opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 325
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
DOI: 10.1177/1073110518782942
We Can’t Go
Cold Turkey:
Why Suppressing
Drug Markets
Endangers
Society
Nick Werle and Ernesto Zedillo
I. Introduction
By now, much of the public and many of its policy-
makers understand the U.S. opioid epidemic through
a single narrative: The problem started as one of pre-
scription painkiller abuse, but users switched to heroin
after pills become somewhat harder to get, and this
black-market supply was quickly tainted by fentanyl
and other highly potent, synthetic opioids. This narra-
tive is powerful, because it also describes both a typical
drug user’s progression from pills to heroin to deadly
fentanyl-laced injections. But it omits a key acceler-
ant that transformed this wave of addiction into an
inferno of death, disease, and personal destruction:
criminalized suppression of drug use. At each stage
of the crisis, policymakers have sought to extinguish
the problem of opioid abuse by directing law enforce-
ment, regulatory agencies, and private parties to try
cutting o the supplies of drugs and deterring indi-
viduals from using them. These suppressive strategies
have produced unintended consequences that made
the crisis substantially more harmful by pushing
dependent users to engage in riskier behavior that is
more likely to transmit diseases and lead to overdoses.
This essay argues that policies aimed at suppress-
ing drug use exacerbate the nations opioid problem. It
neither endorses drug use nor advocates legalizing the
consumption and sale of all substances in all circum-
stances. Instead, it contends that trying to suppress
drug markets is the wrong goal, and in the midst of
an addiction crisis it can be deadly. There is no single,
correct drug policy; the right approach depends cru-
cially on the substance at issue, the patterns of use and
supply, and the jurisdiction’s culture, institutions, and
material resources. Decriminalization is no panacea
for a nations drug problems. Nevertheless, either de
jure or de facto decriminalization of personal drug
possession is a necessary condition for mitigating this
crisis. The United States must shift its policies away
from addressing drug use as a criminal justice issue
and employ a public-health approach to managing
substance abuse. While some U.S. jurisdictions have
adopted harm reduction strategies to deal with people
Nick Werle, J.D., is a graduate of Yale Law School, a research
associate in the International Drug Policy Unit at the London
School of Economics and Political Science, and a fellow at
Yale’s Solomon Center for Health Law and Policy. He received
an MSc in economic policy from University College London
and an MSc in risk and finance from the London School of
Economics and Political Science with support from the U.K.’s
Marshall Scholarship. Ernesto Zedillo, Ph.D., is the director
of the Yale Center for the Study of Globalization, professor in
the field of international economics and politics, and a mem-
ber of the Global Commission on Drug Policy. He received his
M.A. and Ph.D. in economics from Yale University. He was the
president of Mexico from 1994–2000.
326
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
who use drugs, these demand-side interventions will
be insucient on their own to stop this crisis. As the
Global Commission on Drug Policy has emphasized,
1
policymakers must also address the harder, supply-
side problems — by expanding lawful access to opi-
oids, with the twin objectives of undermining the black
market and reducing the harm that existing opioid use
poses to dependent users and their communities.
Suppressive policies intended to address opioid
abuse will likely exacerbate the crisis of overdose
deaths. State governments are rushing to restrict the
supply of opioid painkillers by implementing prescrip-
tion drug monitoring programs (PDMPs) and tighten-
ing regulations on medical practice. Over-prescription
helped trigger the addiction epidemic, so these crack-
downs may appear overdue. But the timing is wrong.
Decades of opioid abuse have changed the background
conditions against which these policies will operate.
Action in the 1990s and early 2000s to prevent the
pharmaceutical industry, unscrupulous healthcare
providers, and misinformed doctors from flooding
communities with painkillers might have made today’s
crisis less acute. But today, there are many chronic opi-
oid users unlikely to stop consuming when painkillers
become scarce. With black-market heroin increasingly
tainted with fentanyl, and without widespread access
to medication-assisted treatment, policies that restrict
the supply of genuine pharmaceuticals will push peo-
ple toward the more dangerous behavior of injecting
black-market powders. Thus, well-intended policies
may increase fatal overdoses and blood-borne disease
transmission, just as the introduction of abuse-deter-
rent pills increased HIV and hepatitis C infections by
pushing users to inject painkillers. The point is not
that painkiller diversion and prescription-drug abuse
are desirable, but rather that policies ought not push
existing users to start injecting fentanyl-laced heroin
by making safer alternatives unavailable. Absent an
accessible and safe supply of opioids for addiction
maintenance and treatment, these suppressive policies
will likely divert dependent demand to street drugs
and worsen the crisis.
This essay pragmatically critiques suppressive drug
laws, arguing that criminalization is a counterpro-
ductive response to opioid abuse. We start from the
premise that opioid use disorder is a chronic, relaps-
ing medical condition, not a moral failing.
2
Thus,
people suering from drug addiction deserve treat-
ment and social support, not punishment. Some
criminalization advocates recognize that opioid use
disorder is a disease, but support criminalization of
drug markets in the misguided belief that this will
reduce the number of people who have this illness. In
this essay we show that in fact criminalized suppres-
sion does little to reduce the incidence of
opioid use disorder, and surely increases
the harm — including the risk of fatal-
ity — for people who use drugs. Other
advocates of criminalization view drug
use primarily through a moral lens, and
believe that conviction is appropriate to
punish degeneracy. Combatting this idea
and its consequent stigma is important,
not least because they contribute to the
social exclusion of people who use drugs
that amplifies substance abuse’s negative
eects. But refuting this punitive view is
beyond our scope.
Racism is another powerful motiva-
tion, conscious or not, to criminalize
people who use drugs. Many people have
powerfully explained how American drug laws reflect
and feed racial anxieties. Criminal drug-control laws
have contributed to immense racial disparities in
the U.S. prison population, and so racial justice is
an important reason to abandon these policies. The
current crisis has been understood in starkly racial-
ized terms, creating a popular understanding that the
opioid epidemic primarily aicts rural, white people,
even though the overdose death toll is more multira-
cial and more urban than generally understood.
3
The
narrative that today’s heroin users are largely white
and that heroin suppliers are largely black and Latino
has contributed to the public’s greater willingness to
address opioid use less punitively, even as politicians
have advocated for more suppressive supply-side
policies.
4
Nevertheless, drug prohibition’s racist ori-
gins and the suppressive framework’s disparate racial
eects are beyond the essay’s scope.
Finally, this essay does not address many of the ways
in which criminalization and incarceration harms
Today, there are many chronic opioid users
unlikely to stop consuming when painkillers
become scarce. With black-market heroin
increasingly tainted by fentanyl, and without
widespread access to medication-assisted
treatment, policies that restrict the supply of
genuine pharmaceuticals will push people
toward the more dangerous behavior of
injecting black-market powders.
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 327
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
individuals, their families, and communities. Convic-
tion and incarceration in any circumstance directly
infringes an individual’s liberty, presents numerous
collateral consequences for that person, and harms
others in ways that radiate through families and com-
munities. These impediments to human flourishing
are crucially important to criminal justice reform,
both in general and specifically with respect to reform-
ing suppressive drug laws. But since this essay focuses
on why suppressive policies have exacerbated the opi-
oid epidemic, we neglect many issues pertinent to a
broader critique of the U.S. criminal justice system.
This essay proceeds in three parts. Section II
describes how the U.S. law has responded to the prob-
lem of drug abuse by suppressing non-medical use
and illicit supply chains. We also discuss criminalized
suppressions historical roots and contrast it to harm
reduction. Section III analyzes criminalized suppres-
sions economic logic and consequences. We discuss
how the rise of fentanyl is a predictable consequence
of suppressive supply-side policies and how deterrence
has exacerbated the human costs of opioid addiction.
We also explain why state governments are wrong to
restrict the supply of prescription opioids by creating
mandatory PDMPs and other suppressive measures
without first radically expanding regulated access to
opioids for maintenance treatment. Finally, section IV
proposes reforms that reject criminalized suppression
and discusses other countries’ pragmatic responses to
drug abuse. We argue that decriminalizing drug pos-
session is a necessary condition for mitigating this epi-
demic and that the United States must expand access
to medication-assisted treatment so as to provide an
accessible, regulated supply of opioids to dependent
users.
II. Criminalized Suppression: The Legal
Structure of Prohibition
American drug laws reflect a policy framework ori-
ented toward suppressing unauthorized drug produc-
tion and consumption, largely through the enforce-
ment of criminal laws. We describe this framework
as “criminalized suppression” of drug markets, an
approach that takes rates of non-medical drug con-
sumption and interdiction of illicit drugs as primary
indicators. This section describes criminalized sup-
pressions historical origins in the period of alcohol
Prohibition and how it shapes opioid regulation and
addiction treatment today.
A. Government Suppression of “Non-Medical” Opioid
Consumption
The United States regulates opioids so as to simulta-
neously suppress and promote their use. On the one
hand, the law employs harsh criminal and regulatory
sanctions to suppress unauthorized consumption.
But on the other hand, legally supplying opioids is an
immensely profitable, legal business: Pharmaceutical
companies may aggressively promote opioid use for
the medically supervised treatment of pain, and DEA-
licensed healthcare providers can prescribe opioid
painkillers to treat self-reported neuromuscular and
autoimmune pain, even absent clinical trials prov-
ing that opioids are safe and eective for those indi-
cations. True, the law bans nearly all access to some
substances, such as heroin. But licensed health care
providers may prescribe numerous chemically similar
opioids for pain management. Even if they prefer spe-
cific substances, dependent users are generally will-
ing to substitute other opioids based on availability,
potency, and price. The black market’s size and acces-
sibility depends not only on law enforcement action
but also on the extent of legal access, because con-
sumer demand shapes drug-tracking networks, just
as consumer demand in other sectors induces suppli-
ers to bring products to market.
Likewise, during the Prohibition era, alcohol
remained legal for specific purposes and in certain
preparations. Thus, the law suppressed the alcohol
trade rather than prohibiting it outright. The Volstead
Act, which regulated alcohol under Prohibition, per-
mitted people to consume “sacramental” wine and to
store pre-Prohibition alcohol in their homes.
5
People
could also obtain liquor under a doctor’s prescription.
6
These rules stratified Prohibitions eects by class. The
wealthy could still purchase legal, high-quality liquor
through compliant doctors and pharmacies. But those
unable to pay the extortionate prices to access genu-
ine, “medical” liquor were relegated to buying traf-
ficked liquor and often-adulterated spirits produced
in black-market distilleries.
7
The Volstead Act permit-
ted sale of so-called industrial alcohols, which were
required to incorporate poisons and distasteful addi-
tives so as to deter drinkers. But the criminal orga-
nizations and independent distillers that emerged to
satisfy the pent-up demand fortified their brews with
industrial alcohol to boost profitability. As a result, the
poor ended up consuming these poisons to devastat-
ing eect.
