Ash Center Occasional Papers
Tony Saich, Series Editor
Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth
Politics and Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist
Bourgeois Liberalism
Joshua Forstenzer
University of Sheffield (UK)
July 2018
Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation
Harvard Kennedy School
Ash Center Occasional Papers Series
Series Editor Tony Saich
Deputy Editor Jessica Engelman
The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation advances excellence and
innovation in governance and public policy through research, education, and public discussion.
By training the very best leaders, developing powerful new ideas, and disseminating innovative
solutions and institutional reforms, the Center’s goal is to meet the profound challenges facing the
world’s citizens. The Ford Foundation is a founding donor of the Center. Additional information about
the Ash Center is available at ash.harvard.edu.
This research paper is one in a series funded by the Ash Center for Democratic Governance and
Innovation at Harvard University’s John F. Kennedy School of Government. The views expressed in
the Ash Center Occasional Papers Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect
those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or of Harvard University. The papers in this
series are intended to elicit feedback and to encourage debate on important public policy challenges.
This paper is copyrighted by the author(s). It cannot be reproduced or reused without permission.
Ash Center Occasional Papers
Tony Saich, Series Editor
Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth Politics and
Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism
Joshua Forstenzer
University of Sheffield (UK)
July 2018
Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation
Harvard Kennedy School
The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation
advances excellence and innovation in governance and public policy through
research, education, and public discussion. By training the very best leaders,
developing powerful new ideas, and disseminating innovative solutions and
institutional reforms, the Ash Centers goal is to meet the profound chal-
lenges facing the world’s citizens. Our Occasional Papers series highlights
new research and commentary that we hope will engage our readers and
prompt an energetic exchange of ideas in the public policy community.
This paper is contributed by Joshua Forstenzer, the Vice-Chancellors Fellow
for the Public Benefit of Higher Education at the University of Sheffield and
a recent Democracy Visiting Fellow at the Ash Center. His research interests
are in political and social philosophy, American Pragmatism, and philosophy
of education. With this paper, Forstenzer answers the call of Harvard Ken-
nedy School’s academic dean and director of the Ash Centers Democratic
Governance Programs, Archon Fung, who has stated, “. . . in this moment, it
is critical to work on the challenges to democracy.”
Just days after the election of Donald Trump to the presidency of the United
States, specific passages from American philosopher Richard Rorty’s 1998
book Achieving Our Country were shared thousands of times on social
media. Both the New York Times and the Guardian wrote about Rorty’s
prophecy and its apparent realization, as within the haze that followed this
unexpected victory, Rorty seemed to offer a presciently trenchant analysis
of what led to the rise of “strong man” Trump. However, Forstenzer points
to Rorty’s own potential intellectual responsibility in the unfolding crisis of
liberal democracy.
Forstenzers paper seeks to elucidate the relationship between Rorty’s liberal
ironism and contemporary post-truth politics. While the paper ultimately
concludes that Rorty is not causally responsible and thus not complicit with
the rise of post-truth politics, it contends that Rorty’s philosophical project
bears some intellectual responsibility for the onset of post-truth politics
insofar as it took a complacent attitude towards the dangers associated with
over-affirming the contingency of our epistemic practices in public debate. In
the last instance, this paper argues that Rorty’s complacency is a pragmatic
failure and thus cuts to the heart of his pragmatism.
You may find all of the Ash Centers Occasional Papers online at
ash.harvard.edu.
Tony Saich, Series Editor and Director
Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation
Harvard Kennedy School
Letter from the Editor
The argument in this paper is the result of a great many discussions con-
ducted over the last year. In its first iteration, this paper was presented at a
masterclass in honour of Richard Bernstein at the Munich School of Philos-
ophy. All participants at that event have my thanks and Richard Bernstein,
Mara-Daria Cojocaru, and Martin Müller have my very special thanks
for their detailed comments. Versions of this paper were then presented at
the “Corrupting Education” conference and at the Centre for the Study of
Higher Education research seminar at the University of Sheffield. On these
occasions, the paper received very helpful comments from Ian James Kidd,
Heather Battaly, Marion Oveson, Charlie Crerar, Gareth Parry, and Heather
Ellis. Many more discussions relating to this paper have taken place within
the Ash Centers Democracy Fellows seminar and over coffee immediately
after our meetings in the fall term of 2017. Ultimately, this paper was pre-
sented during the Democracy Fellows seminar and received very helpful
comments from all in attendance. In particular, I am very grateful to Alice
Xu who made an excellent discussant and raised many important points
that helped significantly improve the paper. In addition, special thanks are
owed to Archon Fung, Clarissa Rile Hayward, Muriel Rouyer, Cornel West,
Markus Holdo, Robert Stern, Alexis Artaud de la Ferrière, María Marta
Maroto, Charles Petersen, Carrie Roush, Sean Gray, Quinton Mayne, and
Jonathan Collins for helpful comments, suggestions, and thoughtful crit-
icisms. Furthermore, I would like to extend my special thanks to Jessica
Engelman for her most excellent editorial guidance and to Daniel Harsha,
Teresa Acuña, and Tim Glynn-Burke for sustained and thoughtful institu-
tional support. Special thanks are also owed to Gaylen Moore from Moore
Better Writing for her kind and thoughtful editorial assistance. Finally, this
paper would not have come into being without the more general support of
the University of Sheffield, the Harvard Kennedy School, Sir Keith Burnett,
Ruth Arnold, Lord David Blunkett, Peter Levine, and Matthew Flinders.
They too have my heartfelt thanks. Of course, the usual disclaimer applies—
all remaining weaknesses, mistakes, and oversights are entirely my own.
Joshua Forstenzer
University of Sheffield (UK)
Acknowledgments
Contents
Introduction ............................................................1
I. What Is Post-Truth Politics? ..............................................5
II. Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism ..................................9
Truth, Justification, and Ethnocentrism .................................10
Rortyan Ironism: Liberalism without Foundations .........................13
III. Rorty’s Responsibility for Post-Truth Politics: Complicity, Causation,
and Complacency ....................................................16
Complicity ......................................................16
Causation .......................................................19
Complacency ....................................................21
Conclusion ............................................................27
Notes ................................................................29
Something Has Cracked
1
[M]embers of labor unions, and unorganized unskilled work-
ers, will sooner or later realize that their government is not
even trying to prevent wages from sinking or to prevent jobs
from being exported. Around the same time, they will realize
that suburban white-collar workers—themselves desperately
afraid of being downsized—are not going to let themselves
be taxed to provide social benefits for anyone else.
At that point, something will crack. The nonsuburban elec-
torate will decide that the system has failed and start looking
around for a strongman to vote for—someone willing to
assure them that, once he is elected, the smug bureaucrats,
tricky lawyers, overpaid bond salesmen, and postmodernist
professors will no longer be calling the shots.
[…]
One thing that is very likely to happen is that the gains made
in the past 40 years by black and brown Americans, and by
homosexuals, will be wiped out. Jocular contempt for women
will come back into fashion. […] All the resentment which
badly educated Americans feel about having their manners
dictated to them by college graduates will find an outlet.
1
(Richard Rorty, Achieving Our Country)
Introduction
Selecting intellectual heroes is a dangerous business. They are inevitably
riddled with vices (small or large, private or public, ethical or epistemic), no
matter how great their virtues. Their ideas go in and out of fashion and are
subject to human frailty as well as the vagaries of time, since they can be,
and often are, misunderstood or made to serve other masters at the hands of
their most ardent devotees as well as their staunchest critics. Worse still, the
tensions at the heart of their work, on occasion, can detract from the very
causes they aimed to serve. Determining how responsible our intellectual
heroes are for the unsavory uses and misuses of their thought is a messy,
human affair that inevitably demands that we take them off the pedestal we
had once erected in our innermost sanctum just for them.
Something Has Cracked
2
This is the thought that struck me when, just days after the election of Donald
Trump to the presidency of the United States of America, the passages cited
above from Richard Rorty’s Achieving Our Country were shared thousands of
times on social media, even leading The New York Times and The Guardian to
write about Rorty’s prophecy and its apparent realization.
2
According to such
articles, Trump’s election was proof that, to use Rorty’s phrase, “something had
cracked”: the rural white working class voted to run back the clock on racial
and gender equality because its economic standing had been so eroded by
globalization as to lose faith in piecemeal improvements, liberalism, and social
harmony, turning instead to a strongman who would sanction unleashing their
pent-up frustration in the form of various shades of bigotry. The Left had thus
failed to bind the concerns of the white working classes left behind by global-
ization and rampant economic inequality with those of the rainbow coalition
(comprising primarily women, the young, and people of color) that had carried
Barack Obama to back-to-back presidential terms.
This account seems to offer a compelling narrative to explain the rise of
“Trumpism.”
3
It is also, however, a simplistic narrative that ignores the more
fundamental question of whether Trump voters were, on the whole, more
motivated by economic distress and political disaffection,
4
belief in outright
falsehoods,
5
hostility towards Hillary Clinton,
6
undue political influence—
foreign (e.g., Russian interference)
7
or domestic (e.g., James Comey’s Octo-
ber 28, 2016, letter to Congress)
8
—or a more or less explicit desire to lash out
at the very popularity of liberal pluralism, exemplified—if nowhere else—in
Obama’s two-term presidency and the prospect of electing the first woman in
the history of the country to its highest office.
9
Nevertheless, in Achieving Our Country, Rorty tells a story that potentially
explains something that remains baffling to many—namely, how some-
one like Donald Trump could become the president of the United States of
America in the twenty-first century. This explanation is, of course, limited
by its prophetic and therefore anachronistic nature as well as by the fact
that it was couched in an attempt to elucidate a different problem: how the
American Left had lost its luster in the second half of the twentieth century.
Indeed, according to Rorty, from 1964 onwards, the Left was torn asunder
by the emergence of a “cultural Left” steeped in academic sensitivity and
focused on advocating for recognition of the historic oppression of people of
color, women, and people whom we might now identify as LGBTQ+. This
cultural Left “thinks more about stigma than money, more about deep and
hidden psychosexual motivations than about shallow and evident greed,”
10
Something Has Cracked
3
thus breaking away from what Rorty called a “reformist Left” that was “in
the business of piecemeal reform within the framework of a market econ-
omy.”
11
In his account, while the cultural Left helped to assert the voices of
underrepresented communities, it did so by relinquishing what Walt Whit-
man called “common dreams” along with the American national project
of becoming “the world’s first classless society.”
12
Rorty further suggested
that this schism caused the Left as a whole to move away from effectively
addressing inequality through national politics because the academic cul-
tural Left focused its attention instead on articulating visions of participatory
democracy and theorizing hegemonic oppression.
13
Ultimately, for Rorty,
the cultural Left was guilty of engaging in the politics of spectatorship while
the solution lies in rekindling the politics of collective action, building an
alliance between the intellectual Left, the labor movement, and the working
classes. He therefore proposed returning to an egalitarian reformist agenda
articulated within the national myth of American (as opposed to universalis-
tic) solidarity, focusing on a People’s Charter that would call for campaign
finance reform, universal health care, renewed funding for K–12 education,
and increased taxation of the very rich.
14
With the current debate (if we can call it that) between the moderate and
radical wings of the Democratic Party thundering on, it is no surprise that
some today find this strategic analysis and recommendation prescient and
even potentially useful.
15
However, in spite (or perhaps because) of Rorty
being one of my former intellectual heroes, applauding his foresight
regarding the undoing of the democratic settlement in America strikes me
as a problematic understanding of his own role in the unfolding crisis of
progressive liberalism. Why? Crucially, because the rise of “Trumpism”
was enabled by framing much of its political project within the rhetoric of
post-truth politics. Moreover, its repeated rejection of a strong standard of
truth seemingly echoes Rorty’s own recurrent assaults—from the Philos-
ophy and the Mirror of Nature onwards—on the very idea that “knowl-
edge,” “facts of the matter,” or “rational justification” can be anything
more than the product of local justificatory practices.
16
In other words,
elite rhetoric relating to post-truth politics echoes significant aspects of
Rorty’s wider philosophical project, a project he once called “postmod-
ernist bourgeois liberalism.”
17
In fact, this connection between Trump
and his acolytes’ style of doing politics and postmodernism is already the
object of media discussion.
