting Smiley v. Holm, 285 U.S. 355, 368
(1932)).
91 146 U.S. 1, 25 (1892).
92 8 A. 881, 882 (R.I. 1887).
93 Id.
94 Id. at 88182.
95 E.g., PG Publ. Co. v. Aichele, 902 F. Supp. 2d 724, 74748 (W.D. Pa. 2012), affd
on other grounds, 705 F.3d 91 (3d Cir. 2013); State ex rel. Beeson v. Marsh, 34 N.W.2d
279, 28687 (Neb. 1948); In re Opinions of Justices, 45 N.H. 595, 601 (1864); see also
Commonwealth ex rel. Dummit v. OConnell, 181 S.W.2d 691, 695 (Ky. Ct. App. 1944).
96 Walter Clark, The Electoral College and Presidential Suffrage, 65 U. PA. L. REV.
737, 741 (1917); Richard D. Friedman, Trying to Make Peace with Bush v. Gore, 29 F
LA.
ST. U. L. REV. 811, 835 (2001); James C. Kirby, Jr., Limitations on the Power of State
Legislatures over Presidential Elections, 27 L
AW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 495, 504 (1962);
Morley, supra note 64, at 198204; Emory Widener, Jr., Note, The Virginia Absent Voters
System, 8 W
ASH. & LEE L. REV. 36, 37 (1951); Note, Limitations on Access to the General
Election Ballot, 37 C
OLUM. L. REV. 86, 87 (1937).
97 AIRC, 135 S. Ct. 2652, 2673 (2015).
96
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
mentioned earlier, the Court dismissed the House of Representatives’s
endorsement and application of the independent state legislature doctrine as
a largely partisan maneuver,
98
and completely ignored a Senate committee
report recognizing the doctrine.
99
Under the majority’s ruling, a state legislature (as well as other entity
or process that qualifies as a “Legislature” under the Elections Clause) is
bound by substantive restrictions set forth in the state constitution when
enacting laws governing federal elections. Such laws, such as proof-of-
citizenship or voter identification requirements, may therefore be
challenged on state, as well as federal, constitutional grounds.
100
The Court
thus has ratified additional barriers to state efforts to protect the integrity of
federal elections.
C. Reallocating Presidential Electors
The AIRC Court’s interpretation of the Elections Clause likely applies
to the Presidential Electors Clause as well, as the two provisions are
typically read in pari materia.
101
Just as the Elections Clause empowers
the state “Legislature” to regulate the time, place, and manner of
congressional elections,
102
the Presidential Electors Clause grants the
“Legislature” power to regulate the process for choosing presidential
electors.
103
The AIRC majority interpreted the term legislature in the
Elections Clause to include public initiatives and referenda. It is likely to
interpret the Presidential Electors Clause the same way.
Commentators have long debated the constitutionality of reallocating
a state’s electoral votes for President through a public initiative or
referendum.
104
Under AIRC, voters likely may use the public initiative
98 Id. at 2674.
99 See S. REP. NO. 43-395, at 9 (1874).
100 See Joshua A. Douglas, The Right to Vote Under State Constitutions, 67 VAND. L.
REV. 89, 10405 (2014); see also William J. Brennan, Jr., State Constitutions and the
Protection of Individual Rights, 90 H
ARV. L. REV. 489, 502 (1977); cf. Morley, supra note
64, at 190 (The standards that the modern Supreme Court has adopted for determining the
constitutionality of election laws are consistent with over a century-and-a-half of state
constitutional precedents that long predate most federal voting rights cases.).
101 See Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.S. 112, 124 n.7 (1970) (Black, J., announcing the
judgment of the Court) (It cannot be seriously contended that Congress has less power over
the conduct of presidential elections than it has over congressional elections.”); see also
Burroughs v. United States, 290 U.S. 534, 54445 (1934).
102 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1.
103 Id. art. II, § 1, cl. 2.
104 Compare Michael McLaughlin, Note, Direct Democracy and the Electoral
College: Can a Popular Initiative Change How a State Appoints Its Electors?, 76 F
ORDHAM
L. REV. 2943, 3000 (2008) (arguing that initiatives may not be used to change state laws
relating to federal elections), and Nicholas P. Stabile, Comment, An End Run Around a
Representative Democracy? The Unconstitutionality of a Ballot Initiative to Alter the
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
97
process to change the way in which states allocate their electoral votes in
presidential elections. All states except for Nebraska
105
and Maine
106
allocate their electoral votes on a winner-take-all basis, meaning that the
presidential candidate who receives a plurality of the state’s popular vote
receives all of that state’s electoral votes. For example, in the 2012
election, Barack Obama received 60.24% of the popular vote in California,
yet was awarded all 55 of that state’s electoral votes.