Federal law has long distinguished between opi-
oid prescriptions intended to treat addiction through
maintenance therapy and those intended to numb
pain. This distinction stretches at least to the 1914
Harrison Narcotics Act, which was the first federal
law to prohibit non-medical opioid use, and its sub-
sequent amendments. The Treasury Department,
charged with enforcement, promulgated regulations
excluding maintenance as a form of legitimate medi-
328
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
cal practice.
8
Doctors could only administer opioids to
treat addiction if they rapidly weaned patients to sobri-
ety, a process known as detoxification. The Supreme
Court subsequently adopted this view: Webb v. U.S.
presented the question of whether the Harrison Act’s
exception for medical opioid administration applied
where a physician prescribes “morphine to an habitual
user thereof, the order not being issued by him in the
course of professional treatment in the attempted cure
of the habit, but being issued for the purpose of pro-
viding the user with morphine sucient to keep him
comfortable by maintaining his customary use.
9
The
Court held 5–4 that maintenance prescriptions were
non-medical and thus prohibited: “[T]o call such an
order for the use of morphine a physicians prescrip-
tion would be so plain a perversion of meaning thatno
discussion of the subject is required.
10
Today, opioid agonist treatment (OAT) for addic-
tion maintenance is the gold standard for treating opi-
oid use disorder. As a chronic, relapsing mental health
condition, opioid use disorder is not susceptible to a
cure, per se. But evidence-based treatments employ-
ing OAT can help patients stabilize their lives, manage
their addictions, reintegrate into society, and reduce
the harmful consequences of drug use.
11
Maintenance
therapy has been shown to be more clinically eective
and more cost eective than detoxification.
12
Absti-
nence-based treatments are common in the United
States, where they often follow the model for alcohol
abuse treatment, with the goal of lifetime abstinence,
but there is little evidence of clinical ecacy.
13
Absti-
nence-based treatment can increase mortality risk:
While heroin withdrawal itself is rarely life-threat-
ening, putting people with opioid use disorder into
withdrawal poses a high risk of overdose, because a
period of abstinence leads to reduced tolerance.
14
This
risk of overdose explains why abstinence-based treat-
ment approaches for alcoholism are dangerous when
applied to people with opioid use disorder: Relapse to
alcohol use is rarely fatal, but relapse to fentanyl-laced
heroin often kills.
The government has long sought to suppress con-
sumption with a medication that would “cure” opi-
oid addiction outright. But evidence shows that this
goal can be deadly, because using medication to keep
someone abstinent further raises overdose risk. Many
drug courts and treatment programs now rely on nal-
trexone, which is sold under the brand name Vivitrol
as a wonder drug for stopping opioid use. Naltrexone
is an opiate antagonist that triggers immediate with-
drawal and blocks opioids’ pharmacological eects.
But this abstinence is costly: Overdoses are more com-
mon following cessation of naltrexone treatment than
among either untreated heroin users or maintenance
patients.
15
Nevertheless, Vivitrol is now the “go-to
option” in many of Ohios drug courts: The state paid
more than $38 million to provide 30,594 doses to
Medicaid-eligible people in 2016, up from 100 doses
in 2012.
16
Methadones legal status illustrates the focus on
suppression rather than user safety or public health.
The FDA first approved methadone as an analgesic in
1947, but since the 1970s it has been used primarily for
OAT. Methadone is a synthetic opioid that produces
longer-lasting, less intense intoxication than heroin,
permitting people with opioid dependence to achieve
a stable, high-functioning state without withdrawal
symptoms or cravings. It has been proven to reduce
illicit opioid use
17
and its harmful consequences,
including mortality, crime, overdose, and HIV.
18
It is
also cost-eective, despite heavy regulation.
19
Still, federal law permits doctors to prescribe meth-
adone for pain more easily than for maintenance.
When used for pain relief, DEA-licensed doctors may
prescribe methadone without any more restrictions
than would apply to another Schedule II drug, such
as OxyContin.
20
In contrast, there are extensive fed-
eral regulations governing methadone maintenance.
Under federal law, all methadone maintenance treat-
ments must occur in a federally regulated opioid treat-
ment program. Specially licensed practitioners must
provide the treatments, and the law prohibits prohib-
its doctors from writing a methadone prescription to
be filled at a pharmacy, like they would for an opioid
painkiller.
21
Methadone for maintenance generally
must be dispensed and immediately consumed, requir-
ing patients to visit clinics daily.
22
Opioid treatment
programs must randomly screen patients for illicit
drugs.
23
And clinics must provide a host of additional
services to patients, adding to the cost and inconve-
nience of methadone maintenance.
24
State laws may
impose other requirements,
25
and local zoning laws
or community opposition complicates opening new
clinics. Methadone patients must organize their lives
around clinic visits, sometimes traveling several hours
daily. These obstacles interfere with employment
prospects and hinder social reintegration.
Other forms of opioid maintenance are also
restricted by law. Doctors seeking to prescribe
buprenorphine must receive special training and
certifications, and federal law limits the number of
patients they may treat at any time.
26
Yet no such pre-
scribing limits exist for opioid painkillers, and phar-
maceutical companies can even monitor prescribing
rates and oer perks to the doctors selling the most
pills.
27
Federal law requires a “legitimate medical pur-
pose” for opioid prescriptions, and it expressly prohib-
its doctors from prescribing opioid painkillers for the
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 329
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
purpose of addiction maintenance, except under the
regulations specifically applicable to buprenorphine
and methadone.
28
This creates an artificial shortage of
buprenorphine, particularly in rural areas far from a
methadone clinic where there are few doctors able to
prescribe buprenorphine but high demand for treat-
ment. Even in large cities, the regulations create an
artificial scarcity for buprenorphine treatment spots,
encouraging physicians to charge premium prices for
access, sometimes refusing to accept insurance.
29
As
a result, access to buprenorphine — much less dis-
ruptive to personal lives and less stigmatized than
methadone — is highly stratified by class and race.
30
State Medicaid rules may also require buprenorphine
patients to attend time-consuming group counseling
sessions, conditions that may be unduly burdensome
for people with poor access to transportation or who
are trying to maintain employment on often-inflexible
terms. Interviews with patients and providers suggest
that these requirements can function as barriers to
treatment, encouraging patients to self-medicate with
buprenorphine purchased from the black market.
Demand for opioid maintenance dramatically
outstrips the artificially constrained supply. In rural
areas, methadone clinics can be distant and doctors
capable of taking on more buprenorphine patients
rare.
31
In urban areas, zoning regulations and inad-
equate funding also constricts supply. Thus, patients
seeking maintenance treatment can face waiting lists
lasting a year or longer, during which time they face a
ten-fold higher risk of mortality than people immedi-
ately taken on.
32
Skeptics have cited black markets and
diversion as reasons to maintain these restrictions,
but with waiting lists that long, diversion should be
seen as a symptom of supply shortages, not evidence
that tight regulations are necessary to prevent abuse.
B. The role of criminalization in suppressing opioid
use
We describe this framework as criminalized suppres-
sion, because criminal law and policing are the central
means of enforcing the legal prohibition on illicit drug
consumption and supply. Typically, production, trans-
port, sale, and possession of illicit drugs are criminal
oenses under both state and federal law. While the
Supreme Court has declared it unconstitutional to
enact a “status crime” of being addicted to drugs,
33
states can achieve the same result in practice, by
criminalizing the incidences of drug addiction, such
as consumption, the possession of drug paraphernalia,
or the knowing keeping of premises for drug-related
purposes.
Even where policymakers have introduced drug
courts and other diversion programs, primary author-
ity remains vested in the police and judicial system,
rather than public health authorities. Drug courts gen-
erally retain the threat of incarceration for non-com-
pliance. This structure is a poor match for managing
a chronic, relapsing condition, and so incarceration
remains common. Judges often make treatment deci-
sions, and without enforceable drug court standards,
training in addiction medicine is scarce. Finally, many
drug courts provide only abstinence-based treatments
to participants. In one 2013 study, only 47% of U.S.
drug courts provided OAT, and only 26% permitted
methadone maintenance.
34
C. Harm reduction: An alternative framework
Many European countries have responded to heroin
crises of their own by shifting from criminalized sup-
pression to harm reduction. Harm reduction is policy
framework less concerned with the quantity of drugs
consumed than with the social and individual harms
wrought by drug production, sale, consumption, and
government policies. Rather than trying to deter peo-
ple from using drugs with criminal sanctions, harm
reduction aims to shift users into patterns of use that
are less dangerous and less disruptive to society. A
suppressive framework, focused solely on reducing
consumption, threatens to withdraw social services
from people with addiction to make drug use more
costly and withhold resources from people deemed
undeserving. In contrast, harm reduction policies
steer people with problematic drug use toward tai-
lored services, such as safe injection facilities, low-
threshold methadone treatment, or supportive hous-
ing. The goal is to help stabilize their lives, improve
their health, and reintegrate them into society, but
not necessarily to get them to stop using immediately.
Crucially, harm reduction services do not require con-
tinuous abstinence from illicit drug use as a condition
of eligibility.
Adopting a harm reduction approach does not
mean condoning drug use. Drug possession is still
illegal in jurisdictions with comprehensive harm
reduction policies, such as Switzerland and Portugal,
as local ocials explain early and often to observers.
However illicit drug possession for personal use rarely
leads to criminal charges. Instead, these societies have
created a set of institutions that treat substance use
as a medical and social issue. Police build trust more
eectively, because drug users need not fear incarcera-
tion. These countries assign primary responsibility for
opioid abuse to public health authorities, who evalu-
ate interventions on the basis of overdose deaths and
disease transmission rates. They also administer low-
threshold OAT, which provides safe, low-cost access to
opioids for maintenance purposes. These governments
330
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
reason that the state can control the black market only
by undercutting it with a safer, cheaper, and more reli-
able supply than trackers provide. Addiction treat-
ment providers can help people achieve abstinence if
they desire, but they define treatment success in terms
of health and social inclusion, rather than urinalysis.
III. The Economic Consequences of
Criminalized Suppression
A century spent trying to eradicate illicit drug use has
confirmed that consumer demand is the most pow-
erful force shaping drug markets. Where there is an
existing stock of habitual users, no degree of suppres-
sion consistent with a democratic society can eradi-
cate supply. Suppressive policies change, rather than
eliminate, drug markets, altering the prices paid, the
suppliers who profit, and the content of substances
ingested. Prohibition increases profitability, by insert-
ing a large risk premium into drug prices. Prohibition
also directs drug-market revenues to transnational
criminal organizations, financing violence and cor-
ruption in consumer, transit, and producer countries.
Criminalization magnifies the risks users face, by
empowering criminal suppliers who predictably cut
drugs with toxic substances, and by stripping users’
access to medical care, social support, and economic
resources.