18
Perhaps the most notable commentaries on
this issue come from Daniel Dennett and Andrew Perrin. In a February
2017 interview, Dennett said:
Something Has Cracked
4
Maybe people will now begin to realise that philosophers
aren’t quite so innocuous after all. Sometimes, views can
have terrifying consequences that might actually come true.
I think what the postmodernists did was truly evil. They are
responsible for the intellectual fad that made it respectable to
be cynical about truth and facts.
19
In contrast, Perrin maintains that “[t]he indictments of postmodernism are
based on a shallow caricature of the theory and an exaggerated estimation of
its effects.”
20
We may thus ask: Has the intellectual movement that is post-
modernism played a role in the rise of post-truth politics?
It is to go some way towards answering this question that I will seek to
articulate a scholarly account of the relationship between Rorty’s post-
modernism and post-truth politics in this paper.
21
This seems an appealing
project for me because I find force in both Dennett’s claim that cynicism
about our epistemic standards is democratically dangerous and Perrin’s
claim that it is unhelpful to discuss postmodernism as though it were a
clearly defined school of thought.
22
To be clear, I think focusing on Rorty
in this discussion is legitimate because: (a) recent attention given to his
‘prophecy’ invites further intellectual scrutiny;
23
(b) he was one of the few
great analytically-trained philosophers who associated himself with post-
modernism (even though he came to regret using the label); and (c) I think
he would have genuinely been appalled at the thought that his philosophical
approach had actually left us with a depleted rhetorical toolbox to con-
front the threat posed by a virulent strain of xenophobic, chauvinistic, and
authoritarian politics.
This paper therefore offers a kind of immanent critique of Rorty’s thought,
subjecting his views to the test of his pragmatism. While I ultimately con-
clude that it is not causally responsible for the advent of, and thus not com-
plicit with, post-truth politics, I will argue that Rorty’s philosophical project
bears some intellectual responsibility for the onset of post-truth politics,
insofar as it took a complacent attitude towards the dangers associated with
over-affirming the contingency of our epistemic claims. In the last instance,
I contend that, since post-truth politics demonstrates that embracing the
contingency of one’s epistemic commitments has been effectively cou-
pled to a regressive and illiberal political agenda, Rorty’s complacency is a
failure to properly embrace the pragmatist maxim. To show this, I will (I)
offer an account of post-truth politics, (II) present a broad outline of Rorty’s
Something Has Cracked
5
postmodernist bourgeois liberalism, and (III) consider its responsibility for
the rise of post-truth politics.
I. What Is Post-Truth Politics?
Truth is not in fashion these days—at least, not in the realm of politics.
Perhaps it never was; lies and deception have probably always played a sig-
nificant role in that part of life.
24
But our collective relationship to the value
of truth seems to have taken a turn for the worse in recent years.
25
Indeed,
Oxford Dictionaries proclaimed “post-truth” its 2016 word of the year, noting
a 2,000-percent increase in its usage over the previous year and defining it
as “relating to or denoting circumstances in which objective facts are less
influential in shaping public opinion than appeals to emotion and personal
belief.”
26
Evidence for the claim that we are living in an age of post-truth
politics is often found in two events: the Leave campaign’s victory in the
Brexit referendum and Donald Trump’s successful run for the US presidency.
Indeed, falsehoods and outright lies are perceived to have played a dispropor-
tionate role in these campaigns, with these electoral events culminating in the
triumph of the campaigns that told the most egregious untruths.
27
Thus, the
“post-truth” character of our politics refers to the relative irrelevance of the
value of truth in contemporary public affairs. Yet, the term “post-truth” has a
longer history.
Steve Tesich first coined the term in his 1992 article in The Nation entitled
“Government of Lies.”
28
There, he used the word “post-truth” to describe
his sense that America had become a society where truth is politically
unimportant. Starting with Watergate, but contending that Ronald Reagan’s
Iran-Contra scandal and George H. W. Bush’s fabricated justification for
America’s involvement in the Gulf War cut deeper still, Tesich explained that
tepid popular reaction to lies in politics had shown that the American people
would prefer to believe in comfortable falsehoods than confront harsh truths.
This realization alarmed him deeply:
We are rapidly becoming prototypes of a people that totali-
tarian monsters could only drool about in their dreams. All
the dictators up to now have had to work hard at suppressing
the truth. We, by our actions, are saying that this is no longer
necessary, that we have acquired a spiritual mechanism that
can denude truth of any significance. In a very fundamental
Something Has Cracked
6
way we, as a free people, have freely decided that we want to
live in some post-truth world.
29
In this post-truth world, according to Tesich, we are left to live in a gray and
fuzzy moral universe with few absolutes and a “cozy universal appeal,” since
it justifies and sanctions moral mediocrity. Here, we are bound to wander
aimlessly between confusion and quiescence.
30
From our current vantage point, it is hard not feel the poignancy of this descrip-
tion: the campaigns during the Brexit referendum and the 2016 US presidential
elections were not only marked by loudly expressed and oft-repeated false-
hoods, but they (each in their own way) also presented limited, unimaginative,
and uninspiring moral worlds where the politically viable options merely
offered a choice between one type of moral failing (passive acceptance of
extreme wealth inequality and of the socially regressive aspects of globaliza-
tion) and another, far worse still (xenophobic sentiment coupled with an agenda
of nationalist retrenchment and a clear disregard for the injustices visited upon
members of minority groups within the supposedly hallowed nation).
31
Rather
than rallying behind bold, vibrant, and ambitious moral agendas, voters were
left to adjudicate between the morally abject and the unspeakably worse. In
Tesich’s view, this moral quandary is made possible by a lack of social and
political currency placed in the value of truth.
While post-truth politics refers to the general diminishment of the signifi-
cance of traditional epistemic standards in public discourse, I think we must
go one step further and recognize that political rhetoric that encourages
(more or less explicitly) the deepening of this phenomenon constitutes a
highly strategic intervention in the public forum.
32
It is the rate of use of this
strategic intervention that distinguishes present day “post-truth” politics from
Tesich’s early “post-truth world.” What is the nature of this strategic inter-
vention? I think post-truth rhetoric operates as what Koopmans and Statham
called a “discursive opportunity structure.”
33
McCammon et al. explain that
discursive opportunity structures are “ideas in the larger political culture that
are believed to be ‘sensible,’ ‘realistic,’ and ‘legitimate’ and […] facilitate the
reception of” certain political proposals.
34
In other words, discursive oppor-
tunity structures act as framing agents for more specific political proposals,
facilitating persuasion by tapping into broader ideas with social currency.
35
Discursive opportunity structures can be more or less stable and more or less
in tune with wider discursive fields, and political actors may capitalize on
them to a greater or lesser degree.
Something Has Cracked
7
In the case of post-truth rhetoric, it is the blatant breach or diminishment
of traditional epistemic norms that serve distinct political agendas (most
recently, Brexit in the UK and Trumpism in the US). By “post-truth rhet-
oric,” I mean the discursive mobilization of ideas relating to the absence
of epistemic norms regarding political claims to motivate popular support
for one’s preferred agenda. One type of engagement in post-truth rhetoric
is when a speaker makes false assertions and refuses to defend them with
reasons when asked to by members of the public or the media. Another type
might be when a speaker makes contradictory statements within a relatively
short period of time and refuses to clarify which claim they believe to be
true. However, perhaps the most powerful type of engagement in post-truth
rhetoric is when a political actor makes a direct rejection of traditional
epistemic norms and/or of the epistemic authority of those who seek to
abide by traditional epistemic norms (such as technical experts, academics,
and reliable media outlets).
During the Brexit campaign, when Michael Gove, then British Secretary
of State for Justice and one of the leaders of the Leave campaign, said that
Britons had “had enough of experts,” his words were taken to give license to
the idea that no one knows anything better than anyone else.
36
Although Gove
later objected to that narrow interpretation of his words, their political effect
was to lend credence to the idea that expertise and official sources of knowl-
edge were not to be taken seriously when they said that the consequences of
Brexit were likely to be grave.
37
Across the Atlantic, during the 2016 tran-
sition, George Stephanopoulos questioned then Vice-President-Elect Mike
Pence about a tweet where then President-Elect Trump purported that he not
only won the electoral college but the popular vote as well, provided that
“you deduct the millions of people who voted illegally.”
38
Stephanopoulos
pointed out that there was no evidence of illegal voting on the scale sug-
gested by Trump’s tweet and asked whether it was a president-elect’s right to
make false statements. In response, Pence said:
Well, it’s his right to express his opinion as president-elect of
the United States. I think one of the things that’s refreshing
about our president-elect and one of the reasons why I think
he made such an incredible connection with people all across
this country is because he tells you what’s on his mind.
39
Here, Pence is conflating matters of opinion with matters of fact to occlude
the fact that Trump’s claim was not grounded in evidence.
Something Has Cracked
8
During his actual presidency, Trump’s political team has been even more
explicit about its epistemic commitments (or lack thereof). When Kelly-
anne Conway, senior presidential adviser, was asked by Chuck Todd on
NBC’s “Meet the Press” about the claim made by Trump and repeated by
Sean Spicer, the White House Press Secretary at the time, that Trump’s
inauguration was the most attended in the history of the United States,
she explained that they were merely offering “alternative facts.”
40
After
many media outlets insisted that such “alternative facts” were nothing
short of falsehoods, Trump started calling the mainstream media “fake
news” with alarming regularity.
41
The term “fake news” won the distinc-
tion of being the Collins Dictionary’s 2017 word of the year and refers
to “false, often sensational, information disseminated under the guise of
news reporting.”
42
In other words, after a campaign during which candi-
date Trump made 560 false statements according to the Toronto Star,
43
Trump was—without a hint of irony—now claiming that the mainstream
media were fabricating facts for the express purpose of politically damag-
ing his administration.
One explanation for this is that Trump and his associates simply do not
believe in the existence of an actual fact of the matter. Therefore, in their
view, all factual claims are merely expressive of partisan bias. As Trump’s
associate and former adviser, Roger Stone, explains it:
Facts are, obviously, in the eye of the beholder. You have an
obligation to make a compelling case. Caveat emptor. Let the
consumer decide what he or she believes or doesn’t believe
based on how compelling a case you put forward for your
point of view.
44
Reading these words, it is hard not to find resonance with some of Rorty’s
most provocative slogans. These include, for example: truth is “what one’s
peers, ceteris paribus, let one get away with saying”;
45
“the question of
whether justification to the community with which we identify entails truth
is simply irrelevant”;
46
“[n]o organism, human or non-human, is ever more
or less in touch with reality than any other organism”;
47
and, perhaps most
damningly, “anything can be made to look good or bad by being rede-
scribed.”
48
Although Stone and Rorty were expressing their views in widely
different contexts, it is precisely this appearance of chiming that warrants
further investigation. That is why I will now discuss Rorty’s wider intellec-
tual project.
Something Has Cracked
9
II. Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism
While Rorty began his academic career as a successful mainstream ana-
lytic philosopher, he famously became impatient with this approach.
49
From
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature onwards, he began to draw (rather
selectively) on Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and Dewey to develop an altogether
different kind of philosophical project. He called this project many names,
including “postmodernist bourgeois liberalism,” “liberal ironism,” and
“pragmatism.” It was in this phase of his career that he became “perhaps the
most extensively referred to of contemporary philosophers, both inside and to
an unusual extent outside academia,”
50
as well as an object of extraordinary
academic scorn:
Conservatives demonize him as a threat to civilization as
we know it; Marxists and other political radicals deplore
what they see as his complacent and uncritical defence of
American capitalism; postmodernists disdain his shallowness
compared with the arcane profundities of their European
gurus; analytical philosophers shake their heads sadly at a
good man gone to the bad; and the leading liberal political
theorists for the most part studiedly ignore him.
51
It is not to add unnecessary opprobrium that I intend to revisit Rorty’s central
philosophical contribution here, but rather to put his ideas to his own test in
the mode of immanent critique. While his style of writing and his detach-
ment from overt logical argumentation makes reading him as a consistent (or
even, at times, a coherent) proponent of a central argument difficult, even
the most uncharitable reading underlines his central concern with affirming
the primacy of practice over theory. Indeed, according to him, the value of
a theoretical idea is to be understood by contemplating its practical effects.