107
At least three main alternatives exist. States could follow the example
of Nebraska and Maine by awarding presidential electors on a district-by-
district basis to the presidential candidate who receives the most votes in
each congressional district.
108
The candidate who receives the most
statewide votes would be awarded the state’s two additional electors.
Under this system, Obama would have received 43 of California’s electoral
votes, and Romney would have received 12.
109
Alternatively, a state’s
electors could be awarded in proportion to the percentage of the statewide
popular vote received by each candidate who exceeds some minimum
threshold. Under this approach, California would have awarded 34 of its
electoral votes to Obama, and 21 to Romney.
110
Some commentators
Method of Distributing Electors, 103 NW. U. L. REV. 1495 (2009), with Vikram David
Amar, Direct Democracy and Article II: Additional Thoughts on Initiatives and Presidential
Elections, 35 H
ASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 631, 641 (2008), and David S. Wagner, Note, The
Forgotten Avenue of Reform: The Role of States in Electoral College Reform and the Use of
Ballot Initiatives to Effect that Change, 25 R
EV. LITIG. 575, 599 (2006) (defending the
constitutionality of using public initiatives to change the method for allocating a states
electoral votes). Cf. Richard L. Hasen, When Legislature May Mean More than
Legislature: Initiated Electoral College Reform and the Ghost of Bush v. Gore, 35
HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 599, 629 (2008) (A strict textual view suggests that initiated reform
is unconstitutional; case law and policy arguments show the question is more uncertain.
Reasonable judges could reach opposite conclusions on the question.”).
105 NEB. REV. STAT. § 32-1038(1) (2015).
106 ME. STAT. tit. 21-A, § 802 (2015).
107 FED. ELECTION COMMN, FEDERAL ELECTIONS 2012: ELECTION RESULTS FOR THE
U.S. PRESIDENT, THE U.S. SENATE, AND THE U.S. HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES 28 (2013),
http://www.fec.gov/pubrec/fe2012/federalelections2012.pdf.
108 Supra notes 10506.
109 David Nir, Daily Kos ElectionsPresidential Results by Congressional District for
the 2012 and 2008 Elections, D
AILY KOS (Nov. 19, 2012, 12:30 PM),
http://www.dailykos.com/story/2012/11/19/1163009/-Daily-Kos-Elections-presidential-
results-by-congressional-district-for-the-2012-2008-elections (specifying that Obama won
41 of Californias 53 congressional districts, as well as the statewide vote, and Romney won
12 congressional districts).
110 See RHODES COOK, AMERICA VOTES 30: 20112012 ELECTION RETURNS BY STATE
10 (2014) (specifying that Obama won 60.2% of the statewide vote in California and
Romney won 37.1%). Approximately 2.7% of the popular vote was split among twelve
third-party and independent candidates. F
ED. ELECTION COMMN, supra note 107, at 28.
None of them received enough votes to be allotted an elector. The “extra” electors that
98
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
instead have recommended various schemes for awarding a state’s electoral
votes based on the outcome of the national popular vote.
111
In states that generally cast their electoral votes for a particular party’s
candidate, politicians from that party likely could prevent the institutional
legislature from changing the method for allocating electoral votes. Under
AIRC, activists and voters may use the initiative process to circumvent
party bosses and ensure their state’s electoral votes more closely reflect the
views of the state’s electorate as a whole. Petitions for such initiatives
were circulated in California in past election cycles, but none received
enough signatures to be placed on the ballot.
112
Particularly since
initiatives often are introduced in off-year election cycles, when voter
turnout is lower,
113
it is reasonably possible that such a measurelike the
Arizona initiative that gave rise to AIRC in the first placemight succeed.
AIRC thus opens the door to potential realignments in presidential politics.
III.
REMAINING QUESTIONS
AIRC has reshaped Elections Clause doctrine and resolved several
longstanding controversies concerning its meaning.
114
This Part discusses
some important questions that remain. Section A argues that the Elections
Clause should be read as imposing a special duty on state and federal courts
to apply the plain meaning of state laws relating to federal elections.