This section analyzes the economic implications of
criminalized suppression. First, we show how crimi-
nalized suppression predictably causes the illicit drug
supply to become more dangerous, because black-
market producers and smugglers have an economic
incentive to use highly potent additives. This “iron law
of prohibition” contributed both to today’s fatal opi-
oid overdose crisis and to the epidemic of poisonings
during alcohol Prohibition. Second, we analyze crimi-
nalized suppressions economic logic, which seeks to
reduce demand by using the threat of punishment or
personal harm to deter people from using drugs. This
framework has been used to justify government poli-
cies that make drug use more dangerous to individu-
als and to society, even though it relies crucially on
the false assumption that the decision to use drugs is
rational, and thus amenable to deterrence. Finally, we
suggest an alternative mode of analyzing drug mar-
kets during an addiction epidemic that considers sup-
pressive policies’ implications for already-dependent
users and people initiating drug use.
A. Supply-side suppression makes the black market
more dangerous
Opioid overdoses are now the leading cause of death in
much of the United States. Many of the deaths are due
to fentanyl, which has adulterated the black-market
drug supply. This development reflects the economic
incentives that criminalized suppression creates for
drug suppliers. The “iron law of prohibition” describes
the tendency for aggressive supply-side policing to
lead drug supplies to become dominated by increas-
ingly potent and toxic additives. Alcohol Prohibition
triggered the iron law, poisoning scores who drank
spirits adulterated with additives that were both toxic
and intoxicating. Today, similar economic forces help
explain why fentanyl has become so dominant in U.S.
drug markets, even though its dangers are widely
known.
Alcohol Prohibition did far more to change what
Americans drank than how much. During the three
years after the Volstead Act took eect, consumption
dropped to almost 30% of its pre-Prohibition level.
35
But instead of making alcoholic beverages unavail-
able, the Volstead Act pushed production, trans-
port, sale, and consumption of alcohol underground.
Organized criminal groups, infamously including the
Mafia, took over illicit alcohol markets, which proved
to be enormously profitable. By the late 1920s, after
the black-market industry had developed, per capita
alcohol consumption rebounded to 60–70% of its pre-
Prohibition value.
36
Even though per-capita alcohol consumption
decreased modestly under the Volstead Act, people
drank far more potent brews. The Acts consequences
validate the Iron Law of Prohibition: “The more
intense the law enforcement, the more potent the
drugs will become.
37
This follows from clear economic
incentives for black market producers, smugglers, and
dealers to increase their products’ potency:
[C]oncentrated, potent drugs are more eciently
smuggled, transported, and sold and are easier
for the consumer to conceal, transport, and
consume without detection. Another advantage
of potent drugs for the seller, but a disadvantage
for the buyer, is that potent drugs can more easily
be “cut” with other chemicals that resemble the
real thing. Often these dilutants are poisons.
38
Market data bear out that Prohibitions greatest eect
on consumption was to cause hard liquor and wine to
replace beer as Americans’ drinks of choice. Per capita
consumption of beer decreased about 70% under Pro-
hibition, but people drank 65% more wine and 10%
more liquor, compared to the period from 1911–1914.
39
Some estimate that the potency of alcohol products
increased by more than 150% during Prohibition,
compared to the periods before and after.
40
This
dynamic follows from the cost structure of illicit drug
tracking: Actual production and refining costs are
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 331
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
often insignificant compared to the expenses involved
in transport, smuggling, and distribution, so cutting
a product’s bulk by boosting its potency is a boon to
profitability. Historical alcohol prices reflect this cost
structure: While beer prices increased more than
700% from pre-Prohibition prices, liquor prices only
increased about 270%.
41
Expenditures on distilled
spirits increased from 40% of total pre-Prohibition
alcohol spending to almost 90% during Prohibition.
42
For those who kept drinking, Prohibition made
alcohol more dangerous. Almost immediately after
Prohibition began, methyl alcohol, which cost about
one-eighth of drinkable ethyl alcohol,
43
appeared in
black-market alcohol. Bootleggers would stretch their
grain alcohol by adding homemade “wood alcohol” or
an industrial alcohol after attempting to distill out the
poisonous components.
44
This added a long-lasting,
powerful intoxication, but distillation was only occa-
sionally successful.
45
Wood alcohol blindness quickly
reached epidemic proportions.
46
Poisonings were
common and came in waves, when tainted batches hit
the streets, just as fatal fentanyl overdoses do today.
The scale was comparable to today’s crisis: In 1926,
industrial alcohol sickened or blinded 1,200 people
in New York City alone; another 400 died.
47
In the
South, a potent concoction known as “Jake ginger”
was legally sold by prescription for stomach ills but
also adulterated and strengthened by bootleggers.
48
Even small quantities of Jake caused nerve damage
and permanent paralysis. It produced an “epidemic
of poisonings,” and ultimately, “public health ocials
estimated the number of Jake victims at fifty to sixty
thousand.
49
The iron law also drives today’s overdose epidemic.
Much the death is due to fentanyl, which has per-
vaded the black market since 2013. Fentanyl-related
overdoses killed more than 20,000 people in 2016,
up more than 540% in three years.
50
Some users buy
fentanyl intentionally, because fentanyl is ultra-fast
acting and produces a more intense intoxication than
other opioids,
51
either from street dealers or via the
“dark web.
52
But fentanyl is also laced into both heroin
and counterfeit painkillers. In recent years, the DEA
has identified the rising trend of fentanyl-laced, coun-
terfeit pharmaceuticals as particularly dangerous,
because it expands the population of at-risk users.
53
Fentanyl’s rise was not an unfortunate coincidence;
it was a predictable consequence of the supply-side
incentives created by suppressive government policies.
Fentanyl is cheaper to produce than heroin, because
it does not require labor-intensive cultivation and
harvesting of opium poppies. But more importantly,
fentanyl is cheaper to trac: Its lethal dose is just 2
milligrams.
54
Suppliers can thus boost profitability
by lacing heroin with fentanyl, since they smuggling
less bulk produces the same number of doses. The
government has sought to fortify the southern border,
responding to Mexican cartels tracking heroin.
55
But
fentanyl has traditionally taken dierent smuggling
routes than heroin. For a while, much of the illicit fen-
tanyl supply entered the United States in illegal ship-
ments from China.
56
But consistent with the iron law,
heightened interdiction rates increased the incentive
for cartels to substitute fentanyl for heroin. Today,
Mexican cartels reportedly synthesize fentanyl them-
selves from Chinese precursors.
57
Prohibition in the face of persistent demand gen-
erates a black market with artificially high prices and
grants criminal organizations monopoly power over
that lucrative commerce. The economies of scale
achievable in drug production, smuggling, corruption,
violence, and money laundering mean that organized
crime will tend to fight for and ultimately establish
dominant positions in their markets. In regions home
to illicit agriculture, cartels can act as monopsonies,
keeping opium prices low and forcing subsistence
farmers to absorb the costs of crop eradication.
58
The
bulk of drugs’ black-market value comes from traf-
ficking them across international borders, so Mexico’s
worst violence has been in the north, with cartels fight-
ing for control of land crossings to the United States.
At the distribution level, a single cartel is dominant in
Just as alcohol Prohibition barely reduced drinking and produced a violent
black market, attacking today’s drug trackers is fruitless so long as the U.S.
opioid market is so lucrative. Production volumes of illicit drugs are so high,
and drug tracking is so profitable, that interdiction cannot raise prices
enough to induce lower consumption.
Instead, supply-side suppression has
encouraged trackers to smuggle cheaper and more potent opioids.
332
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
many U.S. markets, possibly explaining why dealing-
related violence has remained low.
59
Just as alcohol Prohibition barely reduced drinking
and produced a violent black market, attacking today’s
drug trackers is fruitless so long as the U.S. opioid
market is so lucrative. Production volumes of illicit
drugs are so high, and drug tracking is so profitable,
that interdiction cannot raise prices enough to induce
lower consumption.
60
Instead, supply-side suppres-
sion has encouraged trackers to smuggle cheaper
and more potent opioids.
B. Deterrence and the economic logic of criminalized
suppression
An oversupply of pharmaceutical opioids may have
triggered this addiction epidemic, but mitigating it
requires managing Americans’ demand for illicit opi-
oids. Traditionally, demand reduction takes several
forms. First, prevention reduces the number of people
who begin using opioids, a crucial intervention in the
midst of an addiction epidemic. Second, treatment
cuts demand from current users, both by reducing
their consumption and by legally obtaining opioids for
maintenance. And finally, deterrence convinces people
not to use drugs, by increasing the risks of drug use
and threats of legal sanctions. American drug policy
has long relied heavily on deterring drug use and
underinvested in addiction treatment. But that faith in
deterrence is misplaced, because it relies on a flawed
model of human behavior. The economic theory justi-
fying deterrence assumes that drug consumption is a
rational decision, in which potential users weigh the
costs and benefits of getting high. Despite criticism,
this theory continues to motivate government policies
that exacerbate the health risks and social isolation
faced by people who use drugs, entrenching addic-
tions etiology.
Deterring future consumption is the central ratio-
nale for punishing drug users. The modern theoreti-
cal justification for deterrence is rooted in the micro-
economic analysis of addiction, which models drug
use as a rational choice.
61
Microeconomics describes
someone as acting rationally when she takes only
those actions for which her expected marginal ben-
efit exceeds her expected marginal costs; that is, if she
expects the choice to produce more pleasure than pain
in the future. This model’s conclusion is that someone
could rationally use addictive drugs because the plea-
sure of today’s euphoria outweighs the present value
of addiction’s future pain and the risk of punishment
for acting illegally. Consequently, policymakers should
be able to deter people from using drugs by increasing
the expected future costs of addiction. These expected
costs may come from the drug’s purchase price, the
drug’s degradation of health and social capital, or the
possibility of prosecution and punishment for illicit
consumption. The theory also concludes that strong
addictions must end “cold turkey,” arguing that any-
thing but immediate, full withdrawal is irrational, and
thus inappropriate, for treating heroin addiction.
62
Subsequent economic theories have complicated this
picture, explaining the decision to use drugs through
a model of temptation and self-control,
63
mistake,
64
or
time-inconsistent preferences
65
. But these approaches
still assume rationality and counsel the same policies:
deterring future use by raising the user’s expected
costs, suppressing drug supplies, and educating peo-
ple about drugs’ harmful eects.
The rationalist view of addiction has been subject to
extensive critique, but its intuitive theory of deterrence
still animates policy decisions. Deterrence strategy
usually takes the form of trying to make prosecution
more likely and punishments more severe. This strat-
egy reached its apogee during the Reagan era, when
Congress imposed draconian mandatory minimum
sentences for trafficking and production offenses,
criminalized simple possession under federal law, and
introduced several enhancements that lengthened
incarceration for repeat drug oenders and for use of
a firearm in connection with a drug crime.
The United States is unique among developed
democracies in the extent to which it incarcerates
people with substance use disorders, often follow-
ing conviction for minor drug distribution or prop-
erty oenses, even though incarceration is known to
dramatically increase rates of overdose death. While
incarceration generally exacerbates the social, psycho-
logical, and economic reasons why someone ends up
in prison, incarceration poses extreme risks to people
with histories of injection drug use. Few U.S. detention
facilities oer OAT, so incarceration usually produces
withdrawal and a dramatic fall in opioid tolerance.