Rorty’s philosophical project is itself a theoretical idea and the worry ani-
mating this paper is that it may have played a role in contributing to the
advent of post-truth politics. To ascertain whether that is indeed the case, I
will endeavor to give a brief, but hopefully fair, account of his philosophical
project. At its heart, we find a double stance: on one hand, Rorty urges us to
confront the historical and cultural contingency of the justificatory standing
of our most cherished beliefs, and, on the other hand, he hopes to convince us
to remain as committed as ever to a wide and compassionate moral and polit-
ical liberalism. To explain how he thinks these commitments hang together,
let us consider each in turn.
Something Has Cracked
10
Truth, Justification, and Ethnocentrism
Rorty has a fraught relationship with the term “postmodernism.” On one
hand, he is one of the few major analytic philosophers to apply the term to
himself; on the other, he relatively rapidly distances himself from the “post-
modernist” label because he thinks the “term has been so over-used that it is
causing more trouble than it is worth.”
52
Rather, he proposes that we think
of Heidegger, Derrida and—presumably—himself as “post-Nietzschean”
philosophers. Yet, we still find an epistemological continuity in the position
referred to by these changing labels—namely, the rejection of the Enlighten-
ment “myth of the neutral justificatory framework.”
53
It is this rejection that I
will endeavor to explain in this section.
Although Rorty stresses that he does not offer a positive theory of truth, he
sometimes summarizes his view of truth by quoting William James’s famous
words: “The true […] is only the expedient in the way of our thinking.”
54
He
explains this tension as follows:
Philosophers who, like myself, find this Jamesian suggestion
persuasive swing back and forth between trying to reduce
truth to justification and propounding some form of mini-
malism about truth. In reductionist moods we have offered
such definitions of truth as “warranted assertability,” “ideal
assertability,” and “assertability at the end of inquiry.”
55
He therefore begins many of his books with a rejection of the correspondence
theory of truth. This is the view according to which p is true if and only if
p is the case. This view is problematic for Rorty because he maintains that
there is no “God’s eye view,” no “Archimedean” point, no way to ascertain
whether p is the case outside of local, contextually-rooted vocabularies and
practices. However, resisting the urge to make truth a relative concept, he
insists that there are only limited uses of the term “true”:
Commendation: this happens when I assert that p is true to express that I
agree with p and I think you should too;
Caution: this happens when I ask “p is justified but is it true?”—by doing
so I am expressing the thought that p might not be justifiable to other
existing or future audiences; or
Disquotation: this happens when I express how the concept of “truth” is
used in a given language-set.
56
Something Has Cracked
11
Crucially, for Rorty, truth is not the goal of inquiry. He holds that we can only
aim for something if we can know if we have achieved it, because it makes
no sense to say that we are aiming for something, the attainment of which
would remain obscure to us all the same. He takes it as given that we can
never know if we have arrived at truth. In fact, according to him, the caution-
ary use of truth (or what Rorty takes to be fallibilism) does not point towards
a realm of facts waiting to be discovered; rather, it reminds us of the variety
of standards of justification and the future possibility of a better theory. Thus,
for Rorty, inquiry merely aims for warranted assertability or justification.
Warranted assertability and justification, in his view, are never more than the
product of human conversation since, “[t]he world does not speak. Only we
do.
57
In other words, he rejects the correspondence theory of truth because,
while propositions and sentences are a part of the human world, they are not
to be found in the nonhuman natural world under the form of “facts.” Instead,
he proposes his ethnocentric account of justification, according to which jus-
tification is always bound by the standards currently in use in one’s commu-
nity.
58
Thus, the kind of human interaction that would make a belief justified
is discursive through and through, since a belief must be taken to be justified
by one’s community in order to be justified. As a result, for him, justification
is intensely locally (in terms of where the community begins and ends) and
historically (in the sense that a belief might fall in and out of favor) situated.
Furthermore, Rorty maintains that communities are contingent formations
loosely tied together by the existence of a shared vocabulary.
His use of the term “vocabulary” in this context is somewhat idiosyncratic,
since he considers vocabularies to be broad clusters of words and metaphors
thanks to which human beings communicate meaning, as opposed to sets
of concepts thanks to which we represent distinct parts of the world. He
believes this because he holds a pragmatic view of language.
Indeed, he illus-
trates this view by telling a Darwinian story about the evolution of language.
According to him, vocabularies come into existence for the same purpose as
practical tools—namely, “to help us cope with the world.”
59
Further evolu-
tionary processes have helped refine these vocabularies, so that only those
best suited for helping human beings prosper in their respective environments
remained. But these vocabularies are no more representationally accurate
than the chameleon’s ability to take on the colors of its neighboring environ-
ment. Instead, vocabularies can only be said to be more or less useful. The
usefulness of language goes beyond issues of survival, however, in allowing
us to pursue our distinctive conceptions of “human flourishing.”
60
Something Has Cracked
12
Crucially, for Rorty, different conceptions of human flourishing make different
vocabularies more or less useful for us. It follows from this that our judgments
about which vocabularies—and thus which standards of justification—are bet-
ter than others will ultimately depend upon our conception of human flourish-
ing. If a new vocabulary is judged to be closer to our ideal of human life, then
adopting it will be judged to be rational; if not, then adopting it will be deemed
irrational. Therefore, judgments about the rationality of selecting vocabularies
and standards of justification depend on our conception of human flourishing.
Indeed, according to him, we can determine the relative expediency of a vocab-
ulary in promoting a given set of interests and values, but we cannot neutrally
determine which interests and values it is more rational to pursue.
61
When we
make determinations of interests or assert the desirability of certain values, we
are only ever doing so from within our vocabulary.
62
But how are we to adjudicate between the determinations of value, standards,
and justification made by different communities? For Rorty, there is no neu-
tral standard by which we can answer such a question, because vocabularies
are incommensurable with one another—or, as Donald Davidson puts it,
“there is no chance that someone can take up a vantage point for comparing
conceptual schemes by temporarily shedding his own.”
63
The best we can
do, according to Rorty, is to judge the various vocabularies from within our
own vocabulary, which is by “our lights.” Furthermore, he maintains that
our admitting that such judgments are limited by our conceptual schemes
involves no greater loss than our misplaced belief in the myth of neutral jus-
tification. Instead, what we should hope for epistemically is greater solidar-
ity—that is to say, the widening of our community to incorporate more and
more people into the justificatory conversation (Rorty sometimes refers to
this process as growth in inter-subjective agreement).
64
And yet, Rorty goes further still. He actively seeks to discourage us from
aiming for a final vocabulary which would hold a neutral justificatory
mechanism, taking it as expressive of the ambition to impose an unwar-
ranted limitation on human creativity. Moreover, he adds that “the very idea
of a ‘fact of the matter is one we would be better off without,”
65
because
he believes that talk of “facts of the matter” suggests that “there are proce-
dures of justification which are natural and not merely local.”
66
Speaking in
a way that suggests that standards of fact, objectivity, or rational justification
are somehow outside ourselves, somehow beyond the control of our given
community, suggests an implicit commitment to the correspondence theory
of truth and a kind of subservience to the world, which constrains human
Something Has Cracked
13
autonomy by threatening to entrench a contingently held vocabulary as the
“Truth” and thus closing down avenues for conversation and playful rede-
scription.
67
Unbridled conversation and playful redescription, Rorty contends,
are necessary if we are to fully embrace his liberal ideal.
Rortyan Ironism: Liberalism without Foundations
In “Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism,” Rorty asserts that his political
project consists of an “attempt to defend the institutions and practices of
the rich North American democracies without”
68
grounding such a defense
in a transcultural and ahistorical account of rationality, morality, or human
dignity. The term “bourgeois,” he explains, denotes the historically and geo-
graphically situated type of liberalism Rorty intends to defend. He therefore
rejects the need to ground his liberalism in what he calls “philosophical
liberalism” which he understands to be “a collection of Kantian principles
thought to justify us in” our commitment to North American liberal hopes.
Rorty goes on to explain that the term “postmodernist” denotes “[a] ‘distrust
of metanarratives,’ narratives which […] are stories which purport to justify
loyalty to, or breaks with, certain contemporary communities, but which are
neither historical narratives about what these or other communities have done
in the past nor scenarios about what they might do in the future.”
69
Rorty
thus rejects, for example, Kant’s noumenal self, Hegel’s Absolute Spirit, and
Marx’s Proletariat, considering these totalizing entities too divorced from
the lives and concerns of actual communities to be of any real use. He also
suspects that aspiration to “Truth,” in the sense of aiming to reach a more
than merely ethnocentric justification for one’s view, constitutes another such
metanarrative he thinks we would be better served by abandoning.
70
Instead, Rorty takes John Rawls’s attempt at justification in Political Lib-
eralism to be exemplary of another, altogether preferable, approach. Rather
than seeking to ground liberal principles and democratic institutions in a
philosophical account of human nature, ethics, truth, or the self, Rawls limits
himself to seeking a reflective equilibrium amongst free and equal citizens
who are already committed to living in a liberal order rooted in American
public political culture. According to Rorty,
[Rawls] disengages the question of whether we ought to
be tolerant and Socratic from the question of whether this
strategy will lead to truth. He is content that it should lead
to whatever intersubjective reflective equilibrium may be
obtainable, given the contingent make-up of the subjects in
Something Has Cracked
14
question. Truth, viewed in the Platonic way, as the grasp of
what Rawls calls “an order antecedent to and given to us,” is
simply not relevant to democratic politics.
71
Rorty admits that this position presupposes that the self is fundamentally
plastic and malleable, capable of being reshaped to suit “oneself, to [be]
tailored to one’s politics, one’s religion, or one’s private sense of the meaning
of one’s life. This, in turn, presupposes that there is no ‘objective truth’ about
what the human self is really like.”
72
Rather, he invites us to envision the self
as a “centerless web” involved in a rich process of self-creation. This sense
of radical contingency (of the self, of one’s vocabulary, of the justification of
one’s cherished beliefs) is what he calls “irony.” Rorty’s liberal ironists are
thus acutely aware of the contingency of their world view, but nevertheless
choose to be firmly committed to liberalism. The key liberal commitment, in
this view, is an unwavering attachment to the fundamental rule formulated by
Jean Bethke Elshtain: “Don’t be cruel.”
73
But that alone does not suffice. If all liberalism demands is to avoid actu-
ally being cruel, then liberals might be tempted to sit idly and silently on
the side, more or less blissfully unaware of the depths of suffering visited
upon those who are not at present members of their community. Thus, Rorty
supplements the goal of avoiding cruelty with that of expanding one’s sense
of community by expanding solidarity, since solidarity is the means by which
groups grow into one another, becoming larger, more inclusive, and kinder
communities. This is to be achieved by being invested in the project of
involving more people in conversation by developing new and varied vocab-
ularies. These new vocabularies would, by Rorty’s account, permit manifold
groups to come to know one another—this is the meaning of his social hope.
74
Crucially, however, for him, vocabularies among smaller communities often
require protection from more influential vocabularies. Or, at the very least,
they require protection from the dominant vocabulary of universal rational
justification, which threatens to stifle conceptual creativity and innovation
and thus shut down conversation. The liberal ironist is therefore engaged in
the process of developing the virtues of tolerance, open-mindedness, creativ-
ity, inclusivity, and empathy.
How does the liberal ironist square their commitment to liberalism with
their awareness of radical contingency? In short, they do so through parti-
tion. Their awareness of radical contingency is a private matter, while their
commitment to expanding liberal solidarity is a public matter. Yet, it is also
Something Has Cracked
15
the case that Rorty insists on the fact that the expansion of solidarity is less a
matter of epistemic competence and more a matter of emotional education:
In my utopia, human solidarity would be seen not as a fact
to be recognized by clearing away “prejudice” or burrowing
down to previously hidden depths but, rather, as a goal to be
achieved. It is to be achieved not by inquiry but by imagina-
tion, the imaginative ability to see strange people as fellow
sufferers. Solidarity is not discovered by reflection but cre-
ated. It is created by increasing our sensitivity to the partic-
ular details of the pain and humiliation of other, unfamiliar
sorts of people. Such increased sensitivity makes it more
difficult to marginalize people different from ourselves by
thinking, “They do not feel it as we would,” or “There must
always be suffering, so why not let them suffer?”