Section B questions whether Congress’s authority to regulate congressional
elections is truly coextensive with its power to regulate congressional
elections under the Elections Clause. Section C discusses possible
“commandeering” concerns with federal election statutes. Finally, Section
D examines implicit limits on the power the Elections Clause grants states
to regulate congressional elections.
neither Obama nor Romney won directly likely would have been split between Obama and
Romney on a pro rata basis.
111 See, e.g., Vikram David Amar, Response, The Case for Reforming Presidential
Elections by Subconstitutional Means: The Electoral College, the National Popular Vote
Compact, and Congressional Power, 100 G
EO. L.J. 237 (2011).
112 See, e.g., Memorandum from Katherine Montgomery, Initiative Program Manager,
Cal. Secy of State, to All County Clerks/Registrars of Voters and Proponent (Feb. 2, 2011),
elections.cdn.sos.ca.gov/ccrov/pdf/2011/february/11008km.pdf (transmitting official title
and summary for Ballot Initiative #10-0024, entitled Electoral College Reform Act); Letter
from Anthony F. Andrade, Jr., Proponent, to Edmund G. Brown, Jr., Atty Gen., State of
Cal. (May 21, 2007), http://oag.ca.gov/system/files/initiatives/pdfs/07-0016%20(2007-05-
22_07-0016_A1NS).pdf (submitting amendments to proposed ballot initiative #07-0016,
entitled Electoral Reform California).
113 See Nicole E. Lucy, Mediation of Proposition 187: Creative Solution to an Old
Problem? Or Quiet Death for Initiatives?, 1 P
EPP. DISP. RESOL. L.J. 123, 139 n.100 (2001)
(citing sources).
114 See supra Part II.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
99
A. Strict Statutory Construction and the Democracy Canon
Perhaps the most significant Elections Clause doctrine the AIRC Court
did not address is its requirement that both state and federal courts take
special care to enforce the plain text of state election statutes, rather than
applying their own judicial gloss or other doctrines, such as Professor Rick
Hasen’s “Democracy Canon.”
115
As discussed throughout this Essay, the Elections Clause and
Presidential Electors Clause are grants of constitutional authority to state
legislaturesconstrued broadly by the AIRC Court as embracing any
lawmaking entity or process authorized by a state’s constitutionrather
than to states as a whole. The Supreme Court has recognized that this
specific delegation of authority imposes a special duty on other
governmental entities to ensure that they apply election laws as written by
the legislature, rather than with the flexibility and discretion they otherwise
might be permitted to apply.
In Bush v. Palm Beach County Canvassing Board, the Supreme Court
observed that, “[a]s a general rule, [it] defers to a state court’s
interpretation of a state statute.”
116
When a legislature enacts a law
regulating a presidential election, however, it is acting “by virtue of a direct
grant of authority made under [the Presidential Electors Clause].”
117
Laws
enacted under the Presidential Electors Clauseand, by extension, the
Elections Clauserequire a special interpretive approach.
Seven Justices went on to apply such an approach in Bush v. Gore.
118
Chief Justice Rehnquist’s concurrence, in which Justices Scalia and
Thomas joined, stated that, when a legislature acts under the Presidential
Electors Clause, “the text of the election law itself . . . takes on independent
significance.”
119
Courts have a unique duty to ensure they do not “depart[]
from the statutory meaning” of such laws, even if they generally would
have such interpretive power.
120
The four-Justice dissent written by Justice Souter echoed this
sentiment, recognizing that the U.S. Supreme Court’s responsibility was to
ensure that the Florida Supreme Court had not “displaced the state
legislature’s” enactments, and that the “law as declared by the court” was
not “different from the provisions made by the legislature, to which the
115 Hasen, supra note 15.
116 531 U.S. 70, 76 (2000) (per curiam).
117 Id.
118 531 U.S. 98 (2000) (per curiam).
119 Id. at 113 (Rehnquist, C.J., concurring).
120 Id. at 115.
100
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
National Constitution commits responsibility for determining how each
State’s Presidential electors are chosen.”
121
Applying a super-strong plain meaning construction of laws regulating
federal electionsindeed, all electionspromotes fair outcomes because it
minimizes the opportunity for partisan manipulation. Election laws are
enacted before election disputes arise, behind at least a partial “veil of
ignorance.”
122
Because the legislature often will not know which candidate
will benefit from a particular rule, there is an increased likelihood that the
rule will be fair.
123
When courts must interpret and apply the rule,
particularly after an election is over, they generally know which candidates
and political parties will benefit from different possible interpretations.