Thus, formerly-incarcerated people with histories of
opioid addiction face an elevated risk of fatal overdose
in the weeks following release.
66
Trying to deter drug use by raising its risks is a
common and deadly government strategy. During
Prohibition, the federal government tried suppress-
ing illicit drinking by making it riskier, a strategy that
predictably led to severe consequences. In 1926, “dry
congressmen demanded that the federal government
more aggressively deter bootleggers from transform-
ing industrial alcohols into salable spirits. In response,
Secretary of the Treasury Andrew Mellon approved
federal chemists’ “Formula No. 5,” which doubled the
methyl alcohol concentration in denaturing agents.
67
The strategy worked, in the sense that it made safe
alcohol much harder to obtain. But in so doing, it
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 333
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
caused needless death and injury, since people contin-
ued drinking anyway.
68
Opponents of harm-reduction policies often invoke
similar logic, arguing that access to syringe exchanges,
safe injection facilities, housing programs, and low-
threshold OAT will encourage drug use, because it
mitigates the risks of disease, homelessness, and poor
health that supposedly dissuade people from using
opioids. For instance, politicians have argued that
syringe exchange programs encourage illicit drug use,
even though public health research has shown that
syringe exchanges do not encourage injection.
69
In
fact, syringe exchanges are eective conduits to sub-
stance abuse treatment.
70
Indiana exemplifies how misguided deterrence
logic has increased this epidemic’s toll. Scott County
in southern Indiana has seen a severe HIV outbreak
since 2015. According to CDC analysis, the outbreak
emerged from abuse of the painkiller Opana, which
gained popularity after access to OxyContin became
more dicult.
71
In 2012, Opana’s manufacturers had
released an abuse-deterrent formulation designed
to prevent users from crushing and snorting pills.
But once this reformulation arrived in Scott County,
addicts began injecting.
72
Indiana law is hostile to
harm reduction eorts, and possession of syringes
with intent to use them for nonmedical purposes is
a felony.
73
It is illegal to purchase syringes without a
prescription, and a burdensome exception for syringe
exchanges was only added in 2015.
74
But the result-
ing syringe shortage didnt deter injection. It just led
people to share needles, predictably triggering an HIV
epidemic. In 2015, then-Governor Mike Pence permit-
ted one syringe exchange to open in Scott County, and
a few other counties eventually followed suit. But local
politicians have resisted these harm reduction mea-
sures on moral and deterrence grounds. Two counties
closed their syringe exchanges in late 2017 in the face
of ongoing an HIV epidemic. The Indiana Attorney
General recently praised these closures, falsely assert-
ing that syringe exchanges encourage drug use: “Law-
rence County is wise to back o the practice of distrib-
uting free needles to heroin addicts and other opioid
abusers. Handing out clean needles encourages sub-
stance abusers to shoot up and, in many cases, shoot
up more often.
75
Misplaced deterrence theories also
power resistance to harm reduction ser-
vices proven to reduce overdose deaths.
Other countries, including Canada, have
used safe injection facilities (SIFs) to
reduce overdoses, disease transmission,
and public nuisances stemming from
opioid use.
76
But the Department of Jus-
tice recently invoked the threat of federal
criminal prosecution to prevent state and
local ocials from setting up the nations
first legally sanctioned SIF, arguing that
it would encourage drug use.
77
Similar
rhetoric slowed naloxone distribution.
Opponents claimed that reducing over-
dose risk through naloxone access would
encourage injection drug use and would
discourage entry to abstinence-based
treatments. However, numerous studies
have disproven these assertions applying
deterrence theory to naloxone access.
78
These examples demonstrate how
the suppressive logic of deterrence has
exacerbated the health consequences of the opioid
epidemic by obstructing access to harm reduction ser-
vices. When people who use drugs associate state ser-
vices with only repression and punishment, a deficit of
trust develops, the neediest people will be unlikely to
seek out public services. So long as criminalized sup-
pression remains the framework within which drug-
dependent people interact with the state, it will unduly
hamper treatment access and social service provision.
C. Suppressing prescription drugs without expanding
access to opioid maintenance treatment will
exacerbate the overdose crisis
State governments are responding to the overdose epi-
demic suppressing the painkiller supply and making it
These examples demonstrate how the
suppressive logic of deterrence has
exacerbated the health consequences of
the opioid epidemic by obstructing access
to harm reduction services. When people
who use drugs associate state services with
only repression and punishment, a deficit of
trust develops, the neediest people will be
unlikely to seek out public services. So long
as criminalized suppression remains the
framework within which drug-dependent
people interact with the state, it will unduly
hamper treatment access and social service
provision.
334
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
“abuse-resistant.” But these are the wrong policies at
the wrong time. With so many people already addicted
and access to opioid maintenance treatment an inac-
cessible patchwork, making it harder for dependent
users to access pharmaceutical opioids will push them
to inject fentanyl-laced, black-market powders and
ingest counterfeit pills. Prescription painkiller abuse is
serious, but pushing users into the black market mag-
nifies the epidemic’s harmful consequences, including
overdoses. Policymakers should respond to the opioid
problem by expanding access to OAT, rather than by
pushing people toward riskier behavior.
The misguided eort to suppress painkiller abuse
by introducing abuse-deterrent formulations (ADFs)
is a cautionary tale. Starting around 2012, pharma-
ceutical companies reformulated several blockbuster
opioid pills, including OxyContin and Opana, to
make them harder to crush and sni. Manufacturers
had two motivations. Public health research showed
that most heroin users initiated opioid use by tak-
ing legally dispensed pills, crushing and sning the
pills before starting to inject.
79
ADFs were intended to
make painkiller abuse more dicult and thus prevent
painkiller users from developing destructive addic-
tions. But financial incentives may have dominated:
Manufacturers faced impending patent expirations,
which would have opened their blockbuster painkill-
ers to generic competition. They responded by intro-
ducing newly patented ADFs and then lobbying the
FDA to take pills without these “safety” features o
the market, preventing non-ADF generics from com-
peting with brand-name painkillers.
80
At the time, no
generics on the market had ADFs. Several years later,
economists and public health ocials have confirmed
that the ADFs backfired and blame them for accelerat-
ing users’ transitions from pills to powders.
81
Unable
to snort the pills, many users turned to injecting them,
increasing risks of overdose and disease transmission.
Others turned to black-market drugs, buying fen-
tanyl-laced heroin or counterfeit pills.
82
Despite the
evidence, ADFs’ intuitive appeal has attracted federal
ocials eager to be seen responding to the addiction
crisis. Expanding the transition to ADFs is now a cen-
terpiece of the FDAs national response.
83
State governments have taken the lead in responding
to the crisis, but many states’ strategies have empha-
sized restricting prescription opioid access with Pre-
scription Drug Monitoring Programs (PDMPs) and
physician discipline, instead of expanding OAT access.
Forty-nine states now operate PDMPs, statewide
databases that record patients’ prescription histories
for controlled substances.
84
PDMPs permit provid-
ers to identify patients who are “doctor shopping” to
try to obtain multiple, simultaneous prescriptions for
their own use or to sell to others. State health depart-
ments, and law enforcement personnel, can also use
some states’ PDMPs to identify anomalous behavior
and then target providers or patients for enforcement
actions.
85
PDMPs have been shown to reduce the vol-
ume of opioids prescribed by more than 30%,
86
par-
ticularly in the 32 states that mandate provider access
prior to prescribing opioid analgesics.
87
The states have taken other measures to suppress
nonmedical use of pharmaceutical opioids and restrict
the diversion of pills to dealers. Some legislatures and
medical boards have limited the number of pills and
refills doctors may prescribe at a time. Attorneys gen-
eral, medical licensing boards, criminal prosecutors,
and health departments have sought to deter physi-
cians and pharmacists from prescribing opioids to
people with addictions. The federal government, state
attorneys general, and private litigants have also sued
pharmaceutical manufacturers and distributors for
misbranding and negligent distribution practices.
Are these policies helping? PDMPs and these other
measures have been touted for reducing the number
of opioid prescriptions.
88
But this begs the question
of whether reducing prescriptions is an unalloyed
public health benefit. Restricting the volume of opi-
oids that doctors can prescribe to new pain patients
may reduce the rate at which people become addicted.
But prescription opioids’ reduced accessibility also
compels habitual painkiller abusers to switch from
genuine pharmaceuticals to using counterfeit pills or
black-market heroin. As with the similar shift follow-
ing ADFs’ introduction, harmful consequences should
increase. Indeed, empirical work from the past year
has validated these concerns. A recent econometric
analysis found that adopting PDMPs increased by
47%–84% the rate of heroin-involved criminal inci-
dents that police encounter in the counties with high-
est per capita rates of pre-PDMP prescription opioid
consumption.
89
But in lower-consumption counties,
PDMP adoption did not significantly change the rate
of heroin-involved incidents.
90
Studies of overdose
mortality found that PDMP adoption had widely vary-
ing eects across states, but one found that implemen-
tation of PDMPs was associated with an 11% increase
in drug overdose mortality.
91
Another study found a
slight decrease in mortality overall.
92
These data are
consistent with the proposition that reducing access
to genuine pharmaceuticals is harmful where unman-
aged opioid addiction is prevalent and OAT access is
dicult.
In the same vein, states with restrictive cannabis
laws have fared worse than those with legal access.
Cannabis is a less addictive analgesic than hydroco-
done and habitual use is less harmful than habitual
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 335
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
heroin use, so cannabis could have been a better option
for many chronic pain patients and a less harmful sub-
stitute for some non-medical opioid use. A nationwide
analysis from 1999 to 2010 found that states permit-
ting chronic pain patients to obtain medical cannabis
legally had an opioid analgesic overdose mortality rate
25% lower than states without medical cannabis laws.
93
Colorados experience from 2000–2015 also suggests
that legalization of recreational cannabis produced a
6.5% reduction in opioid-related deaths in the follow-
ing two years.
94
This evidence supports our contention
that providing safe, regulated access to “illicit” drugs
mitigates the consequences that drugs pose to society.
Counterintuitively, the best response to the opioid
epidemic at this juncture may be to increase, rather
than to suppress, regulated opioids access. We are not
arguing that prescription opioid abuse is good. Rather,
we contend that with such a large stock of dependent
users and without access to low-threshold mainte-
nance treatment, suppressing the supply of genuine
pharmaceuticals pushes addicted people to consumer
riskier black-market drugs. Therefore, until OAT is
widely accessible, further suppression of pharmaceu-
ticals is unwise.
IV. Toward Public-Health Oriented
Regulation of Opioids
In 2016, more than 2.1 million Americans had an
opioid use disorder.