75
Liberals can attempt to bring those who do not share their views about
the importance of sympathy and solidarity around to their point of view
through playful conversation (“joshing”
76
), but those who prove recalcitrant
to the charms of liberalism must eventually just be considered “mad,”
77
“brutes,”
78
or “fanatics.”
79
These illiberal types (Nazis and religious fun-
damentalists, for example), in this view, are people to whom there is no
need to justify one’s self. They are outside the moral community and no
exhortation to become more rational, to attend to “the facts of the matter,”
to human nature, or to the truth are liable to sway them. Our best hope, as
far as Rorty is concerned, is edification via exposure to detailed narratives
about other people or narratives that offer redescribed versions of our-
selves that encourage people to see others as “one of us” rather than “one
of them.”
80
He thus advocates a turn away from the search for theory, facts,
and criteria, and towards narrative learning for moral and political progress.
Our transitional goal, for him, is to avoid “conversation stoppers,”
81
such as
appealing to the authority of God, Truth, or History, to defend our currently
cherished beliefs. Instead, a thorough awareness of the contingency of our
own views serves as the means to ensure that the conversation remains
forever open. Thus, the ironists realize
that anything can be made to look good or bad by being
redescribed, and their renunciation of the attempt to formu-
late criteria of choice between final vocabularies, puts them
in a position which Sartre called “meta-stable”: never quite
Something Has Cracked
16
able to take themselves seriously because always aware that
the terms in which they describe themselves are subject to
change, always aware of the contingency and fragility of
their final vocabularies, and thus of their selves.
82
Since Rorty considers himself to be offering his own liberal ironist narra-
tive as a means to encourage broader and richer conversation,
83
we may thus
legitimately ask: How effective is Rorty’s own ironist narrative at further-
ing this goal? If nothing else, the advent of post-truth politics has brought a
renewed practical saliency to this question that I think is worth addressing.
As it stands, post-truth politics has not served the end of broadening the
liberal conversation, but of closing it down by bolstering a renascent nativ-
ism and growing mistrust between significant portions of the population in
the US and the UK. That is why I will now seek to ascertain how responsible
Rorty’s philosophical project can be legitimately considered to be for the rise
of post-truth politics.
III. Rorty’s Responsibility for Post-Truth Politics: Complicity, Causation, and
Complacency
Establishing Rorty’s intellectual responsibility for the advent of an empirical
phenomenon (i.e., post-truth politics) is, as I mentioned in the introduction,
inevitably a messy, human affair. Nevertheless, to bring as much light and
clarity to the topic at hand, it is necessary to introduce three different dimen-
sions of responsibility, namely: complicity, causation, and complacency.
84
I
will address these in turn.
Complicity
Complicity involves enabling (i.e., providing a necessary condition for) or
facilitating (i.e., making it more likely that another actor will perform) a
wrongdoing while not being the principal perpetrator of said wrongdoing.
According to Gregory Mellema, the paradigm case of moral complicity is
one where “the agent (or agents) is the principal actor by virtue of moral
wrongdoing and one or more agents contribute to the outcome in a manner
that makes them complicit to the wrongdoing of the principal agent(s).”
85
Crucially, the charge of complicity assumes that the accomplice intends to
aid a perpetrator in carrying out a certain course of action and plays a causal
role in enabling it.
86
Something Has Cracked
17
Now, to be clear, my concern is not that Rorty is somehow complicit with
all of the political agendas associated with politicians who make use of
post-truth rhetoric—his compassionate liberalism precludes him from
intending to bolster cruel, xenophobic, or authoritarian political agendas.
Rather, I am merely worried that Rorty might be complicit with a limited
part of these agendas—namely, the part that involves seeking to diminish the
significance of traditional epistemic standards in public discourse. We may
call this the “post-truth agenda.” I contend that the success of the post-truth
agenda constitutes a harm in its own right, because it aims to deny politically
salient information to citizens. In How Democracies Die, Steven Levitsky
and Daniel Ziblatt explain that “[c]itizens have a basic right to information in
a democracy. Without credible information about what elected leaders do, we
cannot effectively exercise our right to vote.”
87
In other words, denying citi-
zens credible information results in the diminishment of political autonomy
(i.e., citizens’ capacity to partake in meaningful democratic deliberation),
88
because it results in a widespread state of confusion in which objects of
public deliberation become less discernible and standards of public justifica-
tion become increasingly arbitrary. Furthermore, Rorty willfully facilitated
the occurrence of this particular harm by arguing for the adoption of the
post-truth agenda and popularizing certain aspects of post-truth rhetoric.
Returning to our previous definition of “post-truth” as “related to or denoting
circumstances in which objective facts are less influential in shaping pub-
lic opinion than appeals to emotion and personal belief,” it should be clear
that any contribution made by Rorty’s words to encourage others to forego
discussions of fact in favor of emotionally compelling narratives in public
discourse would make him complicit with other, more rhetorically powerful
actors who share this common goal.
But here one might resist the charge of complicity on the grounds that it
assumes an erroneous account of Rorty’s intentions. While the early Rorty
may have been overly romantic in his calls to give up talk of matters of fact
in the public domain, the mature Rorty recognized that this romanticism
should only apply in private: in our private activities (such as poetry and
philosophy), where aesthetic sensibility and emotional development take pri-
ority, freedom of self-creation reigns; in our public activities (such as science
and politics), communal norms of justification and liberal consensus-seeking
are to remain unchanged (i.e., pursing greater solidarity leads to contingent
justification among an ever-widening group while preserving how we ordi-
narily speak about justification and truth); or so the argument goes. Certainly,
Something Has Cracked
18
in some moods, the mature Rorty seems to want his readers to reject the
pursuit of certainty, objectivity, truth, or a final vocabulary in philosophy
and other private musings, but allow citizens to seek inter-subjective agree-
ment within their own terms (including local claims to truth and fact), as
well as permitting scientists and social scientists to function as they normally
would by seeking knowledge in a manner which they would recognize as
being objective (although still only in the sense of being the object of an
inter-subjective agreement).
89
Or as Richard Shusterman puts it:
[The public/private split] performs [Rorty’s] postmodern
remapping of modernity’s tripartite schema of science, art and
the ethico-political into a dualism of public discourse based
on normalcy and consensus versus a private discursive sphere
aimed at radical innovation and individual fulfilment.
90
However, even in his mature writings, Rorty is not always so discriminat-
ing.
91
For example, in Achieving Our Country (a part of his later works), he
begins with a discussion of the proper place of national pride in democratic
politics and rejects objectivity as a relevant goal in this matter. He thus
argues for selecting a narrative of national identity to cultivate an appropriate
amount of national pride to empower co-nationals to imagine how the nation
could be improved, without allowing such pride to escalate into unchecked
arrogance, bigotry, and imperialism. For Rorty, the selection of a narrative is
a matter of future-oriented choice, never a matter of objective knowledge of
one’s nation’s past. He writes:
[T]hough objectivity is a useful goal when one is trying to cal-
culate means to ends by predicting the consequences of action,
it is of little relevance when one is trying to decide what sort
of person or nation to be. Nobody knows what it would be like
to try to be objective when attempting to decide what one’s
country really is, what its history really means, any more than
when answering the question of who one really is oneself,
what one’s individual past really adds up to.
92
In his view, we only ask such questions because they allow us to try out var-
ious self-conceptions that permit the contemplation of various futures; facts
about our past do not matter in the slightest. To illustrate his point, Rorty
contrasts the attitudes taken by James Baldwin and Elijah Muhammad to the
enslavement of black people by white Americans. While Elijah Muhammad’s
Something Has Cracked
19
Nation of Islam holds “that white people started out as homunculi created
by a diabolical scientist,” James Baldwin maintained that “we, the black and
white, deeply need each other here if we are really to become a nation—if we
are really, that is, to achieve our identity, our maturity, as men and women.”
For Rorty, the significant difference between these two visions is that the
former is wedded to a politics of spectatorship while the latter is wedded to
a politics of engagement, not that the former is false and that latter is at least
more likely to be true. While this focus on participation is laudable, Rorty
contends that there is no point in arguing about which view is more accurate,
because both “are intelligible. Either can be made plausible. But there are no
neutral, objective criteria which dictate one rather than the other.”
93
For him,
the same lack of grounds for epistemic adjudication holds between concep-
tions of America proposed by the political Left and those proposed by the
political Right.
94
This indicates that even the mature Rorty occasionally intends for his injunc-
tion to replace talk of objectivity or “facts of the matter” with talk of better
or worse narratives that can be made to look better or worse depending on
how we describe them to apply in the realm of politics.
95
Therefore, his intent
was (at least on some occasions) to convince others to dispense with strong
epistemic norms in the political arena.
However, intention alone is insufficient—the charge of complicity crucially
hinges on whether Rorty’s words actually played a role in causing or facili-
tating the rise of post-truth politics. That is why we must consider its causal
role more carefully.
Causation
Recently, Richard Evans, the historian and long-standing critic of postmod-
ernism, charged postmodernists with causal responsibility for the advent of
post-truth politics. Indeed, he wrote on Twitter:
Apostles of the “post-fact” era graduated from US universi-
ties in the era of postmodernism: Kellyanne Conway 1989,
Sean Spicer 1993 . . . If I am wrong, and postmodernist
disbelief in truth didn’t lead to our post-truth age, then how
do we explain the current disdain for facts?
96
In an interview with historian Deborah Lipstadt about the role he played
in the libel case opposing Holocaust denier David Irving (depicted in the
Something Has Cracked
20
film Denial), Evans further explained that he thinks that postmodernism’s
rejection of the importance and robustness of truth “affected a generation
of university graduates in the States.”
97
In other words, for him, the causal
responsibility of postmodernism for the post-truth age is a pedagogic fail-
ing caused by a discursive shift that led to an unhealthy suspicion of epis-
temic practices. The problem, however, with ascertaining causation is that it
invites the following question: Was the advent of postmodernism a necessary
condition for the rise of post-truth politics? The answer to that question is a
resounding “no.” More likely necessary conditions for the widespread ero-
sion of US and UK citizens’ concern for truth in politics include:
The social and cultural fragmentation caused by rampant income
inequality;
98
The normalization of what Wolfgang Streeck has called “the expert lie,”
which is the politically-motivated mobilization of expertise to assert
politically expedient falsehoods. According to Streeck, notable expert lies
include the Laffer Curve to justify reducing taxes on the very rich, the
European Commission’s “Cecchini Report” promising economic boons
in return for the “completion of the internal market,” and pre-2008 assur-
ances of US financial experts—including Ben Bernanke, Alan Greenspan
and Larry Summers—that “government agencies had no need to take
action to prevent the growth of bubbles” in financial markets;
99
Public revelations of state mendacity (in addition to the instances Steve
Tesich noted in “Government of Lies,” Colin Powell’s infamous claims
about weapons of mass destruction in Iraq come to mind);
The algorithms and norms that regulate our use and experience of social
media, which have given rise to ever-new ways of deceiving one another
(as captured by the idiom “catfishing”
100
);
The rolling “crisis of traditional journalism” marked by audience frag-
mentation, commercial pressure (resulting in a loss of stable revenue for
print journalism), increased political polarization, and loss of trust in the
media’s general commitment to the public good;
101
Systems of primary and secondary education designed to foster testing
results rather than student understanding and critical thinking;
102
and,
A recalcitrant anti-intellectualism coupled with an ardent devotion to a
superficial, market-driven, all too often short-term, pseudo-practical mind-
set (or what Richard Hofstadter called “the mystique of practicality”
103
).
However, adopting a probabilistic account of causation invites considering an
alternative question: Did an event (i.e., the rise of postmodernism in certain
Something Has Cracked
21
academic fields) increase the antecedent likelihood of a particular phenome-
non (i.e., post-truth politics) coming to pass? More to the point, has Rorty’s
work increased the antecedent likelihood of the rise of post-truth politics to
prominence? If we take the successes of the Trump and Leave campaigns to
be the causes of current disregard for epistemic standards in public debate
in the US and UK, respectively, then Rorty likely played no significant role
in facilitating these events—as far as we know, key actors in the Trump and
Leave campaigns were not avid Rorty readers seeking to implement his phil-
osophical visions.