There is a substantial risk that such knowledge may color courts’ views,
leading to rulings that are at least partially outcome-driven. Indeed, some
courts have gone so far as to recognize that adopting an unexpected
interpretation of the rules governing an election after-the-fact can amount
to a due process violation.
124
Limiting courts’ discretion to interpret
election rules may ameliorate the possibility of their partisan bias
improperly influencing the outcome of election litigation.
B. Federal Regulation of Presidential Elections
Another issue the Elections Clause raises is whether Congress’s
authority over presidential elections is coextensive with its power over
congressional elections. The Elections Clause expressly permits Congress
to “make or alter” state election laws;
125
the Presidential Electors Clause
lacks analogous language. The material difference in language between the
Elections Clause and Presidential Electors Clause has not caused the
Supreme Court pause, however. Rather, the Court held that the federal
government has inherent authority to regulate presidential elections.
126
This issue might be ripe for more careful consideration, however, in light
121 Id. at 130 (Souter, J., dissenting); see also Reform Party v. Black, 885 So. 2d 303,
312 (Fla. 2004) ([A]lthough the judiciary has the power and authority to construe statutes,
it cannot construe statutes in a manner that would infringe on the direct grant of authority to
the Legislature through the United States Constitution.”); cf. Roe v. Alabama, 68 F.3d 404,
40607 (11th Cir. 1995) (holding that a state courts construction of an election law contrary
to its plain meaning violated votersconstitutional rights).
122 JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 136 (1971).
123 Chad Flanders, Election Law Behind a Veil of Ignorance, 64 FLA. L. REV. 1369,
137882 (2012).
124 Roe, 68 F.3d at 40607; Griffin v. Burns, 570 F.2d 1065, 107879 (1st Cir. 1978).
125 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 4, cl. 1.
126 See supra note 101; cf. Amar, supra note 111, at 260 (arguing that the Elections
Clause empowers Congress to regulate presidential elections because congressional and
presidential elections occur simultaneously, and rules concerning the latter may affect
turnout for the former).
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
101
of the Court’s recent attention (such as it is) to the language and meaning
of the clause, as well as the strict limits it has imposed on the scope of
Congress’s power to enforce constitutional rights under Section 5 of the
Fourteenth Amendment.
127
C. Commandeering and Federal Election Law
The Court has yet to squarely address whether Printz’s anti-
commandeering prohibitions
128
apply to laws enacted pursuant to the
Elections Clause and whatever authority Congress might possess over
presidential elections. Nevertheless, it appears that anti-commandeering
challenges to federal voting laws are unlikely to succeed.
Printz held that it is “fundamentally incompatible with our
constitutional system of dual sovereignty” for Congress to “command the
States’ officers, or those of their political subdivisions, to administer or
enforce a federal regulatory program.”
129
It invalidated interim provisions
of the Brady Handgun Violence Prevention Act,
130
enacted under the
Commerce Clause,
131
which required “state and local law enforcement
officials to conduct background checks on prospective handgun
purchasers.”
132
Over a century before Printz, the Court had held that state election
officials may be called upon to “fulfil [sic] duties which they owe to the
United States” in connection with federal elections.
133
And in Branch v.
Smith, a four-Justice plurality held that federal laws requiring state officials
to engage in tasks relating to federal elections do not amount to
unconstitutional commandeering, because they simply “regulat[e] (as the
Constitution specifically permits) the manner in which a State is to fulfill
its pre-existing constitutional obligations” under the Elections Clause.
134
That ruling drew a stinging dissent from Justices Thomas and O’Connor,
who questioned the plurality’s refusal to apply Printz to the Elections
Clause.
135
Many commentators have argued that the Elections Clause expressly
authorizes commandeering of state officials, at least for congressional
elections. Commandeering proponents point out that the types of statutes
127 City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (1997).
128 Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898, 935 (1997).
129 Id.
130 Pub. L. No. 103-159, § 102(a)(1), 107 Stat. 1536, 153639 (1993) (codified at 18
U.S.C. § 922(s)(2), (s)(6)(B)–(C)), invalidated by Printz, 521 U.S. at 935.
131 Printz, 521 U.S. at 92324.
132 Id. at 902.
133 Ex Parte Siebold, 100 U.S. 371, 387 (1879).
134 538 U.S. 254, 280 (2003) (plurality opinion).
135 Id. at 30102 (OConnor, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
102
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
the clause expressly authorizes Congress to enact necessarily must be
implemented by state and local election officials.
136
Consistent with this
view, courts have rejected anti-commandeering challenges to the National
Voter Registration Act (NVRA),
137
which requires state officials to make
voter registration forms available at certain public offices and proscribes
detailed requirements for their processing.