95
Those unable to remain absti-
nent need a regulated and safe means of maintaining
their addictions and obtaining treatment. Introduc-
ing a safe, reliable, and suciently accessible supply of
opioids for existing users can erode the demand that
supports black markets. Just as important, a regu-
lated supply system can improve individual and pub-
lic health, because people are less likely to overdose
or contract diseases consuming pharmaceutical-grade
opioids than injecting substances bought on the street
or in an anonymous, online bazaar. This system of sup-
ply should be run through a revamped, low-threshold,
insurance-funded OAT system. This section discusses
why decriminalization of drug possession for personal
use is a necessary response to the crisis and describes
reforms to the U.S. OAT system that could transform
it into an eective way of supplying opioid-dependent
people with an accessible and regulated source for
addiction maintenance.
A. Decriminalization is a necessary but insucient
response to the crisis
Some U.S. jurisdictions have abandoned the most
draconian tactics for suppressing drug consumption.
But even where the government relies less on threat-
ened punishment to deter people from using drugs,
policies remain tethered to suppression, because most
dependent users still lack access to a regulated supply
of drugs. States should rapidly reform both their laws
and practices so as to shift from a punitive framework
to one based on medical treatment, social support,
and harm reduction.
Decriminalization policies must be tailored to spe-
cific communities. In some areas, de facto decriminal-
ization, achieved through law enforcement policies
and cooperative relationships with drug treatment
providers and community groups, may be sucient.
However, de jure decriminalization is better, because
it eliminates police officers’ power to selectively
arrest drug users, thereby fostering greater trust. For
instance, Good Samaritan laws that protect people
witnessing an opioid overdose from arrest amplify the
public-health benefits from equipping police ocers
with naloxone, because witnesses are more likely to
call for help. Even better is the model of cooperation
between police and social workers in the Law Enforce-
ment Assisted Diversion (LEAD) model: Social work-
ers, defense attorneys, prosecutors, and police ocers
work together in case-management teams to stabi-
lize the lives of marginalized drug users. In practice,
LEAD operates as de facto decriminalization of drug
possession, with cooperative rehabilitation replacing
outright suppression. By substituting social support
for arrest, LEAD has been able to reduce participants’
odds of arrest by 58%.
96
Non-U.S. jurisdictions that have eectively stopped
opioid epidemics have shifted primary responsibil-
ity to public-health agencies, which tend to respond
to relapse with service provision rather than punish-
ment. The dierence between American drug courts
and the Portugals commissions for the dissuasion of
drug addiction (CDTs) highlight why public health
authorities must take the leading role. American drug
courts operate on a post-arrest diversion model, with
criminal prosecution held in abeyance pending com-
pletion of the drug court program. People can avoid
a judgment only if they avoid relapsing. The entire
process of arrest, booking, detention, and ongoing
proceedings is costly and stigmatizing, complicating
social and economic reintegration even if someone is
“successful.” But if the defendant fails the drug court’s
program, she remains liable to incarceration. Such
failure is common, because many drug courts ascribe
to an abstinence-based philosophy and either prohibit
OAT or permit it only under restrictive conditions.
97
Because substance use disorder is a chronically relaps-
ing condition characterized by compulsive drug use, a
model that punishes people for “failure” is itself poorly
equipped for success.
336
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
In contrast, the Portuguese public health authorities
run the CDT system. If the police encounter someone
on the street in possession of drugs for personal use,
they give him an administrative summons for atten-
dance at the local CDT. There is no arrest and no crim-
inal record. CDT panels comprise psychiatrists, social
workers, and lawyers, working together with a sta to
understand the client’s needs in a holistic manner. If
the CDT determines that his drug use is unproblem-
atic, they may impose a small fine, order community
service, or merely dismiss him. But if it finds that he
has an addiction or another social problem, it will
refer him to appropriate services, chiefly low-thresh-
old OAT. Access to these drugs is much easier than in
the United States: Vans circulate throughout Lisbon,
dispensing methadone to clients without burdensome
rules or drug testing requirements. The CDT operates
as a case manager, connecting people with necessary
services. People with more severe problems receive
more substantial services, and there is no threat of
juridical coercion.
Portugal’s is a religious and socially conserva-
tive society. Portuguese ocials stress that drug use
remains illegal, but that decriminalization is the neces-
sary condition for their real reform — low-threshold
OAT — to work. American commentators advocat-
ing drug policy reform often point to Portugal as an
example of how “decriminalization” can eliminate drug
problems. But that’s not how the Portuguese see it.
Only by decriminalizing the lives of drug users can the
state build the trust necessary to bring them into state
care for addiction treatment, social services, and OAT.
Portugals current situation is by no means utopian,
and there is still problematic drug use. But the country
enacted a self-consciously pragmatic policy response
to a severe opioid epidemic at the end of the 1990s, and
these measures successfully restrained the crisis and
reduced overdose deaths and disease transmission.
The United States should adopt a similar harm
reduction strategy. Given the prevalence of high-risk
injection drug use, safe injection facilities ought to be
opened as soon as possible. SIFs are professionally
supervised healthcare facilities that seek to reduce
mortality and morbidity by providing high risk drug
users with a safe, hygienic place to consume drugs
obtained o-premises. While politically contentious,
SIFs’ public health benefits are well settled. More than
90 SIFs operate legally in other countries, includ-
ing Switzerland, Germany, Spain, France, Denmark,
Norway, Canada, and Australia.
98
Unsanctioned
SIFs operate in New York City and elsewhere in the
United States, and several cities’ public health depart-
ments are working toward opening a municipal SIF
in 2018, despite the federal government’s steadfast
opposition.
99
Numerous studies have found that SIFs
do not increase injection drug use, drug tracking,
or crime.
100
SIFs do, however, decrease the morbid-
ity and mortality associated with injection drug use,
increase uptake of addiction treatment, and reduce
the public nuisances associated with drug use, such
as discarded syringes and injection in public spaces.
101
SIFs have been remarkable successful in reducing
fatal opioid overdoses: In Vancouver, Canada opening
a SIF caused fatal opioid overdoses to fall 35% in the
surrounding area.
102
In Sydney, Australia, the num-
ber of ambulance calls responding to overdoses near
a SIF decreased 68% during its operating hours.
103
None of the legally operating SIFs has ever reported
a fatal opioid overdose by a someone using its ser-
vice.
104
In 2011, when the Canadian Supreme Court
ordered the Minister of Health to continue licensing
Vancouver’s experimental SIF, the Court declared its
social value to be settled: “[the Vancouver SIF] saves
lives. Its benefits have been proven. There has been
no discernable negative impact on the public safety
and health objectives of Canada during its eight years
of operation.
105
Abstinence-based limits on access to wraparound
social services and public benefits should also be
removed, because requiring people to be abstinent
Law enforcement agencies cannot address the root causes of substance
use disorder, because they lack authority to establish regulated systems of
supply and low-threshold OAT. But for those systems to work,
law enforcement agencies must be fully engaged partners, policing in ways
that reinforce, rather than undermine, the medical care and
social reintegration of people who use drugs.
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 337
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
in order to get access to services does not help people
manage addiction. The best-studied context is hous-
ing, and the evidence is clear: “[The] traditional absti-
nence approach was not more eective at reducing
rates ofsubstanceuse.”
106
In randomized controlled
trials, people provided with housing first, and subject
to no abstinence requirements, were “significantly
less likely to use or abuse substances when com-
pared to Treatment First clients.
107
Deterrence-based
approaches are counterproductive, because relapse
does not follow from rational cost-benefit calcula-
tions. Stable housing permits people who use drugs to
reintegrate into society and better manage chemical
dependencies. Stress is a crucial driver of relapse to
problematic drug use, and eviction needlessly intro-
duces stress, trauma, and disruption into an already
disorganized life. So even if abstinence is the goal, law
should not make it a necessary condition receiving
social support.
Law enforcement agencies cannot address the
root causes of substance use disorder, because they
lack authority to establish regulated systems of sup-
ply and low-threshold OAT. But for those systems to
work, law enforcement agencies must be fully engaged
partners, policing in ways that reinforce, rather than
undermine, the medical care and social reintegration
of people who use drugs.
B. Public health-oriented regulation of opioids
How can we design a system that provides an acces-
sible, regulated supply of opioids to people already
dependent on the drugs without encouraging others
to start using? Other countries, including Switzerland,
Portugal, Germany, and the Netherlands have faced
epidemics of heroin abuse in the past and reformed
their systems for healthcare, policing, and social ser-
vices to abate the crisis and manage future abuse.
Each successful national addiction treatment system
has at its core a comprehensive, low-threshold OAT
system that provides existing users with an accessible
and low-cost source for pharmaceutical grade opioids.
Access to maintenance drugs is considered essential,
mainstream medical care, and so regulations permit
people who have stabilized their conditions to quickly
escape the disruptive pattern of daily clinic visits for
methadone maintenance by shifting oversight to
general practitioners and permitting prescriptions
for take-home doses to be filled at local pharmacies.
Several jurisdictions have also recognized the value
of adding medical-grade heroin as an OAT mainte-
nance option because some patients’ conditions are
more stable with heroin-assisted treatment (HAT)
than with methadone or buprenorphine. Finally,
these jurisdictions use far fewer opioids in pain treat-
ment than the United States and prohibit the kinds of
financial incentives and marketing practices that led
to overreliance on painkillers in the first place.
Low-threshold methadone maintenance is the cor-
nerstone of comprehensive drug treatment. Where
methadone and buprenorphine maintenance is avail-
able in the United States, the numerous regulatory and
practical barriers to access make it a “high-threshold”
service. Features of high-threshold treatment include
requirements that patients visit specialized and often
inaccessible clinics daily for supervised drug admin-
istration, inflexible admission criteria, waiting lists,
limited-duration treatment, zero-tolerance of illicit
drug use, and high prices. In contrast, low-threshold
services impose few requirements to access treatment.
Patients need not abstain from illicit drugs as a condi-
tion of service use, and these programs aim to reduce
all documented barriers to service access and mini-
mize requirements for retention.
108
They also aim to
destigmatize treatment, so people who use drugs feel
welcome, trust the service, and know they will not be
discriminated against. Low-threshold services con-
sider relapses to be expected features of the underly-
ing condition, and they respond with additional ser-
vices rather than discipline. Wraparound services and
counseling are usually oered but are not compulsory.
Service providers seek to be minimally disruptive to
patients’ lives, so they do not require patients to travel
long distances, using pharmacy distribution, “metha-
done buses,” and take-home doses to eliminate daily
clinic visits.
Other countries’ pragmatic responses to opioid crises
of their own can serve as a model for U.S. policymakers.
In France, methadone maintenance must be initi-
ated in clinics, but a patient may transfer her prescrip-
tion to a general practitioner after her condition is
stabilized. Methadone is free in clinics and pharmacy-
dispensed doses are reimbursed through standard
prescription coverage. Pharmacies may provide up to
a week’s doses at a time. Users are not required to reg-
ister, undergo no testing for illicit drug use, and need
not undergo counseling as a condition of treatment.
109
These policies, introduced in 1995, are credited with
substantially reducing opioid overdoses, HIV and
hepatitis C incidence, and drug-related crime.