104
However, if we see the success of these campaigns as the
consequences of a wider sociological reality where epistemic norms play a
diminished role, then it is not unreasonable to think that Rorty may have con-
tributed (however marginally) to the likelihood that citizens would be more
open to dismissing the significance of public representatives brazenly failing
to adhere to traditional epistemic norms. And yet, he may well have caused
others still to defend their attachment to traditional epistemic norms yet more
firmly. Thus, ascribing more than an extremely limited role to Rorty in facili-
tating (i.e., making more likely) the rise of post-truth politics faces a difficult
climb. Therefore, in the absence of strong empirical evidence pointing to
such a causal link, prudence requires that we abstain from a hasty conclusion.
The causal charge must therefore be rejected at this stage and, along with it,
the charge of complicity. But what are we to make of complacency?
Complacency
Complacency is defined as “self-satisfaction especially when accompanied
with unawareness of actual dangers or deficiencies.”
105
According to Jason
Kawall, “[c]omplacency is a vice that does not cause evil or mediocrity; it is
a vice that allows these to exist.”
106
To be concerned about complacency is to
agree with John Kenneth Galbraith that “[i]n all life one should comfort the
afflicted, but verily, also, one should afflict the comfortable, and especially
when they are comfortably, contentedly, even happily wrong.”
107
In this con-
text, to charge Rorty’s philosophical project with complacency is to accuse
it of failing to demonstrate an awareness of, and thus of failing to effectively
challenge, important threats to the realization of its moral vision. As we have
seen, Rorty’s ethnocentric liberalism aims to liberate creative energies so as
to bring more and more people into a broader community of solidarity, united
by nothing more than a common conversation, endlessly renewed thanks to a
shared awareness of the contingency of any one final vocabulary.
At a theoretical level, Rorty’s hope that this free-floating conversation
would naturally bolster liberal values has been thoroughly challenged by
Something Has Cracked
22
many critics. For example, Norman Geras contends that Rorty’s ironism
is problematic for justice because “whatever the conception, to operate
principles of justice, you need to know what has happened or is the case,
under some passable interpretation of it within the multiplicity of these
that there must, of course, always be.”
108
Richard Bernstein points out that
even if we accept that our standards of justification are constrained by the
social practices of our existing communities, Rorty’s “obsession” with
endlessly underlining the contingency of our moral and epistemic commit-
ments gets in the way of taking part in the very practical task of arguing
with our peers about how “to discriminate the better from the worse”
109
within our current social practices.
110
Jeffrey Isaac criticizes Rorty’s liberal
ironism on the grounds that it is impractical to “allow ourselves to remain
captives of the current state of affairs” when such a state of affairs demands
thorough-going critique.
111
These criticisms point to the potential danger of irrationalism and quiescence
within Rorty’s work in the face of serious political challenge. When con-
fronting post-truth politics, this danger becomes actual. We must therefore
ask: Can Rorty’s liberal ironism provide any grounds to challenge post-truth
politics? Let us take a practical example. Consider the following claims made
by Trump in 2017 and their rebuttals by the New York Times (in parentheses
after each statement):
January 23: “Between 3 million and 5 million illegal votes caused me to
lose the popular vote.” (There’s no evidence of illegal voting.)
January 25: “Now, the audience was the biggest ever. But this crowd
was massive. Look how far back it goes. This crowd was massive.”
(Official aerial photos show Obama’s 2009 inauguration was much more
heavily attended.)
January 26: “We’ve taken in tens of thousands of people. We know
nothing about them. They can say they vet them. They didn’t vet them.
They have no papers. How can you vet somebody when you don’t know
anything about them and you have no papers? How do you vet them? You
can’t.” (Vetting lasts up to two years.)
February 7: “And yet the murder rate in our country is the highest it’s
been in 47 years, right? Did you know that? Forty-seven years.” (It was
higher in the 1980s and ’90s.)
Something Has Cracked
23
One may be tempted to dismiss Trump’s claims on the grounds that they
are purposefully mendacious.
112
But let us assume that they are expressed
in earnest. We must thus ask ourselves: Ought we to believe Trump’s
claims or the Times rebuttals? Again, one may be tempted to merely
dismiss Trump’s claims because there is no evidence that they are true.
Yet, many people do indeed choose to believe them. Still putting to one
side the charge of lying or deceit, I and many others want to say that
belief in these claims is misplaced as it is—at the very best—the product
of wishful-thinking, confusion, or mistake. But it is not clear that Rorty’s
philosophical commitments warrant such a conclusion. Why not? In short,
because those who believe Trump’s statements often claim to be doing
so because his claims match their sense of what is true, regardless of the
absence of traditional standards of evidence. Worse still, some claim that
traditional epistemic norms do not apply because these merely express the
interests of another community—the so-called “elite.”
113
On this account, we might conjecture that we are confronting two distinct
epistemic communities: E1, for whom there is a fact of the matter which
makes certain claims true or false and for whom presenting evidence, making
logical arguments, and drawing on expertise are legitimate means of seeking
to ascertain which is which; and E2, for whom there is either no fact of the
matter about a whole series of important claims and/or for whom evidence,
logics, and experts cannot be trusted to determine specific facts. We must
therefore ask ourselves: What are the legitimate grounds for adjudicating
between these communities? By what criteria can we establish that certain
claims are indeed true while others are false? Which group has the epistemic
authority to correct the other?
In response, Rorty’s work presents us with three potential answers:
A. Members of E1 and E2 are equally legitimate in their epistemic stances
(since there is no non-neutral way of adjudicating between vocabularies).
B. Members of E2 are more legitimate in their epistemic stance because they
are better ironists, in the sense that they are more acutely aware of the
contingency of claims to knowledge than E1—i.e., members of E2 believe
Trump but in a mode that makes no claim to “facts of the matter.”
C. The epistemic standards of E1 and E2 are not the relevant sources of
authority for determining which community is to be believed; rather, we
ought to accept the epistemic standards of the group that politically aims
to minimize suffering.
Something Has Cracked
24
Neither A nor B give us grounds to reject E2, but I suspect that a Rortyan
might opt for C because, while the liberal ironist may well have little to say
about the wrongs of post-truth politics simpliciter, they would vehemently
object to the political project of Trumpism which mobilizes post-truth pol-
itics in order to visit unnecessary suffering and humiliation on many disad-
vantaged groups (such as people of color, women, undocumented migrant
residents, etc.).
However, I contend that this argument only moves the problem further
down the field. Why? The political project associated with Trumpism
claims to be standing up for a community that it considers to be under-
served, suffering, and oppressed—namely, white communities, and espe-
cially white men. Speaking at Texas A&M University, Richard Spencer,
arguably the leading ideologue of Trump’s far-Right white supremacist sup-
port base, said that the Left had taken control of the culture and intended to
destroy “white racial identity” with “an undifferentiated global population,
[a] raceless, genderless, identity-less, meaningless population consuming
sugar, consuming drugs, while watching porn.”
114
While supporters of this
view often consider Islam to be the immediate enemy of white western
civilization, they claim the wider enemy, the main source of their purported
oppression, is “globalism.” According to Trump campaign press secretary,
Hope Hicks, globalism is:
An economic and political ideology which puts allegiance
to international institutions ahead of the nation-state; seeks
the unrestricted movement of goods, labor and people across
borders; and rejects the principle that the citizens of a coun-
try are entitled to preference for jobs and other economic
considerations as a virtue of their citizenship.
115
By the campaign’s account, globalism caused the Great Recession, the rise in
opioid addiction in white working-class communities, the closure of factories
in white post-industrial parts of the Rust Belt, and the general weakening
of the grip on power of white working men in America. More conspiratori-
ally, some Trump supporters insist that this process is consciously enacted
by powerful but shady interest groups including global banks, prominent
Jewish people (such as George Soros), as well as powerful figures (such as
Presidents Barack Obama and George W. Bush, and the United Nations).
116
According to Lauren Southern, a host on the Right-wing Canadian media site
Rebel Media:
Something Has Cracked
25
Globalists almost always sneer down their nose at tradition,
disdain national culture, laugh at religion and generally
despise the West while holding a creepy affection for the
third world […] They want open borders, cheap labor, and
antinationalism to benefit their business and political visions,
and are all too willing to shaft the little people to achieve it.
117
In other words, many members of E2 consider themselves to be the vic-
tims of cruelty visited upon them by “globalists.” Moreover, they mobilize
ungrounded and conspiratorial narratives to explain why they are experi-
encing various forms of disadvantage. This, in turn, motivates and justifies
their appetite for what they consider to be a kind of redress against minorities
(most notably Muslims, Native Americans, African Americans, Latinx peo-
ple, women, and members of the LGBTQ+ community).
The crux of the matter for Rorty’s liberal ironist, presumably, has to involve
determining which community stands to suffer most: white people under
the yoke of globalism or members of the minority groups and communities
whose lives, dignity, and livelihoods are at risk as a result of Trump’s polit-
ical agenda? And yet, the specter of incommensurability haunts the Rortyan
here, because it is not clear that they can ascertain which group stands to
suffer most. Since they resist establishing criteria, moral or epistemic, that
would permit us to establish which is greater than the other, we are left
merely with a cacophony of claims and no means to establish which are more
serious than the others. In other words, looking across various epistemic
communities, the liberal ironist cannot distinguish actual suffering from the
mere complaint of suffering. For them, each claim is as good as the next.
However, in response, I think the Rortyan might change tack and say that it
is not the reduction of suffering which would guide their rejection of E2’s
standards but their commitment to tolerance. In “Rationality and Cultural
Difference,” Rorty defines rationality in three ways: Rationality
1
consists
in instrumental rationality; Rationality
2
“establishes an evaluative hierarchy
rather than simply adjusting means to taken-for-granted ends”; Rationality
3
“is roughly synonymous with tolerance—with the ability not to be overly
disconcerted by differences from oneself, not to respond aggressively to such
differences. This ability goes along with a willingness to alter one’s own
habits—not only to get more of what one previously wanted but to reshape
oneself into a different sort of person, one who wants different things than
before.” Rorty explains that Rationality
3
“goes along with a reliance on
Something Has Cracked
26
persuasion rather than force, an inclination to talk things over rather than
to fight, burn, or banish.”
118
The liberal ironist will likely avoid criticizing
Trumpists for lacking in Rationality
1
(because they clearly do not) and
Rationality
2
(because the ironist does not believe that such hierarchies can
be established), but they can criticize the Trumpists for lacking in Rational-
ity
3
. In other words, Trumpism fails to be rational in the sense that it is more
willing to exclude and fight than to include and talk.
At first glance, this seems to go some way towards providing grounds to
criticize the most politically destructive aspects of the Trumpist political
project (for example, attempting to ban millions of Muslim people from
entering the US on the basis of a possible relationship to Syria, Libya, Iran,
Yemen, Chad, and Somalia;
119
threatening to deport “Dreamers” by ending the
Deferred Action for Childhood Arrivals program;
120
demonstrating sympathy
towards white supremacist groups;
121
sanctioning violence against dissent-
ers;
122
and threatening the media
123
). However, Trump and many of his sup-
porters regularly present themselves as the defenders of peace and civility,
arguing that “the other side” is instigating violence or constraining their right
to free speech.
124
While I believe that such claims are entirely spurious (as
well as purposefully misleading and mobilized for highly strategic political
effect),
125
Rorty cannot establish the falsehood of such claims without first
determining which community’s epistemic standards to adopt in order to
evaluate them. Yet, since we need to know which claims are true and which
are false regarding each community’s commitment to tolerance, conversation,
and persuasion to establish which community best respects Rationality
3
,
the
mere invocation of tolerance, conversation, and peacefulness is insufficient
to effectively reject the claims of an epistemic community that believes itself
to be attached to them, but in fact, is not.
126
Rorty is therefore trapped in a
justificatory circle, once again left with conflicting claims made by different
epistemic communities and no stable ground from which to determine which
are more justified. This is practically problematic because it leaves the door
open to the practical possibility of wedding even the most thorough-going
ironism with authoritarian goals. Ultimately, it is this failure to seriously
consider (in the face of repeated warnings) the possibility that a community
committed to an illiberal and oppressive political agenda could draw on the
ironist’s skepticism to explain and defend itself that makes Rorty’s philo-
sophical project complacent about the dangers of post-truth politics.