138
Paul McGreal, however,
offers a persuasive argument that the Constitution’s “text, history,
precedent, [and] structure,” as well as “prior government practice,”
demonstrates that Congress may not commandeer state and local officials
under the Elections Clause.
139
Other commentators
140
sidestep the Elections Clause issue by
contending that, even if Article I does not authorize Congress to
commandeer state officials, it may do so when enacting laws under Section
5 of the Fourteenth Amendment.
141
The Court also has yet to directly
address this theory. Such an approach might be more persuasive than an
argument under the Elections Clause itself, since the Fourteenth
136 Evan H. Caminker, Printz, State Sovereignty, and the Limits of Formalism, 1997
S
UP. CT. REV. 199, 23738; Dan T. Coenen & Edward J. Larson, Congressional Power over
Presidential Elections: Lessons from the Past and Reforms for the Future, 43 W
M. & MARY
L. REV. 851, 897 (2002); Kevin K. Green, Note, A Vote Properly Cast? The
Constitutionality of the National Voter Registration Act of 1993, 22 J.
LEGIS. 45, 8283
(1996); see also Amar, supra note 111, at 25960; Michael S. Greve, Fallacies of Fallacies,
94 B.U.
L. REV. 1359, 1372 n.84 (2014).
137 Pub. L. No. 103-31, 107 Stat. 77, 77 (1993) (codified in scattered sections of 39
U.S.C. and 52 U.S.C. (2012)).
138 Voting Rights Coal. v. Wilson, 60 F.3d 1411, 1415 (9th Cir. 1995) (Congress may
conscript state agencies to carry out voter registration for the election of Representatives and
Senators.”); see also Assn of Cmty. Orgs. for Reform Now v. Miller, 129 F.3d 833, 836
(6th Cir. 1997) (affirming the NVRAs constitutionality because the Elections Clause
empowers Congress to direct states to amend their laws governing federal elections); Assn
of Cmty. Orgs. for Reform Now v. Edgar, 56 F.3d 791 (7th Cir. 1995) (pre-Printz case
affirming NVRA).
139 Paul E. McGreal, Unconstitutional Politics, 76 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 519, 55354
(2001).
140 Caminker, supra note 136, at 23940; Pamela S. Karlan, Section 5 Squared:
Congressional Power to Extend and Amend the Voting Rights Act, 44 H
OUS. L. REV. 1, 24
25 (2007); Brian C. Brook, Note, Federalizing the First Responders to Acts of Terrorism via
the Militia Clauses, 54 DUKE L.J. 999, 100506 (2005); see also William D. Araiza,
Deference to Congressional Fact-Finding in Rights-Enforcing and Rights-Limiting
Legislation, 88 N.Y.U. L. REV. 878, 940 (2013); Roderick M. Hills, Jr., The Political
Economy of Cooperative Federalism: Why State Autonomy Makes Sense and Dual
SovereigntyDoesn’t, 96 M
ICH. L. REV. 813, 88889 (1998). But see Michael D. Hatcher,
Note, Printz Policy: Federalism Undermines Miranda, 88 G
EO. L.J. 177, 18990 (1999).
141 U.S. CONST. amend. XIV, § 5.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
103
Amendment abrogates state sovereignty in a variety of ways
142
and, unlike
the Elections Clause, applies equally to congressional and presidential
elections. Federal election laws would be subject to closer scrutiny,
however, because Congress is not permitted to legislate under Section 5
unless the statute is both congruent and proportional to a constitutional
violation.
143
D. Limits on State Authority
A final Elections Clause issue that also remains for future resolution is
the limit of states’ authority to enact laws concerning federal elections.
States have no inherent power to regulate federal elections; their only
power to do so comes from the Elections Clause and Presidential Elections
Clause.
144
The Court has explained that the Elections Clause grants states
broad power to enact a “complete code for congressional elections,”
concerning not only “times and places,” but also “notices, registration,
supervision of voting, protection of voters, prevention of fraud and corrupt
practices, counting of votes, duties of inspectors and canvassers, and
making and publication of election returns.”
145
It allows states “to enact
the numerous requirements as to procedure and safeguards which
experience shows are necessary in order to enforce the fundamental right
involved.”
146
This broad delegation of authority is subject to implied limits not set
forth in the Constitution’s text. The Court has held that the Elections
Clause is not “a source of power to dictate electoral outcomes, to favor or
disfavor a class of candidates, or to evade important constitutional
restraints.”