110
In Hong Kong, the Department of Health actively
promotes methadone maintenance and makes on-
demand methadone treatment very accessible. Opi-
ate-dependent people can generally access methadone
maintenance on the same day they present for treat-
ment, following a urine test to verify that they are opi-
oid users. People under 18 are admitted, and parental
consent is preferred but not mandatory.
111
The fee for
each visit is fixed at HK$1 ($0.13).
112
The clinics oper-
338
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
ate daily and are open before and after work hours, as
more than half of maintenance patients are employed.
Methadones accessibility is key, and mobile ser-
vice provision has been successful in several cities. In
Amsterdam, the government has distributed metha-
done by bus since the 1970s. These mobile clinics dis-
pense free methadone throughout the city, so patients
may attend more easily.
113
Lisbon adopted this model
in 2001, and now has several buses that dispense
free methadone throughout the greater metropoli-
tan area.
114
One can only imagine how providing such
mobile methadone services would increase mainte-
nance treatment access both in the rural areas of the
United States, where addiction is rampant and metha-
done access extremely limited, and in sprawling met-
ropolitan areas.
The U.S. government should also add pharma-
ceutical-grade heroin to the list of approved drugs
for maintenance therapy. Switzerland, Germany, the
Netherlands, the United Kingdom, France, Australia,
and Canada have all oered heroin-assisted treatment
(HAT) in specialized clinics, either as an established
or experimental treatment.
115
Studies have shown that
incorporating heroin maintenance was more eec-
tive than methadone maintenance alone for certain
groups of long-term and treatment-resistant drug
users and produced no greater incidence of seri-
ous adverse eects.
116
Randomized controlled trials
in the Netherlands have shown that HAT patients
experienced significantly fewer heroin cravings and
engaged in less illicit heroin use than methadone
maintenance patients.
117
A randomized, controlled
trial in Vancouver found that for some patients, using
injectable heroin for maintenance was more eective
than oral methadone at retaining people in addiction
treatment and at reducing illicit drug use and other
illegal activity, such as sex work.
118
Interviews in Van-
couver showed that HAT permitted people with long-
term addictions to stabilize their lives, improve their
health, regain employment, and reintegrate into social
and political life. But realizing these benefits requires
open-ended maintenance treatment, since forced
cessation of HAT causes the gains to evaporate.
119
Introducing pharmaceutical-grade heroin as a main-
tenance therapy option could therefore improve the
health of America’s existing injection drug users and
help extinguish the demand powering illicit markets.
Switzerland shows how government-administered
OAT can stabilize an epidemic of drug use and under-
cut an incumbent black market. Methadone and
buprenorphine are available on a low-threshold basis
through general practitioners and regular pharma-
cies. Patients addicted for more than two years who
have twice failed other treatment regimens qualify for
high-threshold, clinic-based HAT. Swiss health insur-
ance plans must cover all OAT options, providing
extremely low-cost and reliable access to a safe, high
quality, supply. And since providing these services
is not unusually profitable, providers lack structural
incentives to expand the market. The absolute num-
ber of opioid consumers, including OAT recipients,
has stayed consistent since the height of the Swiss
opioid epidemic in the early 1990s, indicating that
prevention eorts and the regulatory structure gov-
erning OAT have kept people from initiating opioid
use, despite collapsing heroin prices.
120
The addiction
treatment system has largely replaced the black mar-
ket as a source for accessing opioids. The black market
has been structurally stable and largely non-violent
during this period, with well entrenched, Albanian
criminal organizations dominating the scene.
121
Intel-
ligence suggests that the heroin trade is now mini-
mally profitable. So long as the potency and volume of
the heroin market remain stable and residual track-
ing activity produces neither violence nor public nui-
sances, suppressing the illicit heroin market remains a
low police priority.
Skeptics may object that expanding the OAT system
and lowering access thresholds would risk providing
an accessible and socially acceptable means for people
to initiate drug use. But the experiences of Switzerland
and other countries belay that fear. Low-threshold
OAT access does not mean no-threshold access: Pro-
viders still test patients’ urine to ensure that they are
opioid users, because giving methadone to someone
without any tolerance is dangerous. A well-regulated
OAT system actually reduces the risk of initiation,
because it undermines black-market suppliers, who
have incentives to promote opioid dependence and
so seek out new customers. In the United States, the
black market’s ubiquity likely explains the troubling
increase from in the proportion of people initiating
opioid use directly with black-market heroin. A recent
study estimated that the proportion of Americans who
initiated opioid use with heroin increased from 9% in
2005 to 33% in 2015.
122
This dramatic increase in peo-
ple starting directly with heroin further suggests that
policymakers focused on restricting painkiller access
are actually fighting the last war.
Opioids are highly addictive substances, but politi-
cal economy is as important as chemistry in triggering
an addiction epidemic. In better regulated supplies,
the goal should providing dependent users with a safe,
accessible, and reliable supply of opioids for addic-
tion maintenance without encouraging oversupply
and initiation of abuse. Unlike today’s alcohol mar-
ket, no entities should have economic incentives to
promote problematic consumption. Given the intrin-
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 339
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
sic risks of dispensing opioids and the documented
success of existing OAT regimens, it makes sense to
organize access through the treatment system and
to fund the care through medical insurance. Relying
on market-based incentives to enlist private-sector
providers entails making maintenance treatment suf-
ficiently profitable. But making opioid prescription
profitable entails its own substantial risks, made plain
in the well-known stories of pharmaceutical industry
manipulations and physician profiteering that ignited
the epidemic of painkiller addiction.
The pharmaceutical industry’s dismal track record
in fomenting this epidemic is a cautionary tale. Even
some libertarian-minded advocates of drug “legal-
ization” have questioned their stances, in light of the
role legal opioids played in triggering addictions.
123
But concluding that prohibition is best follows only
from an ideological premise that criminalized pro-
hibition and unregulated legalization are the only
available policy alternatives. Prescription painkillers
caused such damage because they were aggressively
and deceptively marketed in a regulatory environment
excessively deferential to industry and focused more
on profitability than on health. Many of prescription
opioids’ dangers stem from the fee-for-service financ-
ing models that generally bedevil American health-
care, though the iatrogenic risks of over-testing pale in
comparison to those of over-medicating post-surgical
and pain management patients. Even more dangerous
are laws permitting pharmaceutical manufacturers to
supplement physicians’ incomes with perks and con-
sulting fees, as Perdue Pharma famously did for doc-
tors that prescribed the most OxyContin. To regulate
opioids consistently with public health needs, provid-
ers must be compensated on the basis of population
health, not services rendered. And prescribers should
follow the direction of impartially generated medical
evidence, not industry marketing materials.
Neither are addiction treatment providers guaran-
teed to be public-health regarding. Indeed, this addic-
tion epidemic has spurred a concomitant boom in the
treatment market, and private capital is rushing in to
exploit profit opportunities. This has financed dra-
matic consolidation of addiction treatment providers,
fueled by billions of dollars in cash from the private
equity industry.
124
Since American addiction treat-
ment lacks clear standards of care, profitability, rather
than evidence, often determines treatment regimens.
This frequently means abstinence and group therapy,
rather than OAT. Sometimes, it can also mean com-
pulsory work programs, with sober home residents
or drug court participants sent to work without pay
in local businesses that have made financial arrange-
ments with “treatment” providers.
125
People seeking
addiction treatment for themselves or their loved
ones often lack the information necessary to make
informed choices, and maintenance therapy’s stigma
drives people away from evidence-based treatment.
As a result, many patients are in expensive facilities
but lack access to OAT. The trend has even resulted in
privatization of purportedly public institutions, such
as facilities for civil commitment of opioid users, which
are increasingly run by the private prison industry and
too rarely provide high-quality OAT.
Government has an important role, not just as a
regulator but as a direct service provider or a link in
the supply chain. Models exist for using exclusive gov-
ernment provision of critical supply chain services to
prevent profit-maximizing, private entities from over-
supplying a habit-forming substance and damaging
public health. For instance, the Uruguayan law legal-
izing recreational cannabis created a state monopoly
at the wholesale level. This entity mediates between
highly regulated growers and highly regulated retail-
ers, setting prices that both ensure sucient returns
on investment to attract private capital and prevent
the industry from expanding and commercializing to a
degree that would undermine public health. In an ear-
lier era, the British government successfully addressed
the problem of drunkenness in wartime factory towns
by nationalizing pubs, which then provided alcohol
under conditions dictated by public health concerns
rather than profitability.
126
And following Prohibition,
some U.S. states retained government monopolies on
retail liquor sales. Of course, public control does not
eliminate risk of bad regulatory design: One need only
consider state-run lotteries to see how public entities
can also run amuck.
Widespread public provision of low-threshold
maintenance treatment would be an excellent invest-
ment. Numerous studies have found that mainte-
nance therapies are cost eective, even as currently
provided, because people with OAT-stabilized addic-
tions impose fewer costs on other social programs,
law enforcement, and healthcare services.
127
But the
current system is unnecessarily expensive and thus
crowds out more and better services for people who
use drugs. Methadone is an unpatented medicine
that is cheap to produce. Many of the costs associated
with maintenance treatment are the result of the sup-
pressive regulations that also impede access. Shift-
ing maintenance treatment to a low-threshold model
would not just ease access to care, but that it would
also make proper addiction medicine more aordable
and thus more widely available.
Ultimately, drug policies that govern policing and
prescribing cannot solve this crisis on their own. Issues
as disparate as employment conditions, pharmaceuti-
340
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
cal misbranding regulations, healthcare finance, hous-
ing policy, and sustainable development programs
all aect patterns of drug use and supply. Cannabis
legalization and implementation of harm reduction
responses to the opioid epidemic reflect a growing
awareness that eradication of non-medical drug use
is a futile objective. Our contribution is to show that
suppression is not just fruitless but is actually harm-
ful. Although beset by crisis, the United States has
an historic opportunity to break from the policies of
criminalized suppression. No two drug crises are the
same, just as no two societies are interchangeable.
Nevertheless, other countries’ experiences demon-
strate that a public health approach to drug problems
is both more humane and more eective than crimi-
nalized suppression.
Note
The authors have no conflicts to declare.
Acknowledgements
Many thanks to Kate Stith, Abbe Gluck, and Haynie Wheeler for
making this article possible. The authors also benefitted greatly
from comments and suggestions by John Collins, Alejandro
Madrazo Lajous, Gregg Gonsalves, Nina Cohen, Kate Redburn,
Nathan Guevremont, Lisa Erickson, and Barbara Selvin. The
authors would also like to thank the participants of the work-
shop on opioid regulation at the Yale Center for the Study of
Globalization.
References
1. Global Commission on Drug Policy, Advancing Drug Policy
Reform: A New Approach to Decriminalization, 2016, avail-
able at <https://www.globalcommissionondrugs.org/reports>
(last visited April 25, 2018).