Something Has Cracked
27
Conclusion
We have seen that Rorty’s romanticism led him to hope that widespread
ironism would generate a kinder, more compassionate liberal culture. I have
argued that our present moment of post-truth politics (in the US and in the
UK) has shown us that an overly-contingent epistemic stance (such as that of
the ironist) is compatible with illiberal political projects. Even though Rorty
wished for the advent of a public discussion where questions of fact, objec-
tivity, and truth, would be less significant, since his philosophical oeuvre is
not likely to have played a causal role in enabling or facilitating the advent of
post-truth politics, he is not complicit with the rise of post-truth politics. Ulti-
mately, however, it is Rorty’s failure to articulate criteria by which we can
determine which community’s epistemic standards are preferable to those of
other communities that demonstrates that his project was complacent towards
the dangers of post-truth politics.
In response, I suspect Rorty would have accused me of asking too much of
him. Indeed, he wrote:
It is unfortunate, I think, that many people hope for a tighter
link between philosophy and politics than there is or can be.
In particular, people on the left keep hoping for a philosoph-
ical view which cannot be used by the political right, one
which will lend itself only to good causes. But there never
will be such a view; any philosophical view is a tool which
can be used by many different hands.
127
Yet, it is precisely his failure to seriously attend to the possibility that a
part of his philosophical project (i.e., ironist ethnocentrism) could be mobi-
lized with great effect against another part of his philosophical project (i.e.,
liberalism), which constitutes Rorty’s pragmatic failing. Charles Sanders
Peirce’s formulation of the pragmatic maxim states: “Consider what effects,
which might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of
our conception to have. Then, our conception of those effects is the whole of
our conception of the object.”
128
As a pragmatist, it behooved Rorty to con-
sider the ‘conceivable’ practical bearings of his philosophical project. Had
he attended more carefully to the possibility that asserting the contingency
of our epistemic standards could be used to denigrate and, at times, stop
conversation, perhaps Rorty would have worried about the rise of the kind of
post-truth politics we see today.
Something Has Cracked
28
Is the upshot of my argument that we have no other choice but to return to
an unreformed faith in naïve appeals to pure facts, perfect objectivity, and
ultimate truth? No, it is not. But my argument does suggest that critique of
traditional epistemic norms must be well-motivated, thorough in its consid-
eration of viable alternatives, and careful to bolster (not diminish) the signifi-
cance of democratic conversation.
Something Has Cracked
29
Notes
1. Richard Rorty, Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century
America (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998), 89–90 (hereafter
cited as AOC).
2. Edward Helmore, “‘Something Will Crack’: The Supposed Prophecy of Donald
Trump Goes Viral,” Guardian, November 19, 2016, accessed October 28, 2017,
https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/nov/19/donald-trump-us-election
-prediction-richard-rorty; Jennifer Senior, “Richard Rorty’s 1998 Book Sug-
gested Election 2016 Was Coming,” New York Times, November 20, 2016,
accessed November 17, 2017, https://www.nytimes.com/2016/11/21/books
/richard-rortys-1998-book-suggested-election-2016-was-coming.html.
3. Some people refer to the political movement around Trump as “Bannonism”
rather than “Trumpism” to underscore the influence of Steve Bannon on
Trump’s political project (and, perhaps, for those who doubt Trump’s capacity
for actual decision-making, to cast doubt about his rational agency in shaping
this agenda). I prefer to call it “Trumpism” because core elements of the agenda
chronologically preceded Bannon’s involvement in the Trump campaign, but
also because Bannon agrees with this assessment—in a recent interview with
the New York Times Bannon said that Trump is “the leader of this movement
[…] because if you look back over the last 25 or 30 years, he has preached this
day in and day out. So he embodies it. He is also a charismatic leader. Some-
body who galvanizes people. […] I believe] he is a truly global revolutionary
figure.” From time mark 6:55 to 7:24 in the “Daily” podcast (November 10,
2017), accessed November 15, 2017, https://www.nytimes.com/2017/11/10/us
/politics/steve-bannon.html.
4. Frances Moore Lappé and Adam Eichen, Daring Democracy: Igniting Power,
Meaning and Connection for the America We Want (Boston: Beacon Press,
2017), 1–76.
5. Hillary Clinton, What Happened (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2017), 8–9.
6. Megan Carpentier, “Why Do People Dislike Hillary Clinton? The Story
Goes Far Back,” Guardian, October 18, 2016, accessed November 14, 2017,
https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/oct/18/hillary-clinton-why-hate
-unlikeable-us-election.
7. National Intelligence Council (US), Assessing Russian Activities and Intentions
in Recent US Elections (Washington, DC, 2017), accessed November 15, 2017,
https://www.dni.gov/files/documents/ICA_2017_01.pdf; Donna Brazile, Hacks
(New York: Simon & Schuster, 2017).
8. Nate Silver, “The Comey Letter Probably Cost Clinton the Election: So Why
Won’t the Media Admit as Much?” FiveThirtyEight, May 3, 2017, accessed
November 15, 2017, https://fivethirtyeight.com/features/the-comey-letter
-probably-cost-clinton-the-election/.
Something Has Cracked
30
9. On the racial dimension, see Ta-Nehisi Coates, We Were Eight Years in Power
(New York: One World, 2017), and “Trump Is the First White President,”
Atlantic, October 2017, accessed November 15, 2017, https://www.theatlantic.
com/magazine/archive/2017/10/the-first-white-president-ta-nehisi-coates/537909.
On the sexist dimension, see Mel Robbins, “Hillary Clinton Lost Because of
Sexism,” CNN (opinion) (May 3, 2017), accessed November 15, 2017, http://
www.cnn.com/2017/05/03/opinions/hillary-clinton-interview-sexism-robbins/
index.html.
10. Richard Rorty, AOC, 77.
11. Richard Rorty, AOC, 105.
12. Richard Rorty, AOC, 8.
13. Richard Rorty, AOC, 82 and 104.
14. Richard Rorty, AOC, 99; also, see his “First Projects, Then Principles,” Nation,
December 22, 1997.
15. Conor Friedersdorf, “The Book That Predicted Trump’s Rise Offers the Left a
Roadmap to Defeating Him,” Atlantic, July 6, 2017, accessed November 17,
2017, https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2017/07/advice-for-the-left
-on-achieving-a-more-perfect-union/531054.
16. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton (NJ): Princeton
University Press, 1979) (hereafter cited as PMN).
17. Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 197–202 (hereafter cited as
ORT).
18. See, for example, Paul Waldman, “How Donald Trump Is Turning the GOP into
a Postmodernist Party,” American Prospect, December 5, 2016, accessed
November 11, 2017, http://prospect.org/article/how-donald-trump-turning
-gop-postmodernist-party; Peter McKnight, “Trump as Postmodernist: Truth No
Longer Bound by Facts,” Globe and Mail, January 28, 2017, accessed March
19, 2018, https://www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/trump-as-postmodernist
-truth-no-longer-bound-by-facts/article33796581; Michael Gerson, “Conserva-
tives Defend Our Post-Truth President,” Register-Guard, October 25, 2017,
accessed March 19, 2018, http://registerguard.com/rg/opinion/36084624-78/
conservatives-defend-our-post-truth-president.html.csp; Andrew Calcutt, “The
Truth about Post-Truth Politics,” Newsweek, November 21, 2016, accessed
November 1, 2017, http://www.newsweek.com/truth-post-truth-politics-donald
-trump-liberals-tony-blair-523198.
19. Carole Cadwalladr, “Daniel Dennett: ‘I Begrudge Every Hour I Have to Spend
Worrying about Politics,’” Observer, February 12, 2017, accessed November
7, 2017, https://www.theguardian.com/science/2017/feb/12/daniel-dennett
-politics-bacteria-bach-back-dawkins-trump-interview.
20. Andrew Perrin, “Stop Blaming Postmodernism for Post-Truth Politics,”
Chronicle of Higher Education, August 4, 2017, accessed October 10, 2017,
https://www.chronicle.com/article/Stop-Blaming-Postmodernism-for/240845.
Something Has Cracked
31
21. The most significant contribution to date on this is Eduardo Mendietta’s
“Rorty and Post-Post-Truth” in the Los Angeles Review of Books, July 22,
2017, accessed November 17, 2017, https://lareviewofbooks.org/article/rorty
-and-post-post-truth/. Here, Mendietta argues elegantly that Rorty holds two
conceptions of truth: one that is private and unimportant and one that is public
and of civic significance. To his credit, Mendietta points out that Rorty’s second
version of truth all too often remains inchoate. I discuss this issue in sections
II and III, but I should let it be clear here that I think Rorty’s insistence on dis-
missing epistemic standards (such as objectivity or truth) even when he writes
about politics renders this distinction ultimately unhelpful.
22. Michel Foucault, for one, doubted that it was, saying in an interview, “What are
we calling postmodernity? I’m not up to date . . . I do not understand what kind
of problem is common to the people we call postmodern or poststructuralist,” in
Lawrence D. Kritzman, ed., Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and Other
Writings, 1977–1984, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Routledge, 1988), 33–34.
23. Richard Rorty, Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers Volume
2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 1 (hereafter cited as EHO).
24. Machiavelli, for one, suggested that lies and deception ought to play such
a significant role in politics: “A wise lord cannot, nor ought he to, keep his
promises when such observance would place him at a disadvantage, and when
the reasons for which he gave his word no longer exist.” In The Prince, trans.
Maurizio Viroli (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 60.
25. For an excellent discussion on the nature of this phenomenon, see Christopher
Robichaud, “Facts Aren’t Enough to Save Liberal Democracy,” Niskanen Cen-
ter (blog), January 17, 2017, accessed January 9, 2018, https://niskanencenter
.org/blog/facts-arent-enough-save-liberal-democracy/.
26. The website for Oxford Dictionaries, “Word of the Year 2016 Is…” page,
accessed November 8, 2017, https://en.oxforddictionaries.com/word-of-the
-year/word-of-the-year-2016.
27. See, for example: Matthew D’Ancona, Post-Truth: The New War on Truth and
How to Fight Back (London: Ebury, 2017), e-book; Jonathan Rose, “Brexit,
Trump, and Post-Truth Politics,” Public Integrity, Vol. 19, No. 6, 555–558;
Michael Peters, “Education in a Post-Truth World,” Educational Philosophy
and Theory, Vol. 49, No. 6, 563–566.
28. Steve Tesich, “Government of Lies,” Nation, January 13, 1992.
29. Ibid., 13.
30. Ibid., 14. Moreover, Tesich cites President George H.W. Bush: “[The] moral
dimension of American policy requires us to […] chart a moral course through
a world of lesser evils. That’s the real world, not black and white. Very few
moral absolutes,” 13.
31. To be clear, this is a contingent, not a logical, claim. In this article, I am
not concerned with arguments pertaining to whether or not metaphysical
or metaethical anti-realism necessarily undermine the practical purchase of
Something Has Cracked
32
moral claims. Rather, my argument is contingent all the way down: given
the fact that the diminishment of widespread popular concern with epis-
temic norms and practices in politics happens to have gone together with
a diminishment of the ambition of politically live moral options in the UK
and the US, this poses a pragmatic challenge to Rorty’s romantic hope that
ironism might bolster a more thoroughly kind, liberal, and compassionate
political order.
32. By “traditional epistemic norms,” I mean little more than what Robert Talisse
calls “the norms of truth and responsiveness.” These consist of the following:
“being a believer commits one to aspiring to truth”; “aspiring to truth” demands
that we respond “appropriately to reasons.” “[Therefore] responsible believing
calls us to the social enterprise of examining, exchanging, testing, and challeng-
ing reasons.” “Saving Pragmatist Democratic Theory (from Itself),” Ethics &
Politics 12, No. 1 (2010), 20.
33. Ruud Koopmans and Paul Statham, “Ethnic and Civic Conceptions of Nation-
hood and the Differential Success of the Extreme Right in Germany and Italy,”
in How Social Movements Matter, ed. M. Giugni, D. McCadam, and C. Tilly
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999), 228. Special thanks to
Markus Holdo for pointing me in the direction of this important concept.