147
States therefore lack power to enact laws governing
congressional elections that fall into any of those categories. The Court has
applied this principle to invalidate state laws that attempted, directly or
indirectly, to impose term limits for Congress. In U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v.
Thornton, it struck down a statute prohibiting a candidate from appearing
on the ballot if he or she already had served a specified number of terms in
142 See, e.g., Tennessee v. Lane, 541 U.S. 509, 518 (2004) (recognizing that Congress
may abrogate states sovereign immunity when legislating under Section 5, but not
Article I).
143 City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (1997).
144 Cook v. Gralike, 531 U.S. 510, 523 (2001); U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton,
514 U.S. 779, 80405 (1995); see also Bush v. Palm Beach Cty. Canvassing Bd., 531 U.S.
70, 76 (2000) (per curiam).
145 Smiley v. Holm, 258 U.S. 355, 366 (1932).
146 Id.
147 U.S. Term Limits, 514 U.S. at 83334.
104
NOTRE DAME LAW REVIEW ONLINE [VOL. 91:2
the U.S. House or U.S. Senate, though the person could still run as a write-
in candidate.
148
Likewise, in Cook v. Gralike, it held unconstitutional a law that
required negative messages to be printed on the ballot next to the names of
candidates who refused to support a particular constitutional amendment
imposing term limits for Congress.
149
The Court explained that the
provision “is plainly designed to favor candidates who are willing to
support the particular form of a term limits amendment set forth in its text
and to disfavor those who either oppose term limits entirely or would prefer
a different proposal.”
150
It added, “‘[B]y directing the citizen’s attention to
the single consideration’ of the candidates’ fidelity to term limits, the labels
imply that the issue ‘is an importantperhaps paramount—consideration
in the citizen’s choice . . . .’”
151
The Court concluded that such an attempt
to “dictate electoral outcomes” is “not authorized by the Elections
Clause.”
152
The Court has never enforced the Elections Clause’s implicit limits on
states’ authority outside of the term limits context. Its holding that states
lack power to “dictate electoral outcomes” or “favor or disfavor a class of
candidates”
153
is potentially far-reaching, however. Many facially neutral
election laws may systematically benefit or hinder candidates from a
particular party. It is unclear whether the Elections Clause’s restriction on
state power hinges on the intent of the legislature or the effects of a statute,
and how closely the Court will scrutinize a law’s effects to determine
whether it impermissibly affects an election’s outcomes. Excluding
candidates from the ballot, or printing derogatory warnings next to their
names on the ballot, are direct and substantial handicaps specific to
particular candidates. It remains to be seen whether future Courts will
enforce the Elections Clause’s implied restrictions broadly to prohibit other
measures that might affect the outcome of an election, such as voter
identification laws, absentee voting restrictions, or reductions in early
voting periods.
C
ONCLUSION
The Elections Clause sits at a critical intersection of federalism,
separation of powers, and constitutional rights. It confers power on a
148 Id. at 835 (holding that a state-imposed ballot access restriction is [not]
constitutional when it is undertaken for the twin goals of disadvantaging a particular class of
candidates and evading the dictates of the Qualifications Clauses”).
149 Cook, 531 U.S. at 51415.
150 Id. at 524.
151 Id. at 525 (quoting Anderson v. Martin, 375 U.S. 399, 402 (1964)).
152 Id. at 526 (quoting U.S. Term Limits, 514 U.S. at 83334).
153 U.S. Term Limits, 514 U.S. at 83334.
2016]
THE NEW ELECTIONS CLAUSE
105
specific branch of state government, expressly authorizes federal
preemption of state laws (if not federal commandeering of state
officials
154
), and contemplates regulation of the fundamental constitutional
right to vote. While AIRC has largely settled questions concerning
delegation of Elections Clause authority, the independent state legislature
doctrine, and the permissibility of reallocating a state’s presidential electors
through popular initiative (assuming the Presidential Electors Clause is
read in pari materia), other important issues remain. Perhaps most
significantly, whether AIRC is viewed as a legal process or representation-
reinforcing ruling, the majority’s approach raises substantial questions
about how far the Court will go in allowing the judiciary to preserve the
fairness of federal elections and enforce the right to vote despite express
textual grants of constitutional authority over the electoral system to
Congress. The Elections Clause thus serves not only as the constitutional
basis for a range of election-related doctrines, but perhaps as a harbinger
for the reinterpretation of other related provisions, as well.
154 See supra Section III.C.