2. See, e.g., G. F. Koob and N. D. Volkow, “Neurocircuitry of
Addiction, Neuropsychopharmacology35, no. 1 (2010):
217–238.
3. J. Katz and A. Goodnough, “The Opioid Crisis Is Getting
Worse, Particularly for Black Americans,New York Times,
Dec. 22, 2017.
4. See K. James and A. Jordan, “The Opioid Crisis in Black
Communities, Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 46, no. 2
(2018): 404-421.
5. See Title II, §6, Volstead Act, Pub. L. 66-66 at 311 (exception
for sacramental wine) & Title II, §33 Pub. L. 66-66 at 317
(exception for possession and personal consumption of pre-
Prohibition liquor in one’s dwelling).
6. See Id., §7.
7. See L. McGirr, War on Alcohol (New York: W. W. Norton &
Co., 2015).
8. D. F. Musto, The American Disease, 3d ed. (Oxford: Oxford
U.P., 1999): 122–23.
9. 249 U.S. 96, 99 (1919).
10. Id.
11. See generally W. van den Brink and C. Haasen, “Evidence-
Based Treatment of Opioid-Dependent Patients”The Cana-
dian Journal of Psychiatry51, no. 10 (2006): 635-646.
12. K. L. Sees et al., “Methadone Maintenance vs. 180-Day Psy-
chosocially Enriched Detoxification for Treatment of Opioid
Dependence: A Randomized Controlled Trial, JAMA 283
(2000):1303–1310; See also D. Polsky et al., “Cost and Cost-
Eectiveness of Standard Methadone Maintenance Treat-
ment Compared to Enriched 180-Day Methadone Detoxifica-
tion,Addiction 99, no. 6 (2004): 718–726.
13. See A. Paraherakis et al., “An Abstinence-Oriented Program
for Substance Use Disorders: Poorer Outcome Associated
with Opiate Dependence,The Canadian Journal of Psychia-
try45, no. 10 (2000): 927-931.
14. van den Brink and Haasen, supra note 11, at 637.
15. A. J. Ritter, “Naltrexone in the Treatment of Heroin Depen-
dence: Relationship with Depression and Risk of Over-
dose,”Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry36,
no. 2 (2002): 224-228, at 227.
16. R. Dissell, “Ohio’s Spending on Opioid Addiction Treatment
Drugs Vivitrol and Suboxone Spikes, Spurs Debate on what
Treatments Work,Cleveland Plain Dealer, April 30, 2017.
17. R. P. Mattick et al., “Methadone Maintenance Therapy versus
No Opioid Replacement Therapy for Opioid Dependence,
Cochrane Database Systematic Reviews 3, no. 3 (2009): 10-11.
18. van den Brink and Haasen, supra note 14, at 637.
19. P. G. Barnett, “The Cost-Eectiveness of Methadone Main-
tenance as a Health Care Intervention,Addiction 94, no. 4
(1999): 479–488.
20. C. S. Davis and D. H. Carr, “The Law and Policy of Opioids
for Pain Management, Addiction Treatment, And Overdose
Reversal, Indiana Health Law Review 14 (2017): 1–39, at 17.
21. 42 C.F.R. §8.12.
22. 21 C.F.R. §1306.7.
23. 42 C.F.R. §8.12(f)(6).
24. 42 C.F.R. §8.12(f ).
25. 42 C.F.R. §8.11(f)(1).
26. 21 C.F.R. §1301.28.
27. See P. R. Keefe, The Family That Built an Empire of Pain,
New Yorker, Oct. 30, 2017.
28. 21 C.F.R. §1306.04.
29. See J. A. del Real, “Opioid Addiction Knows No Color, but its
Treatment Does,New York Times, January 12, 2018.
30. H. Hansen, C. Siegel, et al., “Buprenorphine and Methadone
Treatment for Opioid Dependence by Income, Ethnicity and
Race of Neighborhoods in New York City, Drug and Alcohol
Dependence164 (2016): 14-21.
31. S. C. Sigmon, “Access to Treatment for Opioid Dependence
in Rural America: Challenges and Future Directions, JAMA
Psychiatry71, no. 4 (2014): 359-360.
32. E. Peles et al., “Opiate-Dependent Patients on a Waiting List
for Methadone Maintenance Treatment are at High Risk for
Mortality until Treatment Entry,Journal of Addiction Medi-
cine7, no. 3 (2013): 177182.
33. See Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660, 666–67 (1962).
34. H. Matusow et al., “Medication Assisted Treatment in US
Drug Courts: Results from a Nationwide Survey of Availabil-
ity, Barriers and Attitudes,Journal of Substance Abuse Treat-
ment44, no. 5 (2013): 473–480.
35. C. Warbuton, “Economic Results of Prohibition,” (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1932): at 260; See also J. A. Miron
and J. Zwiebel, “Alcohol Consumption During Prohibition,
American Economic Review 81, no. 2 (1991): 242–247, at 242.
36. Miron and Zwiebel, supra note 35, at 242.
37. R. Cowan, “How the Narcs Created Crack, National Review,
December 5, 1986, at 26, 27.
38. S. Duke, “Drug Prohibition: An Unnatural Disaster,Con-
necticut Law Review 27 (1995): 571–612, n. 104 at 598.
39. Warburton, supra note 35, at 260 (comparing consumption
from 1927–1930 with that from 1911–1914).
40. L. Beletsky and C. S. Davis, “Today’s Fentanyl Crisis: Prohi-
bition’s Iron Law, Revisited,International Journal of Drug
Policy 46 (2017) 156–159, at 157.
41. Id.
42. Id.
43. S. L. Ziegler, “The Ocular Menace of Wood Alcohol Poison-
ing,British Journal of Ophthalmology 5, no. 8 (1921): 365–
373, at 368.
44. D. Blum, The Poisoner’s Handbook (New York: Penguin Press,
2010), at 154–156.
opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 341
Werle and Zedillo
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
45. Id. at 161–162.
46. Ziegler, supra note 43, at 365.
47. Blum, supra note 44, at 157–8.
48. McGirr, supra note 7, at 59.
49. Id.
50. J. Katz, “The First Count of Fentanyl Deaths in 2016: Up
540% in Three Years,New York Times, September 2, 2017.
51. H. Smith, “A Comprehensive Review of Rapid-Onset Opioids
for Breakthrough Pain,CNS Drugs26, no. 6 (2012): 509–535,
at 515.
52. N. Popper, Opioid Dealers Embrace the Dark Web to Send
Deadly Drugs by Mail, New York Times, June 10, 2017.
53. DEA Intelligence Brief, “Counterfeit Prescription Pills Con-
taining Fentanyls: A Global Threat,” DEA-DCT-DIB-021-16,
(July, 2016) at 4.
54. European Monitoring Centre for Drugs and Drug Addiction,
“Fentanyl Drug Profile,available at <http://www.emcdda.
europa.eu/publications/drug-profiles/fentanyl> (last visited
January 23, 2017).
55. See M. Keck and G. Correa-Cabrera, “US Drug Policy and
Supply-Side Strategies: Assessing Eectiveness and Results,
Norteamérica 10, no. 2 (2015): 47–67, 50–53 (describing his-
tory of U.S. interdiction eorts at the U.S.–Mexico border).
56. S. O’Connor, U.S.-China Economic and Security Review
Commission, “Fentanyl: China’s Deadly Export to the United
States,” February 1, 2017, available at <www.uscc.gov/sites/
default/files/Research/USCC%20Sta%20Report_Fentanyl-
China’s%20Deadly%20Export%20to%20the%20United%20
States020117.pdf> (last visited May 2, 2018)
57. See A. Ahmed, “Drug That Killed Prince is Making Mexican
Cartels Richer, U.S. Says,New York Times, June 9, 2016.
58. See T. Wainwright, “Narconomics,” (New York: Public Aairs,
2017): 13–27.
59. DEA, “United States: Areas of Influence of Major Mexi-
can Transnational Criminal Organizations,” DEA-DCT-
DIR-065-15, July 2015.
60. See H. A. Pollack and P. Reuter, “Does Tougher Enforcement
Make Drugs More Expensive?” Addiction 109, no. 12 (2014):
1959–1966.
61. See G. S. Becker and K. M. Murphy, “A Theory of Rational
Addiction, Journal of Political Economy 96, no. 4 (1988):
675–700.
62. Id., at 692-693.
63. See, e.g., G, Faruk, and W. Pesendorfer, “Harmful Addic-
tion,”Review of Economic Studies74, no. 1 (2007): 147–172.
64. See, e.g., B. D. Bernheim and A. Rangel, “Addiction and Cue-
Triggered Decision Processes,American Economic Review94,
no. 5 (2004): 1558–1590.
65. See, e.g., T. O’Donoghue and M. Rabin. “Self-Awareness and
Self-control,” in G. Lowenstein, D. Read, and R. F. Baumeister
eds. Time and Decision: Economic and Psychological Perspec-
tives on Intertemporal Choice, (New York: Russel Sage Foun-
dation, 2003): 217–244.
66. See I. A. Binswanger et al., “Release from Prison-A High Risk
of Death for Former Inmates,New England Journal of Medi-
cine 356, no. 2 (2007): 157–165.
67. “Government to Double Alcohol Poison Content and Also
Add Benzine,New York Times, December 29, 1926, at 1.
68. Blum, supra note 47, 158–159.
69. Institute of Medicine, Preventing HIV Infection Among
Injecting Drug Users in High-Risk Countries. An Assessment
of the Evidence (Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press,
2006).
70. R. Heimer, “Can Syringe Exchange Serve as a Conduit to Sub-
stance Abuse Treatment?”Journal of Substance Abuse Treat-
ment15, no. 3 (1998): 183–191.
71. J. T. Brooks, CDC Outbreak Investigations Involving OPANA®
ER 19, presentation at Joint Meeting of the Drug Safety and
Risk Management Advisory Committee and the Anesthetic
and Analgesic Drug Products Advisory Committee, March
13, 2017, available at <https://www.fda.gov/downloads/
AdvisoryCommittees/CommitteesMeetingMaterials/Drugs/
AnestheticAndAnalgesicDrugProductsAdvisoryCommittee/
UCM547237.pdf> (last visited Jan. 23, 2018).
72. S. A. Strathdee and C. Beyrer, “Threading the Needle—How
to Stop the HIV Outbreak in Rural Indiana, New England
Journal of Medicine373, no. 5 (2015): 397-399.
73. Ind. Code § 16-42-19-18 (2017).
74. Ind. Code §16-41-7.5-5 (2017).
75. Curtis Hill, Indiana Attorney General, Facebook, Oct. 19,
2017, available at <https://www.facebook.com/inattygen-
eral/photos/a.261125104318377.1073741828.2605959543712
92/384654158632137/?type=1&theater> (last visited May 2,
2018).
76. S. Burris et al., “Federalism, Policy Learning, and Local Inno-
vation in Public Health: The Case of the Supervised Injec-
tion Facility, St. Louis University Law Journal 53 (2008):
1089–1154.