34. Holly McCammon, Harmony Newman, Courtney Sanders Muse, and Teresa
Terrell, “Movement Framing and Discursive Opportunity Structures: The Polit-
ical Successes of the U.S. Women’s Jury Movements,” American Sociological
Review 72, No. 5 (2007), 731.
35. On framing more generally, see George Lakoffs The All New Don’t Think of An
Elephant! Know Your Values and Frame the Debate (White River Junction, VT:
Chelsea Green Publishing, 2014).
36. Gove insists that he was in fact trying to be specific rather than general in his
objection. His statement reads: “I think that the people of this country have had
enough of experts with organisations from acronyms saying […] that they know
what is best and getting it consistently wrong, because these people […] are the
same ones who got it consistently wrong.” See Ian Katz, “Have We Fallen Out
of Love with Experts?” BBC News, February 27, 2017, accessed September 9,
2017, http://www.bbc.com/news/uk-39102840.
37. Gove did add, however, “I’m not asking the public to trust me. I’m asking
them to trust themselves.” This falls rather close to an outright rejection of
the value of expertise in democratic decision making. See Henry Mance,
“Britain Has Had Enough of Experts, says Gove,” Financial Times, June 3,
2016, accessed November 15, 2017, https://www.ft.com/content/3be49734
-29cb-11e6-83e4-abc22d5d108c.
38. Jennifer Rubin, “Interviewers Cannot Let Trump’s Lies Fly By,” Washington Post,
December 5, 2016, accessed September 8, 2017, https://www.washingtonpost
.com/blogs/right-turn/wp/2016/12/05/interviewers-cannot-let-the-lies-fly-by/.
Something Has Cracked
33
39. Ibid.
40. Alexandra Jaffe, “Kellyanne Conway: WH Spokesman Gave ‘Alternative Facts’
on Inauguration Crowd,” NBC News, January 22, 2017, accessed December
11, 2017, https://www.nbcnews.com/storyline/meet-the-press-70-years/wh
-spokesman-gave-alternative-facts-inauguration-crowd-n710466.
41. Christopher Rosen, “All the Times Donald Trump Has Called the Media ‘Fake
News’ on Twitter,” Entertainment Weekly, June 27, 2017, accessed November
10, 2017, http://ew.com/tv/2017/06/27/donald-trump-fake-news-twitter/.
42. Julia Hunt, “‘Fake News’ Named Collins Dictionary Word of the Year for
2017,” Independent, November 2, 2017, accessed November 15, 2017, http://
www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/fake-news-word-of-the-year
-2017-collins-dictionary-donald-trump-kellyanne-conway-antifa-corbynmania
-a8032751.html.
43. Daniel Dale and Tanya Talaga, “Donald Trump: The Unauthorized Database
of False Things,” Toronto Star, November 4, 2016, accessed November 15,
2017, https://www.thestar.com/news/world/uselection/2016/11/04/donald-trump
-the-unauthorized-database-of-false-things.html.
44. Mattathias Schwartz, “‘Facts Are in the Eyes of the Beholder,’ Says Roger Stone,
Trump Confidant,” Intercept, March 6, 2017, accessed November 15, 2017,
https://theintercept.com/2017/03/06/facts-are-in-the-eye-of-the-beholder-says
-roger-stone-trump-confidante-in-exclusive-interview/.
45. Richard Rorty, PMN, 176.
46. Richard Rorty, ORT, 177.
47. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope (London: Penguin Books, 1999),
xxiii (hereafter cited as PSH).
48. Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1989), 73 (hereafter cited as CIS).
49. Neil Gross recounts this slow but dramatic conversion in detail and underlines
the influence of Thomas Kuhn’s philosophy of science as well as the reality of
academic politics in Richard Rorty: The Making of an American Philosopher
(Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2008), 198–233.
50. Matthew Festenstein, “Richard Rorty: Pragmatism, Irony and Liberalism,” in
Richard Rorty: Critical Dialogues, ed. M. Festenstein and S. Thompson (Cam-
bridge: Polity, 2001), 1 (book hereafter cited as Critical Dialogues).
51. John Horton, “Richard Rorty: Pragmatism, Irony and Liberalism,” in Critical
Dialogues, 15.
52. Richard Rorty, EHO, 1.
53. Matthew Festenstein, in Critical Dialogues, 8. Moreover, Richard Shuster-
man explains that “since Habermas identifies the postmodern with Nietzsche,
Rorty’s terminological substitution does not affect the sense of their debate
[about the desirability of overcoming the Enlightenment’s pursuit of episte-
mological foundations],” “Reason and Aesthetics: Habermas and Rorty,” in
Critical Dialogues, 149.
Something Has Cracked
34
54. William James, Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, MA: Har-
vard University Press, 1975), 106.
55. Richard Rorty, Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 3 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), 2 (hereafter cited as TP).
56. Richard Rorty, TP, 21–22.
57. Richard Rorty, CIS, 6.
58. This claim arguably constitutes Rorty’s neo-pragmatism’s most substantial
point of departure from classical pragmatism. While Charles Sanders Peirce’s
idealized definition of truth as the belief that awaits us at the end of inquiry
(provided that we inquire long enough and well enough) stands in starkest
contrast to Rorty, neither James nor Dewey held that the justification or indeed
the truth of a proposition was entirely contingent on the existing epistemic stan-
dards of an actual community.
59. Richard Rorty, “Putnam and the Relativist Menace,” Journal of Philosophy 90,
No. 9 (1993), 448–449 (hereafter cited as PRM).
60. Ibid., 449.
61. Richard Rorty, CIS, 54–55.
62. Richard Rorty, PRM, 443.
63. Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1984), 185, as cited by Rorty in ORT, 6.
64. Richard Rorty, ORT, 21–34.
65. Ibid., 193.
66. Ibid., 22.
67. Ibid., 193–194: “I should argue that in recent history of liberal societies, the
willingness to view matters aesthetically—to be content to indulge in what
Schiller called ‘play’ and to discard what Nietzsche called ‘the spirit of serious-
ness’—has been an important vehicle of moral progress.”
68. Ibid., 198.
69. Ibid., 199.
70. Richard Rorty, CIS, 40: “The final victory of poetry in its ancient quarrel with
philosophy—the final victory of metaphors of self-creation over metaphors of
discovery—would consist in our becoming reconciled to the thought that this
is the only sort of power over the world which we can hope to have. For that
would be the final abjuration of the notion that truth, and not just power and
pain, is to be found out there.”
71. Richard Rorty, ORT, 191–2.
72. Ibid., 192–193.
73. Jean Bethke Elshtain, “Don’t Be Cruel: Reflections on Rortyan Liberalism,” in
The Politics of Irony, eds. D.W. Conway and J.E. Seery (New York: St Martins,
1992), 199–217; Rorty approvingly quotes Judith Shklars claim that, for liber-
als, “cruelty is the worst thing,” in CIS, 74.
74. See Richard Rorty, PSH, 77–83, but especially 81: “From this point of view,
moral progress is not a matter of an increase of rationality—a gradual
Something Has Cracked
35
diminution of the influence of prejudice and superstition, permitting us to see
our moral duty more clearly. Nor is it what Dewey called an increase of
intelligence, that is, increasing one’s skill at inventing courses of action which
simultaneously satisfy many conflicting demands. People can be very intelli-
gent, in this sense, without having wide sympathies. It is neither irrational nor
unintelligent to draw the limits of one’s moral community at a national, or
racial, or gender border. But it is undesirable—morally undesirable. So it is best
to think of moral progress as a matter of increasing sensitivity increasing
responsiveness to the needs of a larger and larger variety of people and things.
Just as the pragmatists see scientific progress not as the gradual attenuation of a
veil of appearance which hides the intrinsic nature of reality from us, but as the
increasing ability to respond to the concerns of ever larger groups of people—in
particular, the people who carry out ever more acute observations and perform
ever more refined experiments—so they see moral progress as a matter of being
able to respond to the needs of ever more inclusive groups of people.”
75. Richard Rorty, CIS, xvi.
76. Richard Rorty, ORT, 193.
77. Ibid., 187.
78. Richard Rorty, TP, 205.
79. Richard Rorty, ORT, 193.
80. Ibid., 200–1.
81. Richard Rorty, PSH, 168–74.
82. Richard Rorty, CIS, 73–4.
83. See, for example, Matthew Festenstein, “Ethnocentrism and Irony,” in Richard
Rorty: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers, Vol. IV, ed. J. Tartaglia
(New York: Routledge, 2009), 100–6 (hereafter cited as Critical Assessments).
84. These were helpfully distinguished by Philip Conway, “Post-Truth, Complicity
and International Politics,” E-International Relations, March 29, 2017, accessed
November 15, 2017, http://www.e-ir.info/2017/03/29/post-truth-complicity-and
-international-politics/.
85. Ibid., 2.
86. Gregory Mellema, Complicity and Moral Accountability (Notre Dame: Univer-
sity of Notre Dame Press, 2016), 56.
87. Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt, How Democracies Die: What History
Reveals About Our Future (London: Viking, 2018), 199.
88. For more on “political autonomy,” see Joshua Cohen, “For a Democratic Soci-
ety,” in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003), 86–138.
89. For example, when asked point blank: “How would you define truth in terms
of its function in public life?” Rorty answers, “There are two questions here. I
think that what people really worry about is truthfulness. They think they are
being lied to all the time, and usually they are right. They are being lied to. And
they wish that people would tell them the truth. But what they mean here is not
Something Has Cracked
36
a question of the nature of truth. They just want people to say what they believe,
governments to say the same things to the public that they say to other govern-
ments, and so on. Truth as a philosophical problem is a question of whether true
statements are representations of reality, or whether the notion of representation
applies to statements, and so on. This is really technical.” In “There Is a Crisis
Coming—Interview with Zbigniew Stanczyk,” in Take Care of Freedom and
Truth Will Take Care of Itself, ed. E. Mendietta (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2006), 57.
90. Richard Shusterman, “Reason and Aesthetics between Modernity and Postmo-
dernity: Habermas and Rorty,” in Critical Dialogues, 146.
91. For an important discussion of the evolution in Rorty’s public/private romanti-
cism see Martin Mueller, “From Irony to Robust Serenity—Pragmatic Politics
of Religion and Rorty,” Contemporary Pragmatism 14, No. 3, 334–349.
92. Richard Rorty, AOC, 11.
93. Ibid., 13.
94. I strongly suspect that Baldwin would take issue with this, since, in some places,
he affirms—pace Rorty—that facing unpleasant truths is necessary if we are
to begin to tell a story of how we might change the realities expressed by such
truths. Consider, for example, “As Much Truth as One Can Bear,” New York
Times Book Review, 1962, reprinted in The Cross of Redemption: Uncollected
Writings, ed. and introduction by Randall Kenan (New York: Pantheon, 2010), 42:
“Not everything that is faced can be changed. But nothing can be changed until it
is faced. […] Most of us are about as eager to change as we were to be born, and
go through our changes in a similar state of shock.” Also see “If Black English
Isn’t a Language, Then Tell Me, What Is?” New York Times, July 29, 1979,
accessed November 1, 2017, http://www.nytimes.com/books/98/03/29/specials
/baldwin-english.html: “The brutal truth is that the bulk of white people in Amer-
ica never had any interest in educating black people, except as this could serve
white purposes. It is not the black child’s language that is in question, it is not his
language that is despised: It is his experience. A child cannot be taught by anyone
who despises him, and a child cannot afford to be fooled. A child cannot be taught
by anyone whose demand, essentially, is that the child repudiate his experience,
and all that gives him sustenance, and enter a limbo in which he will no longer be
black, and in which he knows that he can never become white. Black people have
lost too many black children that way.”
95. Remaining for a moment within the African-American intellectual legacy, one
notes that even the notion that truth-talk should be reserved to some impersonal
“public sphere” is seriously challenged by Lorraine Hansberry’s opening of
To Be Young, Gifted and Black (New York: Signet, 1969), 45: “For some time
now—I think since I was a child—I have been possessed of the desire to put
down the stuff of my life. That is a commonplace impulse, apparently, among
persons of massive self-interest; sooner or later we all do it. And, I am quite
Something Has Cracked
37
certain, there is only one internal quarrel: how much of the truth to tell? How
much, how much, how much!” Special thanks to Cornel West for introducing
me to some of Baldwin’s and Hansberry’s writings with so much sensitivity,
joy, and interpretive zest.
96. As cited by Philip Conway, op. cit. note 84.
97. Harriet Swain, “Richard Evans Interview: The Film Denial ‘Shows There Is
Such a Thing as Truth,’” Guardian, February 14, 2017, accessed November
17, 2017, https://www.theguardian.com/education/2017/feb/14/richard-evans
-interview-holocaust-denial-film.
98. See, for example: Danny Dorling, Inequality and the 1% (London: Verso,
2014); Joseph Stiglitz, The Great Divide: Unequal Societies and What We
Can Do About Them (New York: W.W. Norton and Company, 2016); Robert
B. Reich, Saving Capitalism: For the Many Not the Few (New York: Vintage,
2016); Thomas Piketty, The Economics of Inequality, trans. Arthur Goldham-
mer (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap, 2015).
99. Wolfgang Streeck, “The Return of the Repressed,” in The Great Regression, ed.
Heinrich Geiselberger, (Malden, Mass.: Polity, 2017), 159–60.
100. Thanks to my “Life Worth Living” students for introducing me to this term.
101. See, for example, Paolo Mancini, “Media Fragmentation, Party Systems and
Democracy,” International Journal of Press/Politics 18, No. 1 (2013), 43–60;
Markus Prior, Post-Broadcast Democracy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 2007); Paul Starr, “An Unexpected Crisis: The News Media in Postindus-
trial Democracies,” International Journal of Press/Politics 17, 234–242.
102. See Gert J. Biesta, Good Education in an Age of Measurement: Ethics, Politics,
Democracy (New York: Routledge, 2010); Gert Biesta, “Why ‘What Works’
Still Won’t Work: From Evidence-Based Education to Value-Based Education,”
Studies in Philosophy and Education 29, No. 5 (2010), 491–503; Michael Field-
ing, “The Human Cost and Intellectual Poverty of High Performance School-
ing: Radical Philosophy, John Macmurray and the Remaking of Person-Centred
Education,” Journal of Education Policy 22, No. 4 (2007), 383–409. Special
thanks to Tim Herrick for introducing me to this important literature.
103. Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (Toronto: Vintage,
1966). Many thanks to Carrie Roush for pointing me in the direction of this
important book.
104. However, a widespread misconception regarding Trump supporters is that they
are primarily working class and under-educated (and therefore unlikely to have
ever been introduced to postmodernist intellectual themes). According to Nich-
olas Carnes and Noam Lupu, Trump’s supporters in the Republican primary
were mostly affluent people with a similar rate of college degrees as registered
Republicans more generally (approximately 30 percent). Moreover, Carnes and
Lupu add that the American National Election Study “showed that in Novem-
ber 2016, the Trump coalition looked a lot like it did during the primaries.”
Something Has Cracked
38
See their “It’s Time to Bust the Myth: Most Trump Voters Were Not Working
Class,” Washington Post, June 5, 2017, accessed February 2, 2018, https://
www.washingtonpost.com/news/monkey-cage/wp/2017/06/05/its-time-to-bust
-the-myth-most-trump-voters-were-not-working-class/.
105. Merriam-Webster, s.v. “Complacency (n.),” accessed September 19, 2017,
https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/complacency.
106. Jason Kawall, “On Complacency,” American Philosophical Quarterly 43, No. 4
(2006), 343.
107. John Kenneth Galbraith, “In Pursuit of the Simple Truth,” Guardian, July 28,
1989, as cited in Jason Kawall, ibid.
108. Norman Geras, “Language, Truth and Justice,” in Critical Assessments, 346. To
explain further, holding that the “fact of the matter” is the description that helps
us cope best, or the one that our peers let us get away with asserting, or one that
is merely coherent with regard to the rules of a specific language game, simply
eludes what is at stake when a citizen claims to be the victim of a miscarriage
of justice or when unrecognized victims level allegations against purported per-
petrators who in turn assert their own side of the story. In those circumstances,
justice hinges on one claim being closer to the facts than the other. Thus, Geras
contends that Rorty either abandons any robust concern for justice or unduly
helps himself to an idea of getting the world right.
109. Richard J. Bernstein, “Philosophy in the Conversation of Mankind,” in Critical
Assessments, 50.
110. In “One Step Forward, Two Steps Backward: Richard Rorty on Liberal Democ-
racy and Philosophy,” Political Theory 15, No. 4 (1987), 560, Bernstein warns
that Rorty’s unease with talk of “standards” or “criteria” to evaluate political
projects endangers the very project of defending an inclusive, egalitarian
liberal democratic ideal: “It is time that Rorty himself should appropriate the
lesson of Peirce, ‘Do not block the road to inquiry,’ and realize that rarified
meta-philosophical or meta-theoretical discussion can never be a substitute
for struggling to articulate, defend, and justify one’s vision of a just and good
society. Rorty, who has eloquently called for open conversation, fails to realize
how his rhetorical strategies tend to close off serious/playful conversation about
liberalism and democracy […] The pragmatic legacy (which Rorty constantly
invokes) will only be recovered and revitalized when we try to do for our time
what Dewey did in his historical context—to articulate, texture, and justify
[Bernstein’s italics] a vision of a pragmatically viable ideal of communal
democracy.”
111. Jeffrey Isaac, “Is the Revival of Pragmatism Practical, or What are the Con-
sequences of Pragmatism?” in A Pragmatist’s Progress? Richard Rorty and
American Intellectual History, ed. John Pettegrew (New York: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2000), 167.
112. Although Rorty seems to think, at times, that we can dismiss those who lie,
this is problematic because accusing someone of lying typically requires
Something Has Cracked
39
establishing both that the claim is false and that the speaker has the intention to
mislead their addressee. Part of the challenge with Trump is that his intentions
are rather hard to ascertain in any given context [for one line of explanation,
see The Dangerous Case of Donald Trump: 27 Psychiatrists and Mental Health
Experts Assess a President, ed. Bandy Lee (New York: St Martin’s, 2017)].
Moreover, above establishing intention, what is at stake here is determining by
what criteria Trump’s statements can be said to be false.
113. At least, that is one way of understanding the claims of various Right-wing
commentators. See for example, Ann Coulters In Trump We Trust: E Pluribus
Awesome (New York: Penguin, 2016), especially 1–37; Milo Yiannopoulos,
Dangerous (Boca Raton: Dangerous Books, 2017); and Danuta Kean, “Milo
Yiannopoulos Labels Low Sales Figures of Dangerous Memoir ‘Fake News,’”
Guardian, July 13, 2017, accessed November 17, 2017, https://www.theguardian
.com/books/2017/jul/13/milo-yiannopoulos-labels-low-sales-figures-of-dangerous
-memoir-fake-news. In fairness, a more reasonable way of interpreting much of
this is that many on the Right are involved in propaganda themselves (see, for
example, Carole Cadwalladr, “Robert Mercer: The Big Data Millionaire Waging
War on Mainstream Media,” Guardian, February 26, 2017, accessed November
17, 2017, https://www.theguardian.com/politics/2017/feb/26/robert-mercer
-breitbart-war-on-media-steve-bannon-donald-trump-nigel-farage. However, for
Rorty, the problem remains the following: How, on his view, are we to determine
who is telling the truth and who is propagandizing?
114. Michael Phillips, “The Elite Roots of Richard Spencers Racism,” Jacobin,
December 20, 2016, accessed November 17, 2017, https://www.jacobinmag
.com/2016/12/richard-spencer-alt-right-dallas-texas/.
115. Liam Stack, “Globalism: A Far-Right Conspiracy Theory Buoyed by Trump,”
New York Times, November 14, 2016, accessed November 17, 2017, https://
www.nytimes.com/2016/11/15/us/politics/globalism-right-trump.html.
116. Ibid.
117. Ibid.
118. Richard Rorty, “A Pragmatist View of Rationality and Cultural Difference,”
Philosophy East and West 42, No. 4, 581.
119. BBC News US/Canada, “Trump’s Executive Order: Who Does Travel Ban
Affect?” February 10, 2017, accessed November 17, 2017, http://www.bbc
.com/news/world-us-canada-38781302.
120. The outlook on this is not promising, but there is still some measure of hope
that a legislative solution might be found before Dreamers are threatened with
arrest and deportation. See Brian Bennett, “DACA Negotiations Slow as Trump
Demands More than Democrats Will Give,” Los Angeles Times, November 17,
2017, accessed November 17, 2017, http://www.latimes.com/politics/la-na-pol
-trump-daca-20171117-story.html.
121. Michael Shear and Maggie Haberman, “Trump Defends Initial Remarks on
Charlottesville; Again Blames “Both Sides,’” New York Times, August 15,
Something Has Cracked
40
2017, accessed November 17, 2017, https://www.nytimes.com/2017/08/15/us
/politics/trump-press-conference-charlottesville.html.
122. Kate Somers-Dawes, “All the Times Trump Has Called for Violence at His
Rallies,” March 12, 2016, accessed November 17, 2017, http://mashable.com
/2016/03/12/trump-rally-incite-violence/#1PoBEvGYIiqg.
123. Chris Cillizza, “Donald Trump just issued a direct threat to the free and inde-
pendent media,” CNN, October 12, 2017, accessed November 17, 2017, http://
www.cnn.com/2017/10/11/politics/donald-trump-media-tweet/index.html.
124. White supremacist activists (who often describe themselves as “alt-Right”) and
Right-wing Republicans (such as Ann Coulter) have been arguing that they are
the victims of censorship and that they are the true advocates of free and open
discussion. See, for example, Alheli Picazo, “How the Alt-Right Weaponized
Free Speech,” Macleans, May 1, 2017, accessed January 17, 2018, http://www
.macleans.ca/opinion/how-the-alt-right-weaponized-free-speech/. Moreover,
after a deadly vehicular attack on anti-racist protesters in Charlottesville, Vir-
ginia, on August 12, 2017, Trump maintained that the “alt-left” had been “very,
very violent” and that there was blame “on both sides.” See Shear and Haber-
man, 2017, accessed January 21, 2018, https://www.nytimes.com/2017/08/15
/us/politics/trump-press-conference-charlottesville.html.
125.
I agree with Jennifer Saul that Trump’s use of racial “figleaves” not only permit
him to appeal to racist voters, it also shifts the norms of public speech. See Jen-
nifer Saul, “Racial Figleaves, the Shifting Boundaries of the Permissible, and the
Rise of Donald Trump,” Philosophical Topics, Vol. 45, No. 2, 97–116 (2017).
126. While I suspect that few informed readers are likely to believe that Trump, his
political associates, and most of his supporters earnestly believe themselves
to be defenders of tolerance and civility, anecdotal evidence suggests that a
sizable number of Trump supporters do. See, for example: Tom McCarthy, “No
Regrets: One Year after They Voted for Trump,” Guardian, October 26, 2017,
accessed January 31, 2018, https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2017
/oct/26/no-regrets-one-year-after-they-voted-for-trump-has-he-delivered. In the
case of Brexit, many Leave voters were explicitly motivated by an attachment
to the parliamentarian value of sovereign self-determination, and others still
were motivated by a Left-wing analysis of the European Union’s attachment to
neoliberalism. In both groups, many citizens likely believed themselves to be—
rightly or wrongly—the defenders of civility, tolerance, and reasoned argument.
See, for example, Anonymous academic, “I Voted Brexit—Why Do Academic
Colleagues Treat Me Like a Pariah?” Guardian, September 15, 2017, accessed
January 2, 2018, https://www.theguardian.com/higher-education-network/2017
/sep/15/i-voted-for-brexit-why-do-academic-colleagues-treat-me-like-a-pariah.
127. Richard Rorty, PSH, 63.
128. Charles Sanders Peirce, The Essential Peirce (Bloomington, Indiana University
Press, 1992–99), 132.
Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation
Harvard Kennedy School
79 John F. Kennedy Street
Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138
T 617.495.0557
F 617.495.4948
ash.harvard.edu