77. U.S. Attorney’s Oce for the District of Vermont, Statement
of the U.S. Attorney’s Oce concerning Proposed Injection
Sites, December 13, 2017, available at <https://www.justice.
gov/usao-vt/pr/statement-us-attorney-s-office-concerning-
proposed-injection-sites> (last visited May 2, 2018).
78. A. R. Bazazi, et al., “Preventing Opiate Overdose Deaths:
Examining Objections to Take-Home Naloxone,”Journal of
Health Care for the Poor and Underserved21, no. 4 (2010):
1108–1113.
79. S. E. Lankenau et al., “Initiation into Prescription Opioid
Misuse Amongst Young Injection Drug Users,International
Journal of Drug Policy23, no. 1 (2012): 37–44.
80. See FDA, “General Principles for Evaluating the Abuse Deter-
rence of Generic Solid Oral Opioid Drug Products Guidance
for Industry,” November 2017, available at <https://www.fda.
gov/downloads/Drugs/GuidanceComplianceRegulatoryInfor-
mation/Guidances/UCM492172.pdf> (last visited Mary 2,
2018) (“applicant should evaluate its proposed generic drug
to show that it is no less abuse deterrent than the RLD with
respect to all of the potential routes of abuse.”)
81. See W. N. Evans, E. Lieber, and P. Power, “How the Refor-
mulation of OxyContin Ignited the Heroin Epidemic,Notre
Dame Department of Economics Working Papers, June 1,
2017, available at <https://www3.nd.edu/~elieber/research/
ELP.pdf> (last visited May 2, 2018).
82. See A. Alpert, D. Powell, and R. L. Pacula, “Supply-Side Drug
Policy in the Presence of Substitutes: Evidence from the
Introduction of Abuse-Deterrent Opioids,” National Bureau
of Economic Research, working paper No. 23031, (2017).
83. See e.g., S. Gottlieb, “FDA Takes Important Steps to Stem the
Tide of Opioid Misuse and Abuse,” FDA Voice by Commis-
sioner Scott Gottlieb, M.D., September 28, 2017, available
at <https://blogs.fda.gov/fdavoice/index.php/2017/09/fda-
takes-important-steps-to-stem-the-tide-of-opioid-misuse-
and-abuse> (last visited May 2, 2018).
84. National Alliance for Model State Drug Laws, Compilation of
Prescription Monitoring Program Maps, May 2016, available
at <http://www.namsdl.org/library/CAE654BF-BBEA-211E-
694C755E16C2DD21/> (last visited May 2, 2018) (hereinafter
NAMSDL), at 2.
85. Id., at 18.
86. Y. Bao et al., “Prescription Drug Monitoring Programs are
Associated with Sustained Reductions in Opioid Prescribing
by Physicians,Health Aairs 35, no. 6 (2016) 1045–1051, at
1048.
87. See T. C. Buchmueller and C. Carey, “The Eect of Prescrip-
tion Drug Monitoring Programs on Opioid Utilization in
Medicare,” National Bureau of Economic Research working
paper, No. w23148, (2017); NAMSDL, supra note 84.
88. CDC, Opioid Overdose: State Successes, available at <https://
www.cdc.gov/drugoverdose/policy/successes.html> (last vis-
ited Jan. 23, 2018).
89. J. Mallatt, “The Eect of Prescription Drug Monitoring Pro-
grams on Opioid Prescriptions and Heroin Crime Rates,
Purdue University Economics Department Working Paper No
1292, (2017), at 20–21.
342
journal of law, medicine & ethics
SYMPOSIUM
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)
90. Id.
91. G. Li et al., “Prescription Drug Monitoring and Drug Over-
dose Mortality,Injury Epidemiology1, no. 1 (2014) at 3.
92. S. W. Patrick et al., “Implementation of Prescription Drug
Monitoring Programs Associated with Reductions in Opi-
oid-Related Death Rates, Health Aairs 35, no. 7 (2016):
1324–1332.
93. M. A. Bachhuber et al., “Medical Cannabis Laws and Opioid
Analgesic Overdose Mortality in the United States, 1999-
2010, ”JAMA Internal Medicine174, no. 10 (2014) 1668–1673,
at 1671.
94. M. D. Livingston et al., “Recreational Cannabis Legalization
and Opioid-Related Deaths in Colorado, 2000–2015,Ameri-
can Journal of Public Health107, no. 11 (2017) 1827–1829, at
1829.
95. SAMHSA, Results From The 2016 National Survey On Drug
Use And Health: Detailed Tables, September 7, 2017, at Table
5.2A, available at <https://www.samhsa.gov/data/sites/
default/files/NSDUH-DetTabs-2016/NSDUH-DetTabs-2016.
pdf> (last visited May 3, 2018).
96. S. E. Collins et al., “Seattles Law Enforcement Assisted
Diversion (LEAD): Program Effects on Recidivism Out-
comes, Evaluation and Program Planning 64 (2017) 49-56,
at 53.
97. B. Andraka-Christou, “What Is Treatment for Opioid Addic-
tion in Problem-Solving Courts: A Study of 20 Indiana Drug
and Veterans Courts, Stanford Journal of Civil Rights and
Civil Liberties 13 (2017) 189–254, at 230.
98. European Monitoring Centre for Drugs and Drug Addiction,
Drug Consumption Rooms: An Overview of Provision and
Evidence (Lisbon: European Monitoring Centre for Drugs
and Drug Addiction, 2015).
99. See A. H. Kral and P. J. Davidson, “Addressing the Nations
Opioid Epidemic: Lessons from an Unsanctioned Supervised
Injection Site in the US,American Journal of Preventive
Medicine 53, no. 6 (2017): 919–922.
100. C. Potier et al., “Supervised Injection Services: What has been
Demonstrated? A Systematic Literature Review,Drug and
Alcohol Dependence 145 (2014): 48–68, at 63.
101. Id.
102. B. D. Marshall et al., “Reduction in Overdose Mortality after
the Opening of North America’s First Medically Supervised
Safer Injecting Facility: A Retrospective Population-Based
Study,Lancet 377, no. 9775 (2011) 1429–1437.
103. A. M. Salmon et al., “The Impact of a Supervised Injecting
Facility on Ambulance Call-Outs in Sydney, Australia,Addic-
tion 105, no. 4 (2010): 676–683.
104. Potier, supra note 100, at 62.
105. Canada (Attorney General) v. PHS Community Services Soci-
ety, [2011] S.C.C. 44 (Can.).
106. D. K. Padgett et al., Housing First: Ending Homelessness,
Transforming Systems, and Changing Lives (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2015): at 54.
107. D. K. Padgett et al., “Substance Use Outcomes Among Home-
less Clients with Serious Mental Illness: Comparing Housing
First with Treatment First Programs,Community Mental
Health Journal 47, no. 2 (2011) 227–232, at 230.
108. M. M. Islam et al., “Defining a Service for People who use
Drugs as ‘Low-Threshold’: What Should be the Crite-
ria?,International Journal of Drug Policy 24, no. 3 (2013):
220–222.
109. International Harm Reduction Development Program, Open
Society Institute, “Lowering the Threshold: Models of Acces-
sible Methadone and Buprenorphine Treatment,” (2010) at
11-12, available at <https://www.opensocietyfoundations.
org/sites/default/files/lowering-the-threshold-20100311.pdf>
(last visited May 3, 2018).
110. J. Emmanuelli and J. C. Desenclos, “Harm Reduction Inter-
ventions, Behaviours and Associated Health Outcomes in
France, 1996–2003,Addiction 100, no. 11 (2005): 1690–700,
at 1696–1699.
111. Hong Kong Legislative Council, “Methadone Treatment Pro-
grammes in Hong Kong and Selected Countries,” RP12/95-
96, March 1996, at 5–10, available at <http://www.legco.
gov.hk/yr97-98/english/sec/library/956rp12.pdf> (last visited
May 3, 2018).
112. Hong Kong Department of Health, “Methadone Clinics,” May
16, 2017, available at http://www.dh.gov.hk/english/main/
main_mc/main_mc.html, (last visited Jan. 23, 2018).
113. See H. N. Plomp et al., “The Amsterdam Methadone Dis-
pensing Circuit: Genesis and Eectiveness of a Public Health
Model for Local Drug Policy,Addiction 91, no. 5 (1996):
711721.
114. H. Waal et al., “Open Drug Scenes: Responses of Five Euro-
pean Cities,BMC Public Health14, no. 1 (2014): 853, at 7.
115. B. Fischer et al., “Heroin‐Assisted Treatment as a Response
to the Public Health Problem of Opiate Dependence, Euro-
pean Journal of Public Health 12, no. 3 (2012): 228–234, at
229.
116. See P. Blanken et al., “Heroin-Assisted Treatment in the Neth-
erlands: History, Findings, and International Context,Euro-
pean Neuropsychopharmacology 20, Supplement 2 (2010):
S105–S158.
117 P. Blanken et al., “Craving and Illicit Heroin use Among
Patients in Heroin-Assisted Treatment, Drug and Alcohol
Dependence120, no. 1 (2012): 74-80, at 7778.
118. E. Oviedo-Joekes et al., “Diacetylmorphine versus Methadone
for the Treatment of Opioid Addiction,New England Journal
of Medicine361, no. 8 (2009) 777786.
119. I. Demaret and E. Quertemont, “Loss of Treatment Ben-
efit when Heroin-Assisted Treatment is Stopped after 12
Months, Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 69 (2016):
72–75.
120. See C. Nordt and R. Stohler, “Low-Threshold Methadone
Treatment, Heroin Price, Police Activity and Incidence of
Heroin Use: The Zurich Experience, International Journal
of Drug Policy20, no. 6 (2009): 497–501.
121. F. Zobel et al., Le Marché des Stupéfiants dans le Canton de
Vaud. Partie 1 : Les Opioids (Lausanne: Addiction Suisse,
2017) at 38–60, 70-90.
122. T. J. Cicero et al., “Increased use of Heroin as an Initiat-
ing Opioid of Abuse, Addictive Behaviors (2017): 63–66, at
64–65.
123. See, e.g., R. VerBruggen, “What the Opioid Crisis Can Teach
Us about the War on Drugs,Law and Liberty, November
1, 2017, available at <http://www.libertylawsite.org/liberty-
forum/what-the-opioid-crisis-can-teach-us-about-the-war-
on-drugs> (last visited May 3, 2018).
124. See J. Whalen and L. Cooper, “Private-Equity Pours Cash into
Opioid-Treatment Sector,Wall Street Journal, September 2,
2017.
125. See D. Segal, “City of Addict Entrepreneurs,New York Times,
January 3, 2018; A. J. Harris and S. Walter, “They Thought
They were Going to Rehab. They Ended up in Chicken
Plants,Reveal News, (October 4, 2017).
126. See R. Duncan, Pubs and Patriots: The Drink Crisis in Brit-
ain during World War One (Liverpool, UK: Liverpool Univer-
sity Press, 2013): 121–